The approach of Aristotle of formulating different arguments and comparing them is more like what we are used to. — Valentinus
According to a conventional view, Plato’s philosophy is abstract and utopian, whereas Aristotle’s is empirical, practical, and commonsensical — Britannica: How Plato and Aristotle differ
The Theory of Forms stands or falls on its own merits or demerits - probably falls - but from a point of view of biography, psychology (see another thread about that) I *speculate* that this is a person who has lost a great friend to political violence and ignorance and is saying "We can't just make up justice, truth, right and wrong, is and is-not; we need to apply some wisdom and thought." — Cuthbert
It is directly related to the text. Perhaps not what you had in mind but one meaning of from the gut is something known without being taught, inborn knowledge or recollection. — Fooloso4
In such a world, what are the values and truths that we can trust? — Cuthbert
Are you suggesting that [the gut] is where our values and truths come from ? — Amity
I was referring to Plato. He is unique in gathering a record of dialogues with different "schools" of thought as actual discussions — Valentinus
Yes, I was thinking about Protagoras, for example. I was also thinking about the Athenian culture that Plato was unhappy about: the society that put Socrates to death — Cuthbert
But I think it's worth thinking about what questions of his time Plato was answering when he wrote the dialogues. For example: in politics, democracy vs tyranny or aristocracy; in metaphysics, how can things both be and not be at the same time (Parmenides, Zeno); in art, irrational violence vs sublime contemplation (Euripides, the Parthenon) — Cuthbert
I'm saying this in the hope of pointing out the emotional force of Plato's writing which can seem abstract, obscure, dry, outmoded and false out of context. — Cuthbert
Plato's criticism of Protagoras must be carefully read in context in order to see what he is and is not rejecting.
The Forms are presented as if they are transcendent truths, but they are hypotheses. — Fooloso4
Yes, I was thinking about Protagoras, for example. I was also thinking about the Athenian culture that Plato was unhappy about: the society that put Socrates to death — Cuthbert
In such a world, what are the values and truths that we can trust? — Cuthbert
The Theory of Forms was not (merely) abstract speculation: it came from the gut. — Cuthbert
Plato's criticism of Protagoras must be carefully read in context in order to see what he is and is not rejecting.
The Forms are presented as if they are transcendent truths, but they are hypotheses. — Fooloso4
Man is the measure does not mean that what any man says is thereby true, but it is, after all, man who measures the arguments made by man. A transcendent standard by which to measure is not available to us. — Fooloso4
"Concepts such as 'Beauty' don't exist by themselves, do they ?
They arise from the real world - we create such - why ? "
This is a viewpoint that Plato is dedicated to challenge. Man is not the measure of all things — Cuthbert
Protagoras is known primarily for three claims (1) that man is the measure of all things (which is often interpreted as a sort of radical relativism) (2) that he could make the “worse (or weaker) argument appear the better (or stronger)” and (3) that one could not tell if the gods existed or not...
Historically, it was in response to Protagoras and his fellow sophists that Plato began the search for transcendent forms or knowledge which could somehow anchor moral judgment. Along with the other Older Sophists and Socrates, Protagoras was part of a shift in philosophical focus from the earlier Presocratic tradition of natural philosophy to an interest in human philosophy...
Plato (427-347 B.C.E.): Protagoras is a leading character in Plato’s dialogue Protagoras and Protagoras’ doctrines are discussed extensively in Plato’s Theaetetus. Plato’s dialogues, however, are a mixture of historical account and artistic license, much in the manner of the comic plays of the period...
Of Protagoras’ ipsissima verba (actual words, as opposed to paraphrases), the most famous is the homo-mensura (man-measure) statement (DK80b1): “Of all things the measure is man, of the things that are, that [or “how”] they are, and of things that are not, that [or “how”] they are not.” This precise meaning of this statement, like that of any short extract taken out of context, is far from obvious, although the long discussion of it in Plato’s Theaetetus gives us some sense of how ancient Greek audiences interpreted it. — IEP article: Protagorus
I think that Plato should have been made a saint a very long time ago for what he did for the Church. — magritte
Yes. Dwelling too much in the past, especially after loss and dealing with grief.Significant unhappiness and unwelcome emotion in people is also produced by rumination and 'festering'. — Tom Storm
This type of work must be so challenging and fulfilling when you see positive results.CBT certainly works to help people develop tools and strategies for managing their emotional regulation - a not inconsiderable concern for people dealing with trauma and addiction, an area I have worked in for 30 plus years. — Tom Storm
So I take it that Plato's literary tricks in the Phaedo and elsewhere, as dutifully imitated — magritte
the authors of the gospels were intended to make all the tales as a cumulative package more life-like, — magritte
The contradictions and discrepancies between the first three and John make it impossible to accept both traditions as equally reliable.[17] Modern scholars are cautious of relying on the gospels uncritically, but nevertheless they do provide a good idea of the public career of Jesus, and critical study can attempt to distinguish the original ideas of Jesus from those of the later authors.[18][19] — Wiki: Gospel
more convincing to naive un-philosophical people who listen to such stories? — magritte
Stopped right in my tracks at this:
I think the important thing is not the labels so much as being self aware, without going overboard. Being able to self-regulate is an important skill for most people and can really help in achieving goals (although I know that language doesn't work for everyone). The stoics influenced Albert Ellis who created RET, which morphed into CBT and DBT. It's great stuff. — Tom Storm
So, what matters most is the fact that we can identify emotions and them reflexively promote some kind of 'care' or interest in what's worthwhile to promote for the benefit of those who suffer. At the very least some kind of concern is necessary, in any regards. — Shawn
It is a difficult matter to explore because who else did/does this sort of thing?
— Valentinus
I skipped over this earlier - not paying attention to the second part.
What did you mean by 'this sort of thing' ?
Stories within a story showing different perspectives ? With the motives of the author(s) in question ? — Amity
'Kind' is another English term for 'Form'. — Fooloso4
And the earth bringeth forth tender grass, herb sowing seed after its kind, and tree making fruit after its kind;
And God prepareth the great monsters, and every living creature that is creeping, which the waters have teemed with, after their kind, and every fowl with wing, after its kind
`Let the earth bring forth the living creature after its kind, cattle and creeping thing, and beast of the earth after its kind:'
And God maketh the beast of the earth after its kind, and the cattle after their kind, and every creeping thing of the ground after its kind (Genesis 1)
This structure is also found in classic religious and philosophical texts. The structure of The Symposium and Phaedo, attributed to Plato, is of a story within a story within a story. In the Christian Bible, the gospels are retellings of stories from the life and ministry of Jesus. However, they also include within them the stories (parables) that Jesus told.
In more modern philosophical work, Jostein Gaarder's books often feature this device. Examples are The Solitaire Mystery, where the protagonist receives a small book from a baker, in which the baker tells the story of a sailor who tells the story of another sailor, and Sophie's World about a girl who is actually a character in a book that is being read by Hilde, a girl in another dimension. Later on in the book Sophie questions this idea, and realizes that Hilde too could be a character in a story that in turn is being read by another. — Wiki: Story within a story
Socrates says that Mind arranges or orders things. (97c) Is this 'Mind' a particular mind? — Fooloso4
2. How are you defining both 'soul' and 'Soul' ?
— Amity
Soul is that which brings life. Here again the distinction is blurred as it was with Snow and snow. — Fooloso4
After saying he assumes the Form he goes on to say:
If you grant me these and agree that they exist ...
The acceptance of the assumption does not come as the result of reasoned argument, it is used as a condition for it. — Fooloso4
Well, given that I can't accept his alleged assumption...I think accepting such matters is by faith... not by reasoned argument. — Amity
Good question. He begins the story of his second sailing by saying how confused he was by looking at things themselves. His hypotheses are his way of bringing order to things. A second sailing means when the wind dies down and you must oar the boat, move it forward under your own power. — Fooloso4
The two uses of 'kind' in English are related. Kind means both the kind of thing something is, that is, its nature or species and something whose nature or disposition is what we describe as kind. — Fooloso4
Really ? How so ?'Kind' is another English term for 'Form'. — Fooloso4
."Also in English as a suffix (mankind, etc., also compare godcund "divine"). Other earlier, now obsolete, senses included "character, quality derived from birth" and "manner or way natural or proper to anyone — Etymology dictionary
Soul with with a capital indicates the Form rather than a particular soul. — Fooloso4
Emphasis addedI think it is Socrates mind ordering things according to kind. It is the kind of thing Mind does. — Fooloso4
Emphasis added.Socrates' soul is of the Kind Soul, but his soul is not the Kind or Form Soul — Fooloso4
It is a difficult matter to explore because who else did/does this sort of thing? — Valentinus
It is a difficult matter to explore because who else did/does this sort of thing?
The unique quality is exposing oneself to argument, no matter the consequence. — Valentinus
The relationship between "universals and particulars" is mixed up
— Valentinus
I simply, naively and perhaps foolishly cling to this, that nothing else makes it beautiful other than the presence of, or the sharing in, or however you may describe its relationship to that Beautiful we mentioned, for I will not insist on the precise nature of the relationship, but that all beautiful things are beautiful by the Beautiful. .” (100c-e) — Fooloso4
Socrates' soul is of the Kind Soul, but his soul is not the Kind or Form Soul — Fooloso4
I think one of the more common issues is new members seemingly posting the first thing that comes to their mind, and not really taking the time to get a feel for the forum, etc — Pinprick
I am thinking of following up with something more diagrammatic, an overview. — Fooloso4
I hope this encourages any other beginner trying to read or follow/participate in the discussion.
I do not know if anyone read it but chose to remain silent. I hope so.
— Fooloso4
I am sure that, given the view count (1.3K) there could well be a few... — Amity
1. Background
a. The Phaedo tells the story of Socrates’ final days. Taking place after the events
depicted in the Euthyphro, Apology, and Crito, this dialogue serves as his swansong.
b. Whereas the Apology had a fairly straightforward structure, consisting mainly of
Socrates’ monologues to the citizens of Athens (with a bit of back-and-forth with
Meletus thrown in), the Phaedo is a full-blown dialogue. In fact, it operates as a
dialogue on multiple levels. First we have the framing dialogue, which consists of the
eponymous main character Phaedo’s account of Socrates’ final words, which he gives
to Echecrates and others on his way home from Athens. Then we have the dialogue
recounted by Phaedo, which takes place between Socrates and those who were with
him in his final hours.
c. First, let’s take a closer look at the framing dialogue. Phaedo (the character) is on his
way back from Athens after attending the trial and execution of Socrates. As he
approaches his hometown of Elis in the Peloponnese, he runs into a group of
Pythagoreans, the most vocal of which is Echecrates. These men are dubbed
‘Pythagoreans’ because they follow the teachings of Pythagoras. While most of us are
familiar with his theorem, Pythagoras had much more to say on the topics of
philosophy and mathematics. For our purposes here, we should only note these
Pythagoreans would’ve been especially open to the mathematical examples Phaedo
tells them Socrates made use of in his final conversation—e.g., the difference
between odd and even numbers, etc.
d. We shouldn’t glide past this framing dialogue too swiftly, although it can be easy to
forget it’s there. The fact that Phaedo runs into Pythagoreans is itself potentially
meaningful. It could, among other things, suggest that the version of Socrates’ ideas
he’s sharing with them has already been re-shaped to suit their interests...
— Sean Hannan: Notes on Plato's Phaedo
It was an enjoyable challenge trying to make sense of the dialogue and putting all the pieces together. No doubt, there are pieces I left out. Perhaps only those who have a fondness for Plato would find my commentary of interest, but in my opinions the details matter — Fooloso4
I trust the thread was worth your while, perhaps in terms of ordering your understanding, perhaps in terms of addressing the various comments here. — Banno
I look forward to a dialogue about this dialogue. — Fooloso4
This thread has taught me to pay more attention to the detail - particularly the objections from the various interlocutors, and the subtlety of some of the distinctions made in the arguments. Also one thing I do commend is your emphasis on interpreting the texts on their own terms and being aware of hidden interpretive agendas. — Wayfarer
there's another couple of passages in the Phaedro that I would like to revisit, (although I'm finding it difficult to concentrate on it, as I have many other balls in the air right at the moment.) But I will certainly be appending some more questions and comments on the text. — Wayfarer
I am sure that, given the view count (1.3K) there could well be a few...I do not know if anyone read it but chose to remain silent. I hope so. — Fooloso4
Outline of the Dialogue
The Philosopher and Death (59c-69e)
Three Arguments for the Soul’s Immortality (69e-84b)
The Cyclical Argument (70c-72e)
The Argument from Recollection (72e-78b)
The Affinity Argument (78b-84b)
Objections from Simmias and Cebes, and Socrates’ Response (84c-107b)
The Objections (85c-88c)
Interlude on Misology (89b-91c)
Response to Simmias (91e-95a)
Response to Cebes (95a-107b)
Socrates’ Intellectual History (96a-102a)
The Final Argument (102b-107b)
The Myth about the Afterlife (107c-115a)
Socrates’ Death (115a-118a) — IEP article Plato: Phaedo
Simply Red played three very special shows at Amsterdam’s Ziggo Dome accompanied by a 40-piece orchestra. The set list beautifully showcased their remarkable career including the classic hits ‘Holding Back The Years’, ‘Stars’, ‘Fairground’ and ‘If You Don’t Know Me By Now’.
A Symposium on Popular Songs is an animated Disney short that originally released to theaters by Buena Vista Distribution on December 19, 1962. It features Ludwig Von Drake lecturing on the state of popular music punctuated by a number of stop-motion musical numbers.
The songs were written by Richard and Robert Sherman, with each song represented a different era in musical history. The brothers considered this one of their favorite Disney assignments.
"The Rutabaga Rag"
"Charleston Charlie"
"Although I Dropped $100,000 (I Found a Million Dollars in your Smile)"
"I'm Blue for You (Boo-Boo-Boo-Boo-Boo)"
"The Boogie Woogie Bakery Man"
"Puppy Love is Here to Stay"
"Rock, Rumble, and Roar"
A Symposium on Popular Songs is a special cartoon featurette made by Walt Disney Productions in 1962. It features songs that were written by the Sherman Brothers, with music arrangements by Tutti Camarata.
Ludwig Von Drake lectures on the state of popular music punctuated by a number of stop-motion musical numbers.
this thread is an earnest attempt to engage with the text of Plato's Phaedo, if you are unable or unwilling to do so, take it elsewhere. I invite people to flag posts in this thread that they believe are not strictly on topic and I (or someone else) will moderate them accordingly. — fdrake
Between this and Rowe's criticism it is clear how far apart those who look at the dialogue as a whole with attention to parts are from those who say:
Have you thought of just drawing out the significant ideas instead of providing your interpretation?
— frank — Fooloso4
I thought as much.my approach would be "Straussian": — Fooloso4
Influential figures are Jacob Klein and Leo Strauss, and his students including Alan Bloom, Stanley Rosen...
— Fooloso4
These are the people I read and whom I have learned the most from. — Fooloso4
One of the central features of such an approach is its deployment of the concept of (Socratic) irony. It appears that one can never take anything anyone says in a dialogue at face value; to see what we are to make of any statement or proposal, an interpreter has to stand back and ask how it relates to everything else that is said or done in that particular dialogue.
That looks fine, up to a point, and especially as a corrective to overliteral interpretations of the texts that refuse to take notice of context, dramatic or otherwise. The trouble is that this way of proceeding lends itself too easily to abuse. Thus what began in Strauss himself as an interesting method with the potential for plausible readings, not least of the Republic, has hardened, in the hands of some of his epigoni, into the treatment of Plato as an advocate for a conservative politics: — Christopher Rowe
...An overarching question of the dialogue is about teaching and learning. Socrates teaches him how to solve the problem and yet claims it was recollection. This is not the place to get into it, but the difference between Meno’s problem, teaching virtue to someone like Meno who is lacking in virtue and teaching someone geometry is very different — Fooloso4
And you yourselves must search too, along with one another; you may not easily find anyone more capable of doing this than yourselves.'
'That shall certainly be done,' said Cebes; '
I appreciate that even with his level of expertise, it is not only a challenge to decipher the dialogue but to present and discuss any understanding....with the dialogues we need to look not only at what is said but at what is done. — Fooloso4
A second problem with both the Neoplatonist and the analytical approach is that their choice of contexts and issues, and indeed of dialogues, to privilege over others is too obviously dictated by their own preoccupations...
Neoplatonizing accounts catch something of the larger picture in which this critique is framed while either missing the critique itself altogether or representing it one-sidedly in terms of oppositions between soul and body, human and divine, descent and ascent.
Such oppositions clearly are Platonic, but they are at one end of a spectrum that also includes, and more frequently, a carefully reasoned, hand-to-hand engagement with people and their ideas: an engagement that presents alternatives that look to this life as much as to anything beyond it.
For their part, analytical interpreters may end up failing even more spectacularly to capture the passionate tone of the Platonic dialogues, by reducing them—at least by implication—to a locus for quasi-academic 26 argument and counterargument. — Christopher Rowe
The last section has implicitly proposed a compromise on another of the dividing lines between interpreters of Plato.
On the one hand there are those who think he believes in another world, over and above this world of ours, inhabited as it were by the ideal forms and by gods and other purified souls, to which it is our business to make our own way, even in this life, by (as Socrates puts it in the Phaedo) “practising for death.” Such a reading 27 accompanies a literal interpretation of the eschatological myths, which are there, on this view, to terrify us into changing our ways if we cannot be persuaded by argument.
But there is also another view of Plato’s position, namely that the talk of another world is at bottom metaphorical and that the myths in question are chiefly allegories of this life. What is clear is that there are grounds, in Plato’s texts, for both readings; the problem for the interpreter is to know how to make room for both. — Christopher Rowe
Such an open-ended type of interpretation has its representatives among two radically different groups: among philosophical interpreters, for whom it makes Plato a philosopher much like them—more interested in, or expecting more from, arguments than in or from conclusions;
and among literary interpreters, who insist on the literary and dramatic form of Plato’s works and argue that we can no more read off his intentions from what he puts in the mouths of his characters than we can infer what an Aeschylus thought from what he has his Clytemnestra or Cassandra say.
But one problem faced by both of these approaches, as by the skeptics of the New Academy, is that of explaining why, if they are right, certain ideas keep recurring in the corpus...
...Platonic metaphysics, that backbone of historical Platonism, also looks comfortably at home in an ethical context, insofar as it places a reconfigured goodness, beauty, and justice within the very structure of things—however it may be that Plato thought that trick could be pulled. Indeed, without that context (and without its inventive elaboration and re-elaboration by successions of Platonists and idealists), it can look as unmotivated as it appeared to an unsympathetic Aristotle.
— Christopher Rowe
It is something that I have been attempting to show — Fooloso4
It is significant that those who have opposed my interpretation have not said anything about the details of what Socrates says in the dialogue about myths. Instead they point elsewhere. — Fooloso4
Platonism is the view that there exist such things as abstract objects — where an abstract object is an object that does not exist in space or time and which is therefore entirely non-physical and non-mental. Platonism in this sense is a contemporary view.
It is obviously related to the views of Plato in important ways, but it is not entirely clear that Plato endorsed this view, as it is defined here.
In order to remain neutral on this question, the term ‘platonism’ is spelled with a lower-case ‘p’. (See entry on Plato.)
The most important figure in the development of modern platonism is Gottlob Frege (1884, 1892, 1893–1903, 1919). The view has also been endorsed by many others, including Kurt Gödel (1964), Bertrand Russell (1912), and W.V.O. Quine (1948, 1951). — SEP article on Platonism
Plato criticized both the epic poetry of Homer and Hesiod, and the tragic and comic poets. Yet he invented myths of his own. So what was his attitude towards literature and myth? Peter tackles this question in a final episode on Plato.
Plato was not willing to go as far as Socrates did. He preferred to address the public at large through his written dialogues rather than conducting dialogues in the agora.
He did not write abstruse philosophical treatises but engaging philosophical dialogues meant to appeal to a less philosophically inclined audience. The dialogues are, most of the time, prefaced by a sort of mise en scène in which the reader learns who the participants to the dialogue are, when, where and how they presently met, and what made them start their dialogue.
The participants are historical and fictional characters. Whether historical or fictional, they meet in historical or plausible settings, and the prefatory mises en scène contain only some incidental anachronisms.
Plato wanted his dialogues to look like genuine, spontaneous dialogues accurately preserved. How much of these stories and dialogues is fictional? It is hard to tell, but he surely invented a great deal of them. References to traditional myths and mythical characters occur throughout the dialogues.
However, starting with the Protagoras and Gorgias, which are usually regarded as the last of his early writings, Plato begins to season his dialogues with self-contained, fantastical narratives that we usually label his ‘myths’. His myths are meant, among other things, to make philosophy more accessible. — SEP article: Plato's Myths
For Plato we should live according to what reason is able to deduce from what we regard as reliable evidence. This is what real philosophers, like Socrates, do. But the non-philosophers are reluctant to ground their lives on logic and arguments. They have to be persuaded. One means of persuasion is myth. Myth inculcates beliefs. It is efficient in making the less philosophically inclined, as well as children (cf. Republic 377a ff.), believe noble things....
Myth can embody in its narrative an abstract philosophical doctrine. In the Phaedo, Plato develops the so-called theory of recollection (72e–78b). The theory is there expounded in rather abstract terms. The eschatological myth of the Phaedo depicts the fate of souls in the other world, but it does not “dramatize” the theory of recollection. — As above