Another reason she's interesting is because very few philosophers in recent times have tried their hand at a complete, systematic "big picture" philosophy with many levels, from synoptic overview to ethical, even aesthetic advice for everyday life. One might say that's because it's been demonstrated to be a fruitless or hubristic endeavour, but really it hasn't; the twee tone of faux humility that's characterized much of academic philosophy in the 20th century, especially in the analytic tradition, has really just been more of a fashion statement and "house style." — gurugeorge
Well, if the world is a formal system of sorts, then what's wrong with trying to find a link between the two? — Posty McPostface
If different infinities have different values then is it really a definite quantity? — 3rdClassCitizen
Amount of real numbers = infinite
Amount of even real numbers = infinite
Does this mean that infinity divided by 2 equals itself?
The law of identity (A=A) is a logical necessity.
Imagine A is not A. We would then have the logical contradiction A & ~A, violating the law of non-contradiction.
My point the idea of sex you are using claims bodies are more than bodies. If I take a body, let's say one with XX chromosomes, a womb, breasts, a vagina, etc., your position proclaims it must belong to the sex category/sex identity of "female." It is subsuming our linguistical/conceptual/social practice of "female sex" into the body itself. You say such a body must be "female" when such a categorisation is not actually given in the existence of body.
Bodies are what they are no matter the category they are sorted. They are defined independently of any sex or gender categorisation.
[...]
It doesn't recognise sex isn't the body at all.
I didn't want to become part of their performance of what they imagined themselves to be. Other people can do that if they want.
58 gender options (below) from which to choose. Most of these look kind of redundant to me, but I am sure there are partisans ready to defend to their death the critical difference between being a cis male and a cis man, between gender fluid and gender juice. — Bitter Crank
By which standard would we be measuring our internal ethical rules and external judgments that allow us to change our internal moral compass or decide not to?
The thing is my point still apply here if I'm wearing Jordans, it doesn't mean I'm telling people I am male! It's just a fashion preference. — Terran Imperium
A woman can behave with a manly attitude, that's what people call a tomboy. Do you know the difference between a tomboy and a transgender man?
Not only trans-gender people but those that thinks there is more than two genders. A non-binary gender? Really? — Terran Imperium
This gender ideology contradicts basic biology.
Human sexuality is an objective biological binary trait: 'XY' and 'XX' are genetic markers of health, not genetic markers of a disorder. — Terran Imperium
"What defines correct thinking?" I defined the term, saying "forms of thought that are salve veritate, not accidentally, but essentially. "Rules." were not mentionde. — Dfpolis
First, if you "create" a system without foundational reflection, there is no reason to think its principles of inference will besalve veritate.
That is a good reason to begin with an examination of correct thought, as Aristotle did. It is no reason to "create" rules of inference that lack an adequate foundation in human thought or in the reality it seeks to reflect.
Your syllogism has an undistributed middle, and the conclusion, while true, is invalid.
You mean there was no Principle of Pseudo-Scotus before Frege?
Really? If that’s what you think, you have completely misunderstood the text. Let's look at it:
When you observe a particle of a certain type, say an electron, now and here, this is to be regarded in principle as an isolated event. Even if you observe a similar particle a very short time at a spot very near to the first, and even if you have every reason to assume a causal connection between the first and the second observation, there is no true, unambiguous meaning in the assertion that it is the same particle you have observed in the two cases. (Schrodinger)
Note that the "identity" being discussed here is not that expressed by the Principle of Identity (“Whatever is, is”) -- which is unitary -- but a binary identity linking two cases. Using one as a counterexample to the other is equivocation.
It does no such thing. "Whatever is" assumes no specific structure to reality. It applies to whatever is actually the case.
No, I did not say the "rule" is different. The "rule" is exactly the same. What is different is that future contingents do not exist, and so fail to meet the conditions of application for the rule -- which applies to all existential situations. This goes to the heart of what I am saying, and what you fail to see -- namely, unless you understand the foundational role of the principles of being, you cannot understand when the conditions of application for logic are met, and when they are not.
I do not reject all use of truth values. I simply see that they are not well founded for every well-formed formula. In other words that truth is a prelational, not an intrinsic property.
Note that "Everything Jones says about Watergate is true." is not a statement about the reality of Watergate, but one about Jones' statements. Similarly, "Most of Nixon's assertions about Watergate are false," is not a statement about Watergate, but about Nixon's locutions. Thus, it cannot be counted among "Nixon's assertions about Watergate."
I am not claiming to have an exhaustive knowledge of being. My understanding only needs to be adequate to justify the principles of being that underpin traditional logic.
No, one we can say conditionally true things about. The condition is what Aristotle called "the willing suspension of disbelief." If you impose this condition on a premise, then it remains imposed on any dependent conclusion. So, if you want to say "In an imagined world with Pegasi, some horses have wings," I would have no objection. But, that conclusion does not make your case.
There is nothing in traditional logic that prevents anyone from stating a set of axioms and working out their implications. Knowing traditional logic only means that they will be able to bring greater insight to the task.
So, you you think its "useful" to be able to prove that some living horses have wings? And believe that "salve veritate" thinking is not "worthwhile"? I am trying to be charitable here, but it's not easy.
Perhaps you have in mind some theorem or empirical finding that cannot be arrived at using traditonal logic? I surely know none.
Or lets take a "problem" from the quantification article for Wikipedia:
I have already said. Let me be more precise: forms of thought that are salve veritate, not accidentally, but essentially. — Dfpolis
Not quite. It is observing that if you're reasoning, and want the truth of your premises to guarantee the truth of your conclusion, your reasoning needs to reflect the principles of being. Adhering to certain forms is one way of doing this.
Let us also agree that mere fact that two areas (correct thought vs the transformation of symbolic forms) differ is not a reason for the study of one to be more in vogue than that of another.
From a contradiction, anything does, in fact, follow. And yes, we are told conflicting things. ( I would not call both conflicting statements "information" because they cannot both reduce what is logically possible.) Does the mere existence of conflicting claims warrant treating contradictory statements as equally true? Hardly.
So, to form our concepts of <being> and <existence>, all we need to do is remove any notes of intelligibility that specify the particularity of the being we are encountering.
Let's be clear. The syllogism only reflects a valid thought process in words. Aristotelian logic is not about verbal forms. It is about the ways of thinking expressed in those forms.
That is precisely the point. Your example has nothing to do with the Principle of Identity we are discussing. To continue to pretend that it does, after I have shown you its utter irrelevance is arguing in bad faith.
My response was that granting the facts you put into evidence does nothing to show that "Whatever is, is" is false. Please do not distort my position. If it is the case that electrons are not indiviualizable, then it is the case that electrons are not indiviualizable. (BTW, I have no reason to doubt this.)
Nor is it useful to pretend that the Principle of Identity is something else. I am not following you down a Trumpian rabbit hole, so I am skipping the rest of your comments on identity.
This is the case with regard to that which is not always existent or not always nonexistent. One of the two propositions in such instances must be true and the other false, but we cannot say determinately that this or that is false, but must leave the alternative undecided. One may indeed be more likely to be true than the other, but it cannot be either actually true or actually false. It is therefore plain that it is not necessary that of an affirmation and a denial one should be true and the other false. For in the case of that which exists potentially, but not actually, the rule which applies to that which exists actually does not hold good.
— Aristotle, De Interpretatione, 9
The reason Aristotle give is exactly that I gave, i.e. that because the case is not actual (does not exist) neither proposition can "be either actually true or actually false."
You can redefine "exists" if you wish, but doing so will not change what I mean by the term.
I do not base the math I use on symbolic logic, as no mathematical system reducible to arithmetic can be shown to be self-consistent. I justify my mathematics by abstracting its foundations from reality -- thus guarantying its self-consistency.
Still, I wonder why you are not commenting on my simple resolution of the "insoluble" paradoxes, or jumping in with an actual defense against my charge that "truth value" is an incoherent concept. "Cute" is not a counterargument.
So, you want me to seriously consider that I may never have encountered existence? I'm not following you down that rabbit hole either.
Still, unless we are discussing ideas or concepts, they do not just point to ideas or concepts. The definition of "Pegasus" is not the definition of an idea, but of a mythical beast.
I did not say the sentence of the Liar paradox had existential import. I said that that the concepts of <truth> and <falsity> did not apply to the sentence because it made no reference to reality.
Stepping back, you're so dogmatic in your commitments that you will not even discuss the merits of my solution.
You were trying to show the outright stupidity of Aristotelian logic, but you could only do so by violating its canons, specifically by ignoring the requirement that Universal affirmative propositions have existential import.
Again, you are closed to my fundamental point. Traditional logic is not about sentential or any other form of symbolic manipulation, It is about correct thinking
Thank you for your faith claim.
There is no problem with my definition. I am not denying that "logic" can have many meanings. I'm specifying the meaning I'm using. — Dfpolis
Mostly, they study systems of symbolic representation and manipulation. So, while they may be correct ways of thinking about various formal systems, they do not study the structure of correct thought, as does classical logic. — Dfpolis
Second, I am not "assuming the Principle of Excluded Middle." I am finding that, when I reflect on the understanding of existence I have abstracted from my experience of reality, I see that some conjectured state must either be or not be. This is not an "assumption," but a finding.
I note that you did not comment on the syllogism I offered in evidence. Is your claim, then, that to apply a principle to a concrete case we do not need to recognize that the concrete case meets the conditions of application? Or perhaps that we can validly apply principles that are not thought of as universal? Or perhaps you want to claim that if the conditions of application can be stated in words that can describe, in another sense, the case at hand, we can still rationally apply the principle to that case?
You see not to understand the Principle of Identity. it does not make contingent claims about reality, saying, for example that electrons are individually identifiable or even that they are individuals. What is says is: "Whatever is, is." So if it is the case that electrons are not individuated, then that is the case.
Now, do you have an actual example of a violation of the Principle of Identity?
"When you observe a particle of a certain type, say an electron, now and here, this is to be regarded in principle as an isolated event. Even if you observe a similar particle a very short time at a spot very near to the first, and even if you have every reason to assume a causal connection between the first and the second observation, there is no true, unambiguous meaning in the assertion that it is the same particle you have observed in the two cases. The circumstances may be such that they render it highly convenient and desirable to express oneself so, but it is only an abbreviation of speech; for there are other cases where the 'sameness' becomes entirely meaningless; and there is no sharp boundary, no clear-cut distinction between them, there is a gradual transition over intermediate cases. And I beg to emphasize this and I beg you to believe it: It is not a question of being able to ascertain the identity in some instances and not being able to do so in others. It is beyond doubt that the question of 'sameness', of identity, really and truly has no meaning."
I am sorry, but this does not contradict my position, but a confirms it. The reason the linguistic expression of the Principle of Excluded Middle does not apply to future contingents is that they do not exist. Since they have no being, there is no justification for applying a principle founded in our understanding of existence.
Again, my position offers a simple solution to the Liar paradox, Jourdain's paradox and other conundrums based on the notion of "truth value." It simply shows that "truth value" is an ill-defined construct.
I am sorry to see you committed to so many errors.
That does not mean that those principles cannot be justified. it only means that they they cannot be deduced. They can, for example, be justified by an appeal to experience. My claim, which you refuse to address, is that the principles of being are abstracted, a posteriori, from our understanding of existence.
Note that while my claim addresses what can be known from our experience of reality, your reply fails to address what we can know from experience. it is, therefore, nonresponsive.
Of course we can't define things into existence. Rather, definitions point to the aspects of reality we're discussing.
What you refuse to grasp is that classical logic is not concerned with linguistic forms, but with correct patterns of thought. Aristotle spent a great deal of time pointing out fallacies -- many of which (such as the equivocation in your example) use apparently correct linguistic forms to mask manifestly incorrect thinking.
That is why they cannot resolve paradoxes such as the Liar and Jourdain's
I spotted it instantly. Are you claiming that "horse" is univocally predicated in "some horses have wings" and "winged horses have wings"?
That is why I defined what I meant by logic: the science of correct thinking (about reality). That is what I am offering to justify. — Dfpolis
Yet, if, in criticizing the proof of a theorem in Constructive Mathematics I were to say that in addition to an axiom you used applying or not applying there was some other possibility you had not considered, surely you would object.
So, while you may construct a system which makes no internal use of the principle of excluded middle, in reasoning about that system, you would use the principle. — Dfpolis
So, when we apply mathematical or cybernetic algorithms, the reasoning justifying their application is quite Aristotelian.
I've said while we can think of impossible states, there can't be impossible states. You have not provided a single example of a real state violating the ontological principles of identity, contradiction or excluded middle. — Dfpolis
No, it is not question begging. It is an experiential claim to which you have provided no counter example or rebutting argument — Dfpolis
No. Definitions of terms point to aspects of reality that can be experienced and analyzed. So, the question is not about the self-consistency of semantic relations, but about the adequacy of my account to our experience of reality. — Dfpolis
As I said, logic is not about the consistency of language, but about salve veritate thinking. To save truth, you must start with truth. "All winged horses are horses" is not a truth, but an equivocation. "Winged horses" are not "horses" in the sense living equine creatures, which is the sense of "horses" required by the conclusion. In the same way, there is no true statement in which "the present king of England" is taken as having a substantive reference. — Dfpolis
It speaks poorly of those who educated you in logic that you are unable to spot so obvious an equivocation. Correct thinking is not about matching letter sequences or manipulating word strings. It is about using conceptual representations rationally.
If logic is not about reality... Then it is? Imagination? — Blue Lux
Logic is a statement of fact/in relation to fact. If there is any error, it cannot be logic/logical. — BrianW
We might be a little more explicit and say it is the science of correct thinking about reality -- because we want it to be salve veritate -- if our premises reflect reality, then we want "correct thinking" to be such that our conclusions will necessarily reflect reality. — Dfpolis
that it is impossible to both be and not be at one and the same time in one and the same way (the principle of contradiction) and that a putative reality either is, or is not (the Principle of Excluded Middle). Thus, these principles are not a priori, not forms of reason, but a posteriori understandings that are so fundamental that once we come to grasp them, we understand that they apply to all being. — Dfpolis
Working through the valid forms of syllogism with this understanding, we can see how the role of identity in propositions, together with the principles of being, justifies them — Dfpolis
That's tricky though, right? Because the sort of abstraction and structure building we associate with mathematics seems to be what we use to formalize existing informal practices. There's some chicken and egg trouble here.
But there are further puzzles. It's also quite natural to think that formalization is possible in the first place because the underlying structure was there and operative all along. Formalization would then be not an invention we superimpose on a practice but the discovery of the true structure, the essence of what we were doing, in our imperfect way, the whole time. That puzzle becomes particularly acute in the cases of mathematics and logic.
The mind can be used to study the mind just like a logical argument can be used to justify logic. This circularity is benign. — TheMadFool
So, there's nothing wrong with using a sound argument to justify logic. This isn't a vicious circularity as long as we come up with a sound argument free of fallacies. — TheMadFool
So, my final argument looks like this:
Argument A:
1. If ALL the predictions of logic are true then logic is justified
2. ALL the predictions of logic are true
So,
3. Logic is justified
Argument A is NOT circular and is a valid application of modus ponens. — TheMadFool
Yes, but as I said it is also true that Clinton did not won the election if something is present (namely a presence of Clinton losing).
I can't see the problem; the "state of how things really are" is that she lost the election.
Do the Buddhists explain why to show the limits of logic, one needs to use logic?
What would be the fault of trying to show the limits of logic without using logic?
Should irrefutable beliefs be valued according to their truth or their utility?
Here, the condition of irrefutable is necessary since otherwise one would clearly value the beliefs according to their truth considering they can be proven to be true or false.
But some condition does have to be met, otherwise the statement is false or not truth-apt. So in the case of the cat on the mat, there has to be some cat on some mat that's being talked about. Same for snow being white and it's raining outside.
One thing to note about those is there seems to be a general condition that's being met for the empirical domain, which is that the condition is something being a certain way in the world. That's where the common correspondence intuition comes from.
What is a deflationist trying to accomplish or say? — Marchesk
X is true iff x is true.
Is that all we've been arguing about? Because that tells me nothing that I didn't already know. Of course a statement is true if and only if it's true — Marchesk
Okay, so it then has nothing to do with the question of what truth is? — Marchesk
To avoid that, deflation is proposing an identity between making a statement and that statement being true. — Marchesk
Can one know what it is like to be a man? Or what it is like to be a woman? How, if one can have no more than one's own experiences? — Banno
Alright, but that's false, because snow is not always white, just like the cat is not always on the mat. You need something else to make the two equivalent. — Marchesk
Okay, I mean nobody disagrees with saying that true and false are linguistic conventions we agreed to. That's not what's of importance. We could have used any word to denote the meaning behind true and false. And it's the meaning that's at stake.
What the defalationist is saying amounts to there being no meaning other than the lingustic convention, which sounds prima facia absurd, and what I'm trying to argue against. — Marchesk
So I'm not sure what the deflationist is trying to say here. Are they denying anything else needs to be said about the relationship between Line 3 and Line 1?
It is not surprising that we should have use for a predicate P with the property that “‘_ _ _ _ _’ is P” an d “_____” are always interdeducible. F or we frequently fin d ourselves in a position to assert each sentence in a certain infinite set z (e.g. w hen all the members of z 11 O n the preceding page Soames makes clear that he takes Tarski to be com mitted both to sufficiency an d to necessity. T he point here is that the “must” obscures the fact that the claims about partial definition can support only the claim that implication of the biconditionals is sufficient.Theories of Truth and Convention T share a common form); lacking the means to formulate infinite conjunctions, we find it convenient to have a single sentence which is warranted precisely when each member of z is warranted. A predicate P with the property described allows us to construct such a sentence: (x)(x ∈ z → P(x)). Truth is thus a notion that we might reasonably want to have on hand, for expressing semantic ascent an d descent, infinite conjunction and disjunction. And given that we want such a notion, it is not difficult to ex plain h o w it is that we have been able to invent one: the Tarski sentences, which axiomatize the notion of truth, are by no means a complicated or recondite axiomatization; the possibility of moving from this axiomatization to the explicit truth definition was always latent in the logical structure of language, though it took a Tarski to discover it. Truth is useful, we may say, as a device of (what Quine calls) disquotation … . To explain the utility of disquotation we need say nothing about the relations between language and the world.
To capture what he considered to be the essence of the Correspondence Theory, Alfred Tarski created his Semantic Theory of Truth. In Tarski's theory, however, talk of correspondence and of facts is eliminated. (Although in early versions of his theory, Tarski did use the term "correspondence" in trying to explain his theory, he later regretted having done so, and *dropped the term altogether since it plays no role within his theory*.) The Semantic Theory is the successor to the Correspondence Theory. It seeks to preserve the core concept of that earlier theory but without the problematic conceptual baggage.
[...]
We can rewrite Tarski's T-condition on three lines:
The proposition expressed by the German sentence
1) "Schnee ist weiss" is true
2) if and only if
3) snow is white
Line 1 is about truth. Line 3 is not about truth – it asserts a claim about the nature of the world. Thus T makes a substantive claim. Moreover, it avoids the main problems of the earlier Correspondence Theories in that the terms "fact" and "correspondence" play no role whatever.