I thought retribution semantically referred to restoration. — Bob Ross
ok, that makes sense of some of the things you have said. Thank you.
Retribution has a curious etymology, apparently referring back to considerations between the three tribes of Rome - from
tri...,
tribe, tribune, tribute, and retribution. So it originally had more of the flavour you suggest. Now it is about punishment.
You never address what I write though — Bob Ross
I devoted just under three hundred words to directly addressing a single paragraph,
.
But I'll do it again, for your 36-point argument.
I think it a
terrible argument. It pretends to be syllogistic, to be of the form of a series of syllogisms, but mixes metaphorical statements, leaps over unarticulated premisses, sliding from ontological claims to personalistic language, without logical mediation. The pretense of syllogistic form masks a series of conceptual sleights of hand, category shifts, and metaphorical intrusions.
This is the nature of the Thomistic style, featuring notions such as divine simplicity, pure actuality, pure intellect, and causal emanation via knowing and willing, all of which are to say the least questionable.
Despite claiming god to be a simple, it juxtaposes will and intellect; subject and object; father and son and so on. But those distinctions are the very thing denied by divine simplicity. The argument rests on this contradiction. Now we know that a contradiction implies anything, so we should be wary of an argument that is so dependent on contradiction.
Then there's the idea that if god thinks something is real, it becomes real. Let's set aside the issue of how this debars god from thinking about things that are not real - the common "what if..." of modality. In thinking about himself he somehow brings about the Son. Is the Son then the same as that thinking, and so not more than a thought, or is the Son a second being caused by God's thinking of himself - in which case he is not simple, not One Being? These and other objections will result from the very notion that to think something, for god, is to create it, since in doing so god must drop the distinction between existing and being thought about. But we have that distinction for good reason.
In more modern terms there is a play on the use of the existential operator, a slide from using it as second order predicate to a first order predicate, that is invalid in ordinary predicate logic. Assigning a predicate to an individual presumes there is an individual, it cannot create that individual. See
Inexpressibility of Existence Conditions.
Then there is the point I made earlier, the use of anthropomorphic language on which the charge of presuming what you wish to conclude rests. Is this language built into the argument, or is it stretching abstract reasoning to meet revelation? It smells like Anselm's "...and this we all call god"; a conclusion unsupported by the proceeding argument, but fitting it neatly into already accepted doctrine. A slight of hand.
Let's look at a sample.
. 6. Since He is absolutely simple, His willing and thinking are identical.
7. Therefore, Him willing something as real is identical to Him thinking of something as real.
8. Therefore, when He thinks of something as real it must create something.
It's not a syllogism, since it misses the hidden assumption that thinking of something as real necessarily makes it real. God, then, can' think of things that are not real, something that is routine for us. So what we have here is a loaded metaphysical claim, not a deduction, as well as the contradiction in being an absolute simple and yet having identifiable will and intellect.
Reiterating, one problem is that the argument assumes divine simplicity but proceeds by introducing various juxtapositions and differentiations.
Another is that it unjustly slides from the language of necessity into the language of revelation.
Another is that it apparently invalidly moves from a second level existential predication to a first level existential predication - it derives the existence of a thing from it's properties.
Another is the ambiguity of key terms such as "create", "real", "person" and so on.
And the main objection, that it is guided by a doctrinal target.
Now I am sure you will be able to mount a defence for each of these objections. That in itself is problematic, since it will add to the count of 36 lines... Sure, you are able to add and add and add, explaining to yourself why this argument makes sense - but is that enough? Don't you aslo want an argument that others will accept? At what point do you give up the whole enterprise as a Bad Lot?
I've already done so.