• Bob's Normative Ethical Theory
    Ah, here it is Bob! I almost missed it. We've already discussed at length on the meta-ethical considerations, but I will dismiss them here.

    I ground the entire (normative and applied) ethical theory in one moral judgment: “one ought to be rational”.Bob Ross

    No disagreement with you there. I'll take it as an assumption going forward. The issue comes from the following statement:

    There is no moral fact which dictates that one ought to be rational, but any sane person will agree to this moral judgment (subjectively)Bob Ross

    Let me type in a similar sentence and I think you'll see the problem:

    "There is no fact that dictates God exists, but any sane person will agree to this judgement."

    Claims like this beg challenges and can cause people to dismiss your claims outright. I'm not going to do that of course. I'm just noting that if you want to get to your point, you don't have to make claims like this. A simple "I'm not here to debate why one should choose the subjective start of, 'one ought to do what is rational.' I'm simply going to start with this and show a morality based on rationality." will work fine. So that's what I'm going to do. I'll assume that we take the prime assumption that we ought to act rationally and go from there.

    t is important to explicate what exactly is meant by ‘rationality’. By this term I mean ‘the quality of being based in reason and logic’.Bob Ross

    Sounds good.

    P1: If something is solely a means towards an end, then it is not an end in itself.
    P2: To value something entails it is solely a means towards an end.
    C1: To value something entails it is not an end in itself.
    Bob Ross

    P1 is fine, but how do we get P2? Can I not value an end itself? If I valued world peace, would that not be the end of my means? Can you explain further what you mean by P2?

    But ok, lets assume C1 is true regardless for now.

    P3: To value something entails it is not an end in itself.
    P4: Minds are something.
    C2: To value a mind entails that they are not an end in themselves.
    Bob Ross

    That is fine, but what if I don't value a mind? I'm assuming with the initial premise of "we ought to be rational" that "minds are rational, therefore they should be valued for they ought to be." The problem is you're trying to separate this from Kant, noting that one can have a mind but it not be rational. This leads into the question "Why should minds, even irrational ones, be valued?" If I recall you've given an answer to this long ago, but I don't remember it and I'm not seeing it here. I think it was something along the lines that you considered rational beings beings that had the capacity for rationality, not that they were necessarily rational. Can you clarify that? Onto the next set.

    P5: Persons (i.e., beings with personhood) are ends in themselves.
    P6: Minds are persons.
    C3: Minds are ends in themselves.
    Bob Ross

    I'm a little confused by P5. Why are persons ends in themselves? Can't I use persons as means to my goals, even benevolently? If I send soldiers out to stop a terrorist, am I not using those soldiers, those people, as means to an end?

    For P6, your intended goal was to separate minds from persons so that it can apply to rational agents, not merely persons. If you want to keep with that intention I would reorder P6 to "Persons are minds" or "Persons have minds". With this C3 follows.

    P6: One should not accept contradictions as true.
    P7: If one values a mind, then they are contradicting themselves (because it concedes that a mind is and is not an end in itself). [ !(C2 ^ C3) ]
    C4: One should not value minds.
    Bob Ross

    I see you're trying a proof by contradiction but you've left out an equally probable conclusion: That persons, and thus minds are means and not ends in themselves. This is because you haven't proven either of the statements, only asserted them. Still, lets continue and assume you can demonstrate C4 as true.

    P7: One should not value minds.
    P8: To consider a mind valueless is to value them at 0.
    C5: One should not consider minds valueless.
    Bob Ross

    Again I'm going to assume minds have value because they are rational and therefore have innate value. So since we should not consider minds valueless, they have value. And since minds have value, people have value. But then doesn't this prove that people are not ends in themselves?

    P9: If one should not value a mind (including a value of 0), then minds should be considered invaluable.
    P10: One should not value a mind (including a value of 0).
    C6: Minds should be considered invaluable.
    Bob Ross

    I'm a bit confused again, but are you saying that your conclusion C5 is now being contradicted though P1? That we should consider that minds have value? Then why are we asserting that minds don't have value? Are you stating that not valuing a mind with the representation of 0, is in fact a value? Because that just doesn't work Bob. The number zero is a representation of there not being a quantity. The number zero is not a quantity in itself. The number zero for value is a representation of there being no value, a numeric assignment of zero for value does not mean there exists a value. It means there is no underlying represented value.

    Finally, the term 'invaluable' means that it has so much value, it cannot be quantified into one number. It doesn't mean it has no value at all.

    From the sheer impossibility (without conceding a contradiction) to value something which creates value, any rational agent is required treat creators of value (i.e., minds: persons) always as simultaneously ends in themselves: as invaluable. It follows from this the sanctity of persons (i.e., of minds) because they are invaluableBob Ross

    It seems the overall conclusion you want to make out of this is it is impossible to value something that creates value. Since we cannot value an end in itself, we should treat people as so valuable they cannot be quantified into any comparative value? And because we cannot quantify this value, we cannot 'evaluate a value' of them, thus they are ends in themselves?

    I think you're trying to say something here, but its just not coming across correctly. It seems to me that when you speak about valuing something, you're talking about a quantative value. For example, lets say we valued a person's worth at 10,000 dollars. If of course we could value people quantitively, then we could use them as means to an end. For example, I could use a person worth 10,000 dollars to make myself 1 million dollars. However, if human value is so valuable as to be beyond quantification, an infinite value so to speak, then we could never use a human as a means to an end. We don't use infinite money to make infinite money, that's silly. We simply enjoy infinite money.

    Is that what you were trying to say? This seems to jive with your idea of your formula of ideal sovereignty. If all people are infinitely valuable, sacrificing one infinity for 99 infinities works in the moment of practical necessity, but one infinity is just as equivalent in value to 99 infinities, thus this sacrifice should be abated where possible.

    I'm going to stop here for now and let you answer the questions I've posted.
  • Mitigating Intergenerational Dysfunction Through Knowledge and Awareness
    I agree with you. The primary reason, at least in America, why I can see this not being implemented is the long abstinence policy and sexual shame we heap upon teenagers to control them. The only child rearing lesson is typically an assignment in which a person has to lug around a fake baby for a week or two and find out how much of a pain it is to take care of it to discourage young women or men from having unprotected sex, or to abstain entirely.

    Not that I think we shouldn't try to lobby such a thing, but there might be a non-insignificant outcry of "the government shouldn't be teaching us how to raise children", and "Why do teenagers need to know how to raise kids? They shouldn't be having them in the first place."

    Still, nice points.
  • Why is the Hard Problem of Consciousness so hard?
    You are not describing the HPoC. It's true that nobody/thing can experiences my subjective experiences. But the HP is not that we can't communicate subjective experience; it is how a clump of matter can have them at all.Patterner

    You may have misunderstood that point within the full context of what I was communicating, or I was unclear. It is not that we cannot communicate our subjective experience. Its that we cannot experience another's subjective experience. Meaning that there is no objective way to measure another's subjective experience.

    We can very clearly identify and even medically manipulate consciousness. We use anesthesa to put people unconscious. You can drink alcohol, get drunk, and alter your consciousness. Consciousness is clearly physical. How we define consciousness through behavior, and test to understand it at a mechanistic level is the easy problem. Have we fully solved the easy problem? Not at all. Science will likely take centuries to uncover how the brain works at a complete physical level.

    The bet you referred to, as I understood it, was about the Easy problem. You can read it here.
    https://www.nature.com/articles/d41586-023-02120-8 I'm careful to make a full claim on this because this is one article from a news reporter who may not have understood the full subject. But from my understanding, the neuroscientist believed they would have a neuronal explanation of what causes consciousness. This is the easy problem. Even if this is answered, the hard problem of what it is like to experience consciousness for any particular subject will still exist.

    " Explaining why consciousness occurs at all can be contrasted with so-called “easy problems” of consciousness: the problems of explaining the function, dynamics, and structure of consciousness. These features can be explained using the usual methods of science. But that leaves the question of why there is something it is like for the subject when these functions, dynamics, and structures are present. This is the hard problem.

    In more detail, the challenge arises because it does not seem that the qualitative and subjective aspects of conscious experience—how consciousness “feels” and the fact that it is directly “for me”—fit into a physicalist ontology, one consisting of just the basic elements of physics plus structural, dynamical, and functional combinations of those basic elements. It appears that even a complete specification of a creature in physical terms leaves unanswered the question of whether or not the creature is conscious. And it seems that we can easily conceive of creatures just like us physically and functionally that nonetheless lack consciousness. This indicates that a physical explanation of consciousness is fundamentally incomplete: it leaves out what it is like to be the subject, for the subject. There seems to be an unbridgeable explanatory gap between the physical world and consciousness. All these factors make the hard problem hard."

    https://iep.utm.edu/hard-problem-of-conciousness/#:~:text=The%20hard%20problem%20of%20consciousness%20is%20the%20problem%20of%20explaining,directly%20appear%20to%20the%20subject.
  • Why is the Hard Problem of Consciousness so hard?
    However, the fact of my own consciousness is apodictic (beyond doubt) for each of us, is it not? That is the sense that Descartes' cogito is right on the mark, is it not?Wayfarer

    Yes, definitely. The hard problem does not exist for our own selves. For we are the experiencers of that particular locus of matter called the brain. I would be able to measure my brain waves and find out exactly what brain state made me feel what I feel. The problem is, I could never communicate that exact subjective feeling to others in an objective way. The hard problem is not in objectively measuring our own subjective experience with our brains, its in communicating our own subjective experience to another subjective being with an objective means of verification.

    Its really really another variation of, "Is the green I see the green you see?" We both have the wavelength of light enter our eyes and processed by our brain a particular way. We both call it green. We could see the process of the brain and wait for each of us to say when we see green. But do we subjectively experience what we each call green exactly the same way? That's something beyond our capability to objectively know.
  • Why is the Hard Problem of Consciousness so hard?
    I would have thought that the distinction between sentient beings and insentient objects is a fundamental not only in philosophy.Wayfarer

    The point of the hard problem is to demonstrate the limits of what we can know about consciousness and sentience in others besides their behavior. Like you said, there is no brain correlate to what a person subjectively feels as pain, only what a person expresses or is observed to be in pain. Logically, this means we cannot state what a person feels like or does not feel like. Meaning, we cannot know the subjective feeling beyond their behavior. This also means we cannot know the subjective feeling despite their behavior.

    This leads to the P-zombie. The creature that acts conscious, but we do not know if it subjectively feels conscious. But a P-zombie can sometimes confuse the issue as well, as people get stuck on the behavior. You know the debates. A rock is a more simple way of getting to the heart of the problem by removing the idea of behavior entirely. A rock does not act conscious, but we do not know if it subjectively feels conscious. For if we did know that it does or does not subjectively feel conscious apart from its behavior, then we would have an objective way of telling if something does or does not subjectively feel conscious. That is something we can never know be it rock, bug, animal, plant, or human.
  • Why is the Hard Problem of Consciousness so hard?
    But what it is it like to BE the rock AS the rock?
    — Philosophim

    I think this demonstrates a failure to grasp the point at issue.
    Wayfarer

    I appreciate the citation to get the point home, but I think the rock analogy is also useful as well. We know about consciousness through our own behavior and then others mimicking that behavior. But we cannot know what it is like to actually be that other. A rock does not show any behavior of being conscious, and we do not believe a rock can have the experience of a rock, but we cannot know that either.
  • A Digital Physics Argument for the existence of God
    without first contrasting what a simulation is vs what a non-simulated world is, its mostly circular.
    — Philosophim

    A world is a set of objects in a space. The decision of whether something is simulated versus non-simulated would rest on whether something emerges from information processing.
    I haven't spotted the circularity, could you point it out to me?
    Hallucinogen

    Sure. What I meant is that without defining what a non-simulated world is, but only defining a simulated world, its turned out like:

    A. Its given that the world is simulated.
    B. Therefore the world is simulated.
  • Why is the Hard Problem of Consciousness so hard?
    The hard problem of consciousness is largely misunderstood by many people. Its not that mechanics lead to consciousness. We know that. Its uncontroversial except to soul people.

    The truly hard problem of consciousness is that we can never objectively test what it is like to be conscious from the subjects view point. Think of it like this, "What is it like to be a rock?" We understand the atomic make up and composition of the rock. But what it is it like to BE the rock AS the rock?

    This is unknowable. Same as it is for anyone else but you to know what it is like to be you. We could reproduce your atomic makeup down to the T, but we could never objectively monitor what it is like for the subject itself to feel what it is feeling. We can measure your brain states and after testing say, "When the subject's brain state is X, we have learned this is when the subject feels happy." But we don't know what its like for that subject to be happy. We could learn the mechanics of your brain and body and predict everything you were going to think and say seconds before you thought or said it. But we can never know what its like to be the person with that brain, thinking or saying those thoughts.

    As such, its unsolvable. Its simply a limitation of our ability to know. Only if we could erase our self-consciousness, place our self into another consciousness, then retain the memories of that consciousness when we reverted to our own, could we claim to know what its like to be another consciousness. So far, that's impossible.
  • About definitions and the use of dictionaries in Philosophy
    The primary goal of any philosophical discussion is to be in agreement on clearly defined concepts, or definitions. A dictionary is a fantastic way to start, because it forces the conversation into something that can apply to the language of the user outside of these forums. I've often stated that defining a word too far from the norm is a logical fallacy. Generally its done by people who want the normal emotion evoked from the word, but don't like the logical consequences of the original meaning, so twist it into something they want. We all do it to a degree, its the reason why that can tell us whether its in the wrong or not.

    While a dictionary is a great place to start, sometimes the philosophical discussion is about the word itself. Meaning that the current definition has something lacking. If so, the person who wants to change the definition should give a very clear alternative definition, and also why they think it is necessary and enhances the word. This should be the very first step in any philosophical discussion, and oftentimes discussions boil down to whether a person accepts this new definition or not.

    That being said, anyone who gives you flak for daring to use a dictionary should be red flagged in your mind. Anyone who resists clear definitions is likely a charlatan who will continue to twist and retwist the meaning any time you think you get a handle on it and it points to a contradiction. Discussing with people like this can be a waste of time, so be careful.

    This is different from discussing from someone who is trying to get a clear definition. Such a person will appreciate the dictionary reference, but point out where it lacks, and propose an alternative. Often times this alternative has not been fully explored either, and can gain solid identification through the act of discussion. Arguably, this is the entire goal and purpose of philosophy. Read the intent of the person to see if the discussion is about discovery or "I want to be right and use this word no matter what the underlying definition is".
  • A first cause is logically necessary
    This is what I wanted you to say. So, since we can imagine or define whatever we want, does that mean there's an any-to-any relationship between the thing defined and the symbol we attach to it (e.g., the meaning, the concept)?Hallucinogen

    It appears we're veering into a discussion of knowledge opposed to the OP about a logically necessary first cause. I've written an extensive knowledge theory here: https://thephilosophyforum.com/discussion/14044/knowledge-and-induction-within-your-self-context/p1

    If you want a summary, Caerulea-Lawrence in the first reply wrote a near perfect grasp of the theory. So you can read that first before to see if it sparks your interest to wade in.
  • A first cause is logically necessary
    Did you mean that the concept of infinity comes from a mind?
    — Philosophim
    I mean both -- I don't believe anything has a non-mental origination.
    Hallucinogen

    Interesting, do you mean how we interpret the world is all mental? I don't think anyone would disagree with that. But the world beyond our interpretation doesn't seem mental. If a tree falls in the forest and no one is there, something still happens as a thing in itself. The mental tries to define and create identity in the sea of existence, but the sea of existence is still there whether we are or not.

    As the infinite is unprovable
    — Philosophim

    Would you say that you can decide whatever it is you mean?
    Hallucinogen

    Let me clarify. There are two things. Definitions, and their application.

    I can define a unicorn, but in applying it, I cannot confirm a unicorn exists beyond an idea. We can invent whatever definitions and concepts we want inside of our head. It is their ability to be applied to reality, or their lack, that determine what I meant by 'provability'. So, I can create whatever definition and meaning for that definition I want. But if I cannot apply it to reality, then it is merely an idea and not anything that is provable within reality.
  • What is the way to deal with inequalities?
    Its a very good question. What I like to consider is first a floor, or minimum standard for a decent human life. What does that entail within a society?

    Second, what is that society capable of? Is it still a hunger gatherer society? Does it have modern infrastructure? What is the basic minimum technology needed to perform at this floor within that society?

    Third, what is the minimum expected output of work for a human to obtain these things? Such a minimum should not be taxing to the point where the individual suffers undue calculable harm vs the benefits it brings them. In a hunter gatherer society, hunting poses risks, but is necessary to meet the minimum standards of being able to eat.

    Fourth, what is the individual capable of doing within society? Are they disabled? Weak? Smart? Strong? We should expect such people to be able to contribute with their strengths, and not push them to work in ways that constantly expose their weaknesses.

    As a starting point, I believe a society should work with these ideas in mind. Of course, as others work past these minimum requirements and further technology and outcomes, the floor will rise and things will need to be readjusted. The invention of a wheel chair allows a person who cannot walk new mobility. Medication for psychiatric disorders and let a person function normally. The invention of the internet allows new social connections and immediately accessible knowledge.

    Because of this, a maximum ceiling of benefits should only be considered in the case where this prevents the floor from rising, or pushes the floor down for others. Other than that, we need people who push past the floor because it is the only way we rise as a species.
  • A first cause is logically necessary
    Of course the Alpha does have prior reasoning why it came into existence: itself.Hallucinogen

    I appreciate the read and hope it was enjoyable. We're stating practically the same thing. In the most technical sense, there is nothing prior to the alpha existence's self, so that is why I do not say "prior reason". But this statement : "Inference to the Alpha allows its interior universe to have logical basis on which to explain its own existence and that of the Alpha." is spot on.

    Causality isn't infinite but there has to be reasonable grounds on which we include infinity in a model or not. That means that infinity does have a criteria for being explained within a certain structure. Well, we conceptualize infinity and we have minds, so it seems that the infinite has a mind.Hallucinogen

    Did you mean that the concept of infinity comes from a mind? I can agree with that. There is nothing within the infinite itself that indicates it is a 'thing' with a mind. As the infinite is unprovable, as any actual test for the infinite would always reveal more to test, it is a plausible concept, but not a provable reality.
  • A Measurable Morality
    I asked why do normative “moral” claims need a reason and you said because “if there is no reason, then there is no ‘should’”: why?

    This seems to imply that I cannot assert “one should not torture babies” without an underlying reason; but I clearly can, no?
    Bob Ross

    Because that is the nature of 'should' vs 'an action or statement'. I can claim, "One should not torture babies." If you then ask "Why?" there's a reason why we should do X. If I answer, "No reason," then I can come back with, "Well I think we should torture babies". If you ask "Why?" and I answer "No reason." then we shouldn't do X. Why even use the word 'should' at that point?"

    If I can claim X should while in the same breath claiming that X should not, then should and should not have no meaning. If should and should not have no meaning, there is no morality. But of course, we're assuming morality exists for now.

    No. Again, I think you missed the point: if platonism were true, then “I should not torture babies” does get reasoned down to “why should anything exist?” or “something should exist”: it is true in virtue of a Platonic Form.Bob Ross

    I noted earlier that what I am talking about is a foundation. To prove a foundation exists, you must prove that the foundation is logically true, and that means there is nothing that exists prior. It is true in virtue of its existence and nothing else. I'm assuming we both agree Platonic forms aren't true and not a foundation. If you do believe it to be a true foundation, then please, show me how.

    So for example, "Platonism is True because of A. It should exist because it is necessary that Platonic forms exist, and there is no other possible option." If of course there are other options other than Platonic forms, then the chain continues. If you're not seriously demonstrating Platonic forms are the foundation of 'should', just understand we're using "Platonic forms" as an abstract X for a thought experiment about the foundation of 'should' to help you understand the chain.

    I think, and correct me if I am wrong, you are noting that whatever moral claims may be true they are not useful to the subject if the subject doesn’t think they should exist; and then you are applying that to existence itself: “to be or not to be?”. But, crucially, it can go the other way around just as easily: “one should help the sick” implies that “one should continue existing”--in this case, the former is not true in virtue of the latter but actually vice-versa.Bob Ross

    No, this has nothing to do with the usefulness to a subject. Humanity isn't even the picture. There is just the question of "Should at least one point of atomic existence be" or "Should nothing be?" That's the foundational question.

    But, crucially, it can go the other way around just as easily: “one should help the sick” implies that “one should continue existing”Bob Ross

    Right. Because if I claim, "One should help the sick." A pre-requisite is that one exist. But we're not talking about what one should do at this point. That's a few steps away. We're just talking about the foundation of good if morality is indeed objective.

    I think you may have misread my response there: I disagree with you that there is a contradiction in A B C argument you have.Bob Ross

    I never claimed that there was a contradiction.

    Therefore, there should not exist a reason that justifies non-existence.Bob Ross

    If objective morality is true (Remember, this is an assumption!), and 'nothingness' has no reason for it to be, then then the only other option is that existence should be.
  • A Case for Moral Subjectivism
    I want to, firstly, express my gratitude for your elaborate response: I can tell you read through it all and I know how much effort it is to respond that lengthy and substantively—so thank you!Bob Ross

    Not a problem! I greatly respect your work and try to give it its full due. I have noted in the past that it is something I greatly appreciate you having done with me in the past. It is the least I can do!

    But truth isn’t a thing-in-itself in that sense...that just seems super weird to say that the relationship itself exists as an entity, a thing-in-itself, out there that we are grasping. This seems platonistic to me.Bob Ross

    I agree it is a bit weird. I was thinking of a better way to say it earlier today as thoughts on your paper were roaming through my head. The thing in itself is objective. Truth as forever unknown to us is a thing in itself. Truth as known to us is subjective, and is at best an approximation that can never be known in the objective sense. The best way to subjectively know truth is to make a judgement that is not contradicted by reality.

    Which would you like to talk about, or would you like to pause and discuss normative ethics?Bob Ross

    Honestly Bob, whatever you want. I'm just another subject giving opinions as I look into your ideas from another viewpoint. At any time you can agree to disagree, simply note things that have been stated or move on. It is respect for the time and effort you've put into this work that I try to seriously read your ideas and give it thought. Where this is useful to you, lets us continue. Where it is not, it is not!

    Let me at least answer your summaries, and feel free to select what you find worth discussing.

    1. Moral judgments expressing something subjective vs. being subjective themselves. You seem to be focusing on the latter, while I the former.Bob Ross

    To me, I do not see a separation between the two with your definition of subjective. If everything we judge is mind dependent, then all moral judgements are subjective (in the fact we make them) and all moral judgements express something subjective (in the fact we make them). Since what is objective is mind independent, there is nothing we can say, do, or judge that is objective, as it is all subjective.

    2. You believe I didn’t provide a positive case for prong-2 of my thesis, but I think the proof of (1) moral judgments being propositional, (2) some moral judgments being true, and (3) that moral judgments do not express something objective entails that moral judgments express something subjective.Bob Ross

    If your claim is simply "Moral judgments express something subjective", by you definition of subjective, this is a given. It is only when you introduce truth where the question of objective comes in. If the thing in itself of a moral judgement correlates with reality, then it is objectively true. To subjectively know this, we simply observe whether our judgement is contradicted by reality.

    The point I was trying to get at was not that this was 'wrong'. My point was that the definition of subjective is so broad, that this applies to anything we state, judge, do or say, even outside of morality. It also doesn't negate the fact that there is still objective truth, and how we know that truth subjectively. We might call this subjective truth a non-contradictory belief, or knowledge.

    If you are claiming there are subjective moral judgements that are true, then there must be some underlying objective morality that is true. If there is no underlying objective morality in which our subjective judgement correlates with reality, then there is no true subjective moral judgement either. This goes for any statement, intent, action, etc.

    3. Truth-aptness for you is not contingent on a statement/sentence, but for me it is.
    4. The liar paradox, stated as ‘this statement is false’, for you is truth-apt, for me it is not.
    Bob Ross

    That's fine, mine is another viewpoint to consider or dismiss.

    For you, it seems to be a problem that we cannot acquire 100% certain knowledge of what is objective because we only know it through ourselves as subjects, which I don’t see anything wrong with. I have no problem admitting that we only have conditional knowledge of the things-in-themselves, in the sense that we only every analyze representations of things-in-themselves: this doesn’t mean that we are just analyzing things which are purely subjective.Bob Ross

    I don't have a problem with the first part at all. But by consequence, this means that everything we analyze is purely subjective, as our analysis is mind dependent. As you have defined subjective, if there is even an iota of mind dependency, its 100% subjective. As defined, everything is purely subjective that we discuss. I have no problem thinking along these lines, I just find that it just makes the term 'subjective' fairly pointless when discussing morality, as everything we do is subjective. For me it boils down to the question, "If what is objective is mind-dependent, how can we as minds ever analyze anything objective?" To me, we can't, therefore everything we do is subjective, not just morality.

    You seem to think that it is a flaw in my theory that moral judgments cannot never be false relative to the psychology of the person at hand, but this just seems like it is the central idea behind the theory itself.Bob Ross

    I really should have used another word, falsifiable. If you are making a claim that something is true, it must also be falsifiable to be considered seriously in application. So for example, if I claimed "God exists", someone should be able to ask, "So what would be the case in which God does not exist?" Even if that case is not true, I should be able to make a case such as, "If I pray and God does not answer, God does not exist". If the claim of God existing was not falsifiable, someone would always come up with an excuse or reason why that doesn't prove God false.

    So in what case is your falsifiable claim that moral decisions are true based on our psychology? You need not reply to me, just something to ponder for yourself.

    7. I think that moral permissibility is the allowance to do something, which doesn’t entail that one should or should not do it, and you seem to think it means that one should do it; and this is why I think you think there is a symmetry behind my example of eating a sandwhich = permissible and not eating a sandwich = impermissible; but I would say being permissible is not the same thing as one being obligated to do it.Bob Ross

    My problem with understanding your point was that you seemed to imply that acting in a particular way made it permissible. For something to be permissible, something else must be impermissible. If all is permissible, then there is nothing impermissible. And if there is nothing impermissible, at that point, why even use the term permissibility?

    As well, you seemed to imply it was actions itself that made something permissible. But if what is acted upon is permissible, then what is not acted on would be impermissible. Again, if what you did not act on was not impermissible, then it is permissible as well. But then we have everything permissible again, and it just seems simpler to say, "There is nothing one should or should not do, thus no morality."

    8. I don’t think moral nihilism is the view that there is no objective morality; but you seem to think we can simplify it down to that claim.Bob Ross

    Moral nihilism (also called ethical nihilism) is the meta-ethical view that nothing is morally right or morally wrong and that morality doesn't exist.
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Moral_nihilism#:~:text=Moral%20nihilism%20(also%20called%20ethical,a%20particular%20culture%20or%20individual.

    If there is no objective morality, then it can never be true nothing should or should not be. If nothing should or should not be, then morality does not exist.

    10. At one point, you said I don’t believe there are true moral judgments, but I do.Bob Ross

    I wasn't trying to imply that you didn't believe there are true moral judgements, I was noting what it would entail to have a true moral judgement. A subjectively true moral judgement must at some objective level, correlate with reality. This is best known when reality does not actively contradict us.

    1. If there is not an objective morality, it means all possible claims of what should or should not happen,
    even contradictory claims, correlate with reality.

    This is not at all what objective morality means [in metaethics].
    Bob Ross

    I claimed what it entails for there not to be an objective morality with your definitions. An objective morality in your definitions, would be a moral judgement that objectively correlates with reality. Our understanding of it would be subjective, most likely in our judgement not being contradicted by reality. If there is no objective morality, then all subjective judgements, even contradictory ones, correlate with reality. There is no truth in what one should or should not do, only actions.

    Again, feel free to reply what you want to, or move on Bob. Take what is useful and discard the rest. :)
  • A Measurable Morality
    But why think that all normative claims need a reason? Why can’t “existing should be” just have no reason?Bob Ross

    First, as I requested, please stop using the term normative so that this stays simple and clear. We're not talking about any claim, but "moral claims". A moral claim involves 'should'. 'Should' requires a reason. If there is no reason, then there is no 'should'. If there is no 'should' there is no objective morality. Remember, we're assuming there is an objective morality, not proving that there is. If there is an objective morality, then there must be a should, and must be a reason.

    What if someone just says “well, if you can have no reason for why it is, then I don’t need a reason for why it should be”: what’s the symmetry breaker here?Bob Ross

    There is none. We can substitute this sentence with, "There is no objective morality". The symmetry comes in with the assumption "there is an objective morality".

    I think this missed my point, although I see what you are saying. You claimed all chains of reasoning boils down to “should existence be, or not?”...but my example clearly, if platonism were granted as true, that this is not true. The point was not that platonism is true, it is that if there are moral facts, then the chain of reasoning for a normative statements ends at the fact that makes it true, and not necessarily “should existence be, or not?”.Bob Ross

    Platonism's truth has nothing to do with whether it should be. For example, someone kills a baby. I can claim they should not have killed a baby. But its still true they killed a baby. When we say something 'should' exist, we say it that it is preferable that it be versus not be. So we can ask, "Why should Platonism exist?" To answer why Platonism or anything else should exist, we really have to answer the question, "Why should anything exist?" first.

    This doesn’t explain how this is a calculus of the universe: your answer seems to be that we just assume it. I guess this just boils down to me granting it for the sake of the conversation, so let’s just move past that point.Bob Ross

    Exactly! I am not claiming at this moment that there is an objective morality, I'm simply noting what an objective morality must necessarily be. After seeing the calculus in the rest of the OP and seeing if it works or not, we can definitely address that point.

    A. There exists a reason that nothing should exist.
    B. If that is the case, then the reason that nothing should exist, should not exist.
    Therefore, there should not exist a reason that justifies non-existence.

    There’s no logical contradiction in that syllogism, and I wholly agree with its form. In fact, I am glad you wrote this because that is way more precisely what I was trying to convey then what I was saying! (:
    Bob Ross

    We are in agreement then! We can then agree the only logical conclusion is that nothing should not be. Assuming an objective morality, the only thing we can start with then is that something is what should be. With that, we can move onto the next points.
  • There is No Such Thing as Freedom
    It all depends on how you define freedom. Freedom can simply mean, "To be free to follow one's intentions without hinderance". Of course what creates those intentions is biological and thus you're not free from them. But such a definition works with many phrases.

    Financial freedom - The freedom to buy what you want without risk of harm.
    Freedom of speech - The freedom to say what you want without being stopped.
    Freedom of choice - The freedom to choose an action despite others opinions that you shouldn't.
  • Getting rid of ideas
    So basically there's an idea that ideas don't exist? I think that answers its own question. :)
  • A Case for Moral Subjectivism
    I reviewed this and MAN is this long. A lot of these points address several details that honestly lead up to the summary at the end. I think the issues are summarized as follows:

    1. Making sure I understand your definitions of objective, subjective, and truth and their logical conclusions.
    2. Noting that the claim that all of our moral judgements are subjective, as is anything we do. Defining what it means to have a true moral judgement.
    3. Noting that you have no underlying claim as to why all true moral judgements are based on psychology through the definitions you use, and why such a claim leads to contradictions.

    I may repeat myself in points, so feel free to make the next focus about those three points so you don't have to spend too long on individual issues. For me, its the 3 points that matter, and all the details are an attempt to get to those points.

    Judgments are not necessarily statements. A moral non-cognitivist would say that moral judgments are emotional dispositions (i.e., they are conative not cognitive) that are along the lines of ‘boo to torturing babies!!!!!!!’, where they are not saying the moral judgment is the statement ‘boo to torturing babies!!!!!!’ but, rather, the underlying emotional attitude which can be expressed without a statement (e.g., someone looks very angry and astonished when witnessing someone torturing a baby, etc.). So when you say statements are truth-apt, even if it is true, it doesn’t get you moral cognitivism. You would have to demonstrate moral judgments are truth-apt; and you seem to just blow this off and ignore the entire literature on moral non-cognitivism.Bob Ross

    Ah, you didn't mention that specific definition of judgement. I would note that, or reference that there are some definitions like judgement which are being used in accordance with certain moral theories. But let me show you that what I noted still stands. Everything you do is truth apt. I'll explain below.

    Likewise, a ‘fact’ is a ‘statement which is true’ or, more precisely, ‘a statement which is truth-apt (i.e., a proposition) which corresponds appropriately with reality’.Bob Ross

    Meaning that anything a subject does either corresponds with reality, or does not. Including our feelings. I might feel angry at the idea of killing a baby and judge that I shouldn't. We can imagine an animal for example. Should it though? Its either true or false. Language is not needed. Morality is about the intent to act and the question on whether it should be acted upon or not. Its either true or false that you should. But the fact that its false that you should doesn't necessitate that its true that you shouldn't.

    In other words, if there is no true morality. there is no should, then it is false that you should. But this still makes moral judgements truth apt, as when something is false, it enters into the binary of the possibility of true. Truth-apt simply means what is stated could be true or false conceptually. It makes no claims as to the actual outcome.

    Meaning, if I take your definition of truth, subjectivity, and objectivity, everything is truth-apt. Either a belief, statement, emotion, etc. corresponds to reality, or it does not.

    2. Statements are not always truth-apt. For example, I would say that the statement “this statement is false” is not truth-apt because it cannot be evaluated as true or false...it lacks that capacity.Bob Ross

    But it is true that the statement is false. Many statements require implicit context for meaning. If we remove those implicit contexts, then It says nothing meaningful. Sentences which lack meaning are not truth apt, because they mean nothing but noise. Don't get caught up in the classic word game. :) We simply break the statement from nonsense into something that makes sense.

    A. This is a sentence - True
    B. A is false - False

    The above word game is just a classic mistaken case of combining two propositions and their assertions into one sentence. Regardless, you are talking about moral judgements, which are evaluations of what one should do. Anytime you introduce the word should, there is the result of its true that you should, or false that you should.

    If ‘1+1=2’ can be true, then you have already conceded it is truth-apt, but we are questioning why. Why think it is truth-apt?Bob Ross

    Because it is either true that 1+1=2, or it is false. I can write 1+2=2. This is also truth-apt. It is either true or false that 1+2=2. If something is true, it is truth-apt. If something is false, it is truth-apt.

    "A sentence is truth apt if there is some context in which it could be uttered (with its present meaning) and express a true or false proposition."
    https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/oi/authority.20110803105953845

    Yes, there are specific cases when there is no question of truth or falsity, but we're not talking about exceptions into here when we're speaking about morality and simple statements. The question isn't whether judgements and statements are truth-apt. The question is, "What is true?" And you've already answered that. So when we say true in your paper we mean, a subjective statement which is in concurrence with reality. The concurrence with reality is objective, and outside of the ability of the subject to know.

    Of course not! That’s what a normative ethical theory is for! The point of moral subjectivism is to note that whatever a person judges morally, it is made true by being a fact about their psychology and not some moral fact out there in the world. I think you have missed the point if you are demanding actual normative claims out of the theory.Bob Ross

    I definitely did miss the point! =D I suppose from my end, once you defined truth, its a given that judgements and statements are truth apt. However, something being truth-apt does not mean it is true. Which leaves me scratching my head when you make the leap to "Whatever a person judges morally, is true by their psychology." This is a claim that needs proof.

    A. Morality is about what I should do. It is truth-apt, meaning what should be done could be true, or
    false.
    B. A true moral judgement is a moral decision of 'should' that corresponds with reality. A
    false moral judgement is a moral decision of 'should' that does not correspond with
    reality.
    C. There is the possibility that I make an incorrect moral judgement, or one that does not correspond to
    reality. This would be a false moral judgement.
    D. I have a psychology. I make a moral judgement that I should do X because of my psychology.
    E. It is true that I should do X because of my psychology.
    F. But I have not shown why my psychology concurs with what should be in objective reality.
    G. Because of that, I can state, "It is false that I should do X because of my psychology." with equal
    weight.
    Therefore: G contradicts E.
    (I go over this again as a summary at the end)

    In other words Bob, for something to be truth apt, it must have the possibility of being assigned a true and a false condition. An example of something that is not truth-apt is something like the amateur understanding of God. There is no condition in which it is possible for God to be false, therefore God is not truth-apt, God is simply true.

    To demonstrate that a moral judgement is truth apt, there must be a condition for a moral judgement in which it could be false. Can you give me an example of a moral judgement based on one's psychology that would be false? And what I mean is, the condition. For example, "God is a physical being." It doesn't matter whether this is true or false, it simply means that if its true, God is physical, and if its false, God is not. What is the truth-apt condition of making moral decisions based on our judgements?

    4. Because we are subjects, morality is subjective.

    I’ve never argued this. This is clearly false.
    Bob Ross

    Let me clarify. We cannot know things in themselves. You've eliminated the term "objectivity" from any meaningful understanding besides "That which exists which we cannot know." So there could be an objective morality, but it would be beyond our knowledge. For if we could know it, that knowledge would be mind dependent. Known and discussed morality, by your definition, is subjective. As is everything we speak, judge, etc. So technically I should be saying, "Morality as we know it is subjective." But if we state that there is a true moral judgement, this means that our subjective moral judgement is concurrent with objective reality. This concurrence is itself objective, as it does not require our subject to realize this is happening. Truth as well is "a thing in itself" (More details on this later!) Since everything we discuss is from a subject Bob, everything as we know it is subjective.

    Likewise with moral cognitivism and moral non-nihilism. You just flatly assert or implicitly assume that they are true without providing an argument.Bob Ross

    First, I haven't been thinking at all in these terms. I'm just using the terms of your OP and showing where I see them logically leading. If I am oversimplifying, please correct me when you see it.

    There is nothing implicit about it though. For something to be permissible, there is an implication that something is not permissible. Does that mean that not eating a sandwich implicitly concedes it is impermissible?

    No, because not eating the sandwich could have implied one finds it morally permissible not to eat it. Whereas, eating it immediately implies that it is permissible to do so—it wouldn’t make sense if it implied they thought it was impermissible.

    Also, I don’t why it would be the case that “for something to be permissible, there is an implication that something is not permissible”, unless you mean that X being morally permissible entails that it is morally impermissible for X to not be morally permissible? But, then, I don’t see your point.
    Bob Ross

    Ok, I've been wracking my brain trying to understand how you're arriving at this conclusion, and this is the best I can come up with. So are you stating that because you think morality is based on our own psychology, whatever we do we must view as permissible? Because the logical equivalent is that whatever we do not do, is not permissible. Which means if at a future date, we decide not to eat a sandwich, not eating is permissible, while eating it is impermissible. The only way this binary does not exist is if there are actions that are not permissible nor impermissible. In which case, we cannot say that everything we do or do not do is permissible or impermissible. In which case, your claim that whatever we do is permissible doesn't work.

    If permissible is synonymous with 'our actions', then why not just say, 'our actions'? We have to be very careful when we redefine words in philosophy, a thing I struggle with as well. The reality is, we all want a particular outcome. Sometimes we like the emotional intention of the original words, but want to change the underlying meaning. This is because the original meaning contradicts with the outcome we want with words. But when we change the original meaning of the words and try to use the original emotional intention, that can result in flawed philosophy. Its as logical a fallacy as any other.

    The original intention of 'permissible' is what should or should not be done, but also assumes that someone can make an action that is impermissible, or not take an action on what is permissible. The emotional intention is a strong law that should be enforced. But all you're doing is taking the first portion of the word and throwing away the second part. But without the second part, what separate 'permissible' from moral? In which case, why not just use the word 'moral'?

    I feel like your overall point is simple, but its bogged down at points by redefinitions and unnecessary labor. I get it. When I first wrote my knowledge paper years ago it was just like this. It was an over 200 page monster saddled with ideas, definitions, redefinitions, and thoughts that ultimately were unnecessary for the overall point. Its the nature of creating something unique and interesting. Few people understand the amount of thinking, labor, rewriting, etc. that lead to a succinct and solid idea. It is a compliment to your creativity and thinking, please don't take my attempts to simplify the points as trying to overcome your intent. I'm simply trying to cut what I see as fat to get to the meat. Where I oversimplify, please add why and how I can fix it.

    That’s not the point of moral non-nihilism: it is the position that there are true moral judgments—i.e., they are not all false. Error theorists, i.e., moral nihilists, claim that moral judgments are truth-apt and express something objective but they are all false.Bob Ross

    Which is fine. Once again, we can more simply state, "Moral non-nihilism claims there is an objective morality." "Moral nihilists claim there is no objective morality". The excessive truth-apt true, false is just unnecessary wording that hinders the point. And yes, we understand that the morality as they know it is subjective in your terms, because anything we say, do, feel, etc is subjective.

    If truth is objective, then yes, true moral judgements are not subjective.

    No and yes. Truth being objective just means that the correspondence exists mind-independently, but to say that moral judgments express something objective does not follow from that.
    Bob Ross

    Yes. If you were making sure I understood this distinction, I do. So yes, if truth is objective, and there is a moral truth, then if a person's subjective claim to morality corresponds to this objectivity, it is a true moral judgement. This is as I've been intending. Because as I noted earlier Bob, everything we say, do, think, feel, etc. is subjective under your theory. So if I say, "true moral judgements are not subjective", this is of course a subjective statement. I am noting the thing in itself of the subjective judgement correlating with reality. Meaning the judgement as intended by the person is subjective, as everything is, but it so happens to correlate with the objective morality. This as well does not not that an objective morality exists.

    2. True moral judgments express something subjective [moral non-objectivism]
    I would tweak this once again to, "We can make subjective moral judgements that are true."

    You cannot do that validly: they are two different claims. The moral judgment is subjective and it expresses something subjective—i.e., judgments are always subjective because they are themselves an issuance by a subject and these particular judgments (moral ones) are true in virtue of projections of one’s pyschology and not some non-pyschological fact about reality.
    Bob Ross

    Once again, everything we ever do, say, judge, act, etc. is subjective. Which means that if my judgement corresponds with reality, then it is a true moral judgement. Which means we can make moral judgements which are true. Of course, since truth is objective, we can never know if our moral judgements are true, because what is objective can never be known as the thing in itself. Again, this is not me saying we have proven that an objective morality exists, only what must be entailed by a true moral judgement.

    You statement “we can make subjective moral judgments that are true” could be compatible with a moral realist’s claim that “moral judgments express something objective” just as much as a moral anti-realist’s claim that “moral judgments express something subjective”.Bob Ross

    Yes, this is the logical result of your vocabulary. If it is the case that a judgement (remember, no need to add subjective to this, everything we do is subjective) is concurrent with reality, this concurrence is objective and true. It doesn't mean we as subjects realize it is true. Objective truth is the reality of the situation as it is in itself. If a person has a judgement that is not concurrent with reality then there is no objective concurrence. There is only the subjects claim to what is moral while reality does not concur. So both sentences are right depending on the context and intent.

    Ah, I see with point one. To more accurately reflect this I would change
    1. Moral judgments are propositional [moral cognitivism]
    into
    1. True moral judgments are propositional [moral cognitivism]

    You cannot do that, because something being propositional does not entail that it is true, it entails that it has the capacity to be true or false.
    Bob Ross

    No Bob, I can. Just as I can logically say "False moral judgements are propositional". If something is true, then of course it has the capacity to be true or false. The capacity has nothing to do with whether it is true or false, only that by being true or false, there is the binary option of it being the other. If I use a proposition and state, "This proposition is true", it still has the capacity to be false in a logic set up. Typically this is done to set up logical fallacies or proof by contradiction.

    I am quite literally arguing that there are no moral states-of-affairs that exist mind-independently: “there are no moral phenomena, just moral interpretations of phenomena” as nietzsche put it.Bob Ross

    Ok, so you don't believe there's an objective morality, nor any true moral judgements. If morality does not exist mind independently, then any judgement to should or should will correlate with this lack of objectivity. Thus it would be true that there is no objective morality. Now all you have to do is prove it.

    Problem is, you can't with your current evidence.

    1. If there is not an objective morality, it means all possible claims of what should or should not happen,
    even contradictory claims, correlate with reality.
    2. Point 1 can be proven in two ways.
    a. Explore all possible moral judgements and conclude they correlate with reality, including
    contradictory psychological judgements.
    b. Demonstrate why a moral judgement can never be contradicted by reality (Contradiction is an
    opposition of opposite of correlation)
    2. You claim our psychology is the basis for morality through your psychology.
    3. I claim our psychology is not the basis for morality through my psychology.
    4. This is a contradiction in reality.
    5. Therefore neither of us can state morality is not objective until this contradiction is solved.
    6. To solve this requires evidence to be presented to ascertain that either point 2 or point 3 is correct.
    7. But, if point 2 is correct, then point 3 also stands, as my psychology can claim point 2 is wrong, and
    you'll have to agree with me if point 2 is right.
    Therefore if point 3 stands while point 2 stands, there is a contradiction. Therefore by point 6, point 2 is false.

    But even knowledge cannot know truth, as truth is an objective thing in itself.

    I would say that truth is not a thing-in-itself, because things-in-themselves are objects. This is why I find it hard to say truth is objective but also that truth isn’t. There isn’t a object, abstract or not, that exists which is the correspondence of thought with reality. The mere relationship between thought and reality such that they correspond is what truth is, and this can be acquired from a subjective viewpoint so long as that subject agrees that there are objects. They don’t come to know truth itself like an object that they observe, it is the abstract relationship between thinking and being: between mind and not mind.
    Bob Ross

    Yes, I understand but disagree with one statement. The "thing in itself" does not refer to an object. An object is a subjective attempt at understanding what a 'thing in itself is'. Our thoughts are 'things in themselves'. Their intentions, judgements, etc. about other things in themselves. When our intentions about other things are expressed and they correlate with reality, then they are true. Of course, this does not mean we know they are true. How we would know they are true would be subjective. But the subject does not need to have the knowledge or idea of objects, thoughts, etc, only an existence, judgement, etc that is correlating with reality.

    Thus, if I claimed, "I believe I should do this," the fact that you believed that you should do this correlates with reality and is true. Everything is self-referential, therefore true. But if you claim, "I believe you should do this," it is uncertain whether this correlates with reality and is a true moral judgement."

    Ok, that's a big chunk for you Bob! I know its busy because its Christmas season, so happy holidays if I don't hear from you before then!
  • A Measurable Morality
    Great! I've really wanted to bounce this idea off of someone else for some time. Whether it works or not, this will be fun.

    2. If something 'should' be, there is a reason for it.

    Three things:

    1. If someone claims that ‘there should be <...>’ and that it is just an upshot of their emotions, then they have no reason for it. What is incoherent with that under your view?
    Bob Ross

    I would say that's a reason. "I should help the world because I feel like it" is a reason. The point is I could then ask, "Why should your feelings matter?" In other words, asking the reason behind the reason.

    2. The chain of reasons has to stop somewhere, so the very foundational reason will have no reason; and that foundational reason may very well be a claim like ‘because there should be <...>’. In fact, this gets your point 12 in a lot of trouble:Bob Ross

    Yes, it does have to stop somewhere. But a reason does not have to have a prior reason. I'm saying the ultimate reason is, "It is". This is by necessity as there is nothing prior, nor nothing to negate 'what is'.

    3. This seems incoherent with point 12. You say, on one hand, that every claim of ‘something should be’ has a reason underpinning and then claim in 12 that ‘existing should be’ is valid yet has not reason underpinning it: “Existence is, and has no prior reason for being besides the fact that it is. As such, it is the foundational good. It is the prime reason behind all questions of what should be.”--but ‘existing should be’ is the foundational claim of your theory, and it has no reason for it because allegedly existence doesn’t have a prior reason for it.Bob Ross

    You would be absolutely correct if all reasons had an underlying reason. I'm noting that we reach a point in which there is no underlying reason, but a foundation. Recall we are assuming morality exists. So if this is the case, and we've reached a foundation, that is what we build upon.

    4. All chain of reasoning reduces down to the final question, "Should existence be, or not"?

    I don’t see why this is the case. Moral realists can just have to ground the normative claim in a moral fact. For example, I could say that ‘I should not eat children’ is true because there is a Platonic Form that dictates such and that would be the end of the chain of reasoning. I don’t need to further ask “why exist?” to ground why “I should not eat children” if it is made true by a moral fact. This is unnecessary.
    Bob Ross

    I could just as easily say, "I should eat children because God tells me to." A claim does not make it so. But you make a good point in the fact I have not explicitly stated a "true reason". If morality is true, then the reasoning behind morality must also be true. Meaning we can make claims of reason, but we must demonstrate why they must be.

    So in your example of Plato's forms, I could say, "What's the proof behind Plato's forms?" But lets say that it is true. Plato's forms DO exist. I then would ask, "Why should Plato's forms exist?" Do you see the chain now?

    We're asking why it should be beyond our own opinions. We're looking for the calculus of the universe.

    This is exactly the problem with assuming moral realism without explaining it: what calculus of the universe determines what is morally right or wrong? You seem to think it is “to be or not to be, that is the question”...but what makes this a calculus of the universe and not just a human existential question? The way gravity behaves is clearly rules or laws in the universe, but asking “to be or not to be?” does not seem (by my lights) to have an analogous correlate.
    Bob Ross

    Because we're doing a test. We're saying, "If morality, or what 'should' be is apart from humanity, what logically would that be? We must first define it, only then can we apply it. To say that morality exists apart from human opinion but leave it without what that would entail means we don't know what we're talking about.

    8. There can be no reason to explain why nothing should be, as there is 'no reason' if there is nothing.

    This is a non-sequitur: the reason can exist and be true that nothing should exist. The fact that the reason must exist has nothing to do with whether or not that reason is valid such that nothing should exist.
    Bob Ross

    No, this is not a non-sequitur at all. Your statement "The reason can exist and be true that nothing should exist" leads to a contradiction Bob. Think about it carefully.

    A. There exists a reason that nothing should exist.
    B. If that is the case, then the reason that nothing should exist, should not exist.
    Therefore, there should not exist a reason that justifies non-existence.

    Logically, that means that there should exist a reason that something should exist.

    Alright! This is what I wanted to discuss. Poke at it to your hearts content!
  • A Case for Moral Subjectivism
    I thought I understood what you meant by objective and subjective, so let me clarify it as I've understood it from our past conversations. I assumed that what was 'mind-independent' was essentially the thing in itself. We had spoken about that and I agreed with you that know one can know what the thing in itself is, it can only represent it within its mind. This is what I thought you meant by 'mind-dependent'.

    This seems to fit as you revise truth to be objective. As I understood it it would be when a person has a representation of a thing in itself that happens to correspond with the thing in itself. This correspondence is not mind-dependent, as it is not the mind trying to represent the correspondence. The correspondence is a thing in itself.

    If I had the above correct, there is nothing objective we can ever reference with any clarity besides, "the thing in itself" But:

    You cannot come to know something objective according to your terminology. Objectivity is mind independent. Meaning that its existence is what is without any mind ever attempting to correspond to it.

    I disagree. We come to know what is objective through reasoning and observance. We intuit that there is stuff which exists without us trying to think about them and that is what is objective.
    Bob Ross

    But we can't if I understood it correctly. Reasoning and observance are all subjective representations of the world. What we can conclude are reasoning and observance that seem to correspond with the thing in itself. An active representation of this could be called 'knowledge'. But even knowledge cannot know truth, as truth is an objective thing in itself. We can only at best, represent it correct? Meaning intuition is subjective. The only thing we can know about objectivity through our subjective reasoning, is that we can never know what the thing in itself is.

    Once any attempt at correspondence is made, it is now subjective, or mind dependent

    No. The claim or statement is trying to express something objective. Of course, we only approach the limit of what objectively is out there; but that doesn’t mean that it doesn’t exist nor that we don’t have good reasons to believe it does
    Bob Ross

    I agree that we approach the limit of what is objective, or mind-independent by basically using 'lack'. A thing in itself is the thing that we attempt to identify, but it is defined by the fact that it is always a representation and never an actual understanding of what it is in itself.

    "An object exists independently and we can come to know that object truthfully".

    This just begs the question by invoking “truthfully”; as truth is the correspondence of thought (subjectivity) with reality (objectivity).
    Bob Ross

    I wouldn't say its begging the question. We can also take correspondence of thought and not know it truthfully. For example, we may believe that a particular apple is healthy, but we're unaware that there is a small rotten piece inside that contains nasty bacteria. We only know when we don't correspond to reality when it demonstrates our correspondence doesn't work. But to know a correspondence doesn't work, that correspondence must be tested. We have plenty of things we subjectively know and believe that are not true, we simply haven't put it to the test yet or misinterpreted the results.

    Likewise, a ‘fact’ is a ‘statement which is true’ or, more precisely, ‘a statement which is truth-apt (i.e., a proposition) which corresponds appropriately with reality’. — Bob Ross

    Therefore, we can refine P2 to mean:
    Moral facts are judgements that a particular state of reality is preferable over another possible state of reality, and that these judgements are true.

    Moral facticity is not just what you described there. If a fact is a statement that corresponds to reality such that what it purports thereof is and ‘moral’ language signifies ‘what is permissible, omissible, or obligatory’, then a moral fact is a statement which accurately purports a state-of-affairs about reality that in virtue of which makes the moral judgment true (and thusly a fact). This means that there are states-of-affairs, if there are moral facts, that do inform us how reality ought to be, which violates P1.
    Bob Ross

    But Bob, if something is permissable, omissable, or obligatory, then this can be simplified to what 'should' or 'should not' be. Within the language that implies states of affairs. Morality is about comparing states of affairs and deciding which one is permissable, omissable, or obligatory. If you eliminate states of affairs, or make "reality" the combined set of all states of affairs, then you ALSO eliminate morality. To state something moral is by definition to state, "Reality in this state is better than in this state."

    If P1 does not address states of reality, then you cannot have morality. Your true P2 should be "Morality is the claim that reality in one state is permissable, omissable, or obligatory over comparative states of reality". While P1 can indicate that any particular state alone cannot demonstrate morality, it doesn't negate the fact that morality is an act of comparison. If you cannot compare, you have no morality.

    A potential state of reality in the sense of what could possibly happen due to the current state does not inform us of what ought to be either. You could tell me “this ball will probably hit this other ball” and I would not know from that claim anything normative, although I would know something about the next potential state of reality.Bob Ross

    That's simply untrue. As soon as you compare states of reality you have a moral choice. That's the only way something is permissable. To be permissable it must be the case that we can change the state to something else that is not permissable.

    If for example a baby is about to get shot, you have time to decide what the future reality will be. You could shoot the shooter first. Step in front of the baby. Dive Hollywoodesque in slow motion to move the baby out of the way. These choices come about because we have in our head at a minimum two outcomes. Dead baby or living baby in a future state of reality. What is permissable? We only know this by comparing the two outcomes.

    If I was a being that was born into a reality without time where a baby lay dead, then yes, this slice of reality alone cannot tell me what is morally permissable. In this only, I completely agree with P1. It is only after experiencing multiple states of reality and comparing them can we come to conclusion that some states of reality 'should' exist over others. Morality does not exist in a stateless non-comparative state. It only exists in a stateful comparison analysis.

    Lets translate this into simpler terms:
    1. Moral judgements are made by subjects (minds)
    2. Moral judgements are expressions of subjects.
    3. At least one moral judgement corresponds with reality.

    #1 here is not a summary of prong-1 (of the thesis). Prong-1 is moral cognitivism, which is the view that moral judgments are truth-apt statements (i.e., propositions) and not that moral judgments are made by subjects.

    #2 is also false. Moral judgments expressing something subjective is not the same thing as judgments being expressions of subjects. Again, this is a conflation between statements and judgments being subjective and whether or not they express something objective/subjective.

    #3 True! (:
    Bob Ross

    Ah, I see with point one. To more accurately reflect this I would change
    1. Moral judgments are propositional [moral cognitivism]
    into
    1. True moral judgments are propositional [moral cognitivism]

    This would then follow with:

    2. True moral judgments express something subjective [moral non-objectivism]
    I would tweak this once again to, "We can make subjective moral judgements that are true."

    #2 is also false. Moral judgments expressing something subjective is not the same thing as judgments being expressions of subjects. Again, this is a conflation between statements and judgments being subjective and whether or not they express something objective/subjective.Bob Ross

    If truth is objective, then yes, true moral judgements are not subjective. We of course cannot know if they are true because we cannot, as subjects, know what is objective. It is a correspondence that happens despite our beliefs or observations as what is objective is completely independent from minds (subjects). The tweak I made I think makes this more clear.

    3. There is at least one true moral judgment [moral non-nihilism].

    Taken as a thesis and not a proof, this is fine. This still does not negate that there is not really anything meaningful stated here. Replace, 'true moral judgements' with 'true statements' and its still the same thing. So my criticism of this lacking any meaningful weight still holds for me.

    As we can see, all this argument notes is that we can think say or do things, and maybe they correspond with reality. This indicates nothing that should be done.

    It indicates what moral properties subsist in or of and what their nature is. Of course it doesn’t indicate what should be done, because it isn’t a normative ethical theory. That’s what I was trying to convey in the other thread! Metaethical theories should not be conflated with normative theories!
    Bob Ross

    Lets simplify this further. You set up some definitions and propositional assumptions without a conclusion. That's not a normative theory. A theory has a conclusion with proof. No one cares about normative or metaethical as concepts except scholars with too much time on their hands. Did you come up with a theory of morality that is meaningful and useful to others? That's all that matters. It is a trap in philosophy I've seen many brilliant people fall into over the years. To focus on terminology and miss the one true point: usefulness and applicability. Take my advice here as an equal: eliminate any words or phrases that does not make your arguments as simple and clear as possible. Use George Orwells six points of writing. It is an ongoing battle for myself as well, but it is the way to make clear and meaningful arguments. An insistence on a normative and metaethical separation is missing the trees in the forest. You didn't do anything meaningful in your setup.

    But if there are no true moral judgements, then we don't have to consider that there is anything morally permissible. There is nothing to permit or deny. Meaning my objection still holds.

    I think you are trying to step outside of morality, but I say that action implicitly concedes that morality exists. You cannot go and eat a sandwich without implicitly, in action, conceding it is morally permissible to do. You can say “morality doesn’t exist”, but your actions do not match your words.
    Bob Ross

    There is nothing implicit about it though. For something to be permissible, there is an implication that something is not permissible. Does that mean that not eating a sandwich implicitly concedes it is impermissible? Action simply implies something has been done. The question of whether that action should have been committed or not is morality. If you state that all actions are permissible, then no actions are impermissible. In which case, there is no question of how we should act, and thus no morality.

    Depends on what you mean. It certainly answers what the nature of morality is and what moral properties subsist in or of and answers various metatethical concerns underpinning normative ethics.Bob Ross

    I don't see that at all. Basically what you've done is set up basic definitions.

    1. There is truth, definitions of objective, subjective.
    2. We are subjects. What we say, do, think, comprehend, etc is subjective.
    3. What is objective is mind-independent. Truth is mind-independent, therefore objective.
    4. Morality is what is permissible. You have not given a clear example of what is permissible with any proof. Only that we can make moral judgements, and if they correspond with reality, or what is objective, its true.
    4. Because we are subjects, morality is subjective.
    5. Except that this is true for any statement, word, or concept in existence because of the way you've defined subjective. Making this statement meaningless and getting us no where closer to understanding or solving the question of morality.

    No. Moral cognitivism is that moral judgments are statements that are truth-apt. Whether or not any of them are true needs a different argument because it is a different claim.Bob Ross

    Again, I can replace 'Moral cognitivism' with any phrase I want. "Claims about dogs are statements that are truth-apt." Any statement is truth-apt Bob. If you claim there is truth, and that statements which are true are those that correspond with reality, that's all you need. If its true, its 1+1=2. We don't call it "Cognitive number theory vs non-cognitive number theory". We call it math.

    I only say this because I think you're brilliant Bob. I do not mean to say this as talking down to you, but with great respect as I see your amazing potential. Yes, we must understand the names to be successful in the philosophical world. I understand. But don't get caught up in naming math. DO math. Because you can while so many can't. Let them worry about naming it. While I disagree with your repurposing of subjective and objective for the reason's I've given, the underlying concept as I've understood it from your previous writings makes sense. That's the math. Math is what changes the world and allows humanity to achieve great things. I don't care what you call it. Neither should you.
  • A Measurable Morality
    With all due respect, you are though! It doesn’t matter what terms you call them. At the end of the day you are claiming that “morality is objective” without providing any justification for it; or the justification you have given doesn’t prove it is objectiveBob Ross

    It is perfectly fine that what I describe fits normative and metaethical within your head. I do this often in philosophy, translating terminology into my own, but then translating it back out into the language of the speaker where I can. I do not want to have a debate about what normative and metaethical are. As I've mentioned in prior discussions, I find words like this often unintentionally hide clarity, especially when they are introduced by someone else. First lets see if you understand the terms as given, then lets see if more vocabulary or other ethical theories are needed for comparison.

    But I'm glad we can just agree to get to the point because I want to have some fun thinking about something new Bob! Let me repost the argument once more so we can continue. I'll flesh out points I think you had some questions about.

    1. Good is what "should" be.
    2. If something 'should' be, there is a reason for it.
    3. If there is a reason for something, that reason may also have a reason for why it 'should' be.
    4. All chain of reasoning reduces down to the final question, "Should existence be, or not"?
    5. As this is a binary, only one can be correct.

    Note on 4: You seemed to imply that number 4 wasn't a given. I'll walk through it.

    Lets say I say, "I should help a person in need." Why? "Because I want to alleviate their suffering." Why? "Because suffering is bad." Why? I could go on like this for some time, but at one point there will be the question, "Why should they exist?" We can give a lot of human reasons why they should exist, but this again will drill down into, "Why should humanity exist?" We can give the reason, "We like existing," but we're not asking a personal opinion.

    We're asking why it should be beyond our own opinions. We're looking for the calculus of the universe. Gravity does not need our opinions, it is a measurable and repeatable event. Same with the question of morality. What measurable and repeatable event can demonstrate that humanity should exist? The question of 'should' is not a human one. It is an existential one.

    Of course, this then leads into the question, "Why should a calculus exist? Why should there be anything measurable?" Whatever the answer there, we finally get into the prime question, "Why should anything exist?" To simplify this further, we get down to the idea of an Aristotelian atomic existence versus the idea of complete nothingness. Should there be something, or nothing? At this point, there is no other reducible option, nothing prior to reference. For without answering this question first, no other 'should' question has an answer. It is the base to build the house, the floor for our legos. :)

    With that, I attempt the next set.

    6. Attempt to claim that 'nothing' is what should be.
    7. If it were the case that nothing should be, and it were possible to find a reason, this reason must exist.
    (I'll rewrite the above to be clearer, but kept the original for reference)
    7 Revised: If it were the case that nothing should be, there must be a reason.
    8. There can be no reason to explain why nothing should be, as there is 'no reason' if there is nothing.
    9. Therefore it is not possible to claim that it is good for nothing to exist through any reason. This leaves the binary that existence is what should be.
    Philosophim

    I did note that this binary only exists if morality exists at an existential level. If of course morality does not exist at this level, this binary does not exist. For our purposes, we're going to assume morality exists. As well, just because we've proven one side of the binary false, it does not mean we haven't shown that the other side of the binary is not also false.

    9. Attempt to claim that 'something' is what should be.
    10. If it is the case that existence should be, there needs to be a reason behind it.
    11. For there to be a reason, there must be existence.
    12. Existence is, and has no prior reason for being besides the fact that it is. As such, it is the foundational good. It is the prime reason behind all questions of what should be. It is the prime reason upon which all other moral questions are built upon.
    13. Thus, "Should existence be?" The answer is yes. If it is not, then nothing should be and there is no morality. But this leads to a contradiction.
    Philosophim

    I'll let you take it from there Bob. Keep the vocabulary simple. Do not introduce other moral theories. Even remove the idea of objective and subjective if it helps. Simply take the terms as given and see if the conclusions hold water.
  • A Case for Moral Subjectivism
    After reading I think this all comes down to the terms subjective and objective. Now that I've seen your definition, its necessary they be included in your 'pre-requisites' section

    This is already in the OP under ‘Brief Exposition of a Correspondence Theory of Truth’, which, I would say, is where it should be:
    Bob Ross

    My apologies! I reskimmed and missed it. Your argument is dense, so I did not retain it after I had finished reading your OP the first time. That's on me. :)

    You are saying the same thing I am saying, but less refined. I say there is no such thing as an objective statement because all statements are subjective, you are merely predicating that subjective statement with ‘objective’ if it is true in virtue of corresponding to some mind-independently existing state-of-affairs.Bob Ross

    If you wish to define subjective this way, that's fine. But if this is true, what's the point of the word? If all statements are subjective, why not just say "statement"? "Subjective statement" is redundant at that point as there is no contrast. The term subjective is only uniquely useful in contrast with an "objective statement". If you eliminate the vocabulary of objective statement, then you may as well eliminate the term "subjective statement" as well.

    Finally, the elimination of these terms does not eliminate the original concepts they embodied. There is still the question of making a statement in regards to utilizing only your personal viewpoint, or making a statement that can be logically agreed upon by all potential viewpoints. But if this is your choice, that is fine. I'll re-examine your argument using what you've provided.

    ‘trueness’ is the property ascribed to statements of which what they allege of (refer to about) reality correspond/agree with reality with respect to that specific regardBob Ross

    What you've done here is make trueness subjective. I did read your other post, and your conclusion that truth is a merge of the two doesn't fit. Either something is mind independent, or mind dependent. This is the clear binary you've created. A statement is mind-dependent. I see your intention is to say, "I'm taking this objective thing, having a subjective stance about this objective thing, and if the two correspond, this is true." Really, this is the same as saying you take an object and subjectively identify it in a way that corresponds with reality. I have no issue with this. But to say that it is neither objective nor subjective is false. To be mind independent is to be free of any mind. To be mind dependent is to have at least an iota of mind in there. :) It is still mind dependent, as without a mind, you cannot make a true statement.

    A statement from a mind that is true = Subjective
    A statement from a mind that is false = Subjective

    I have no problem with this as long as the definitions are consistent and logically flow. This is again the problem of 'everything is now subjective' and it devalues any meaning to the term. I'm addressing this now as it will become relevant soon.

    Addressing P1: The way reality is does not entail how it ought to be.
    (Me) In very simple terms, this doesn't work because you forgot the possibility of different states of reality.

    (You) I don’t think comparing potential states of affairs (of reality) helps get around P1. P1 is the claim that it doesn’t matter what is the case about reality at all when it comes to what ought to be: what ought to be is despite what is.
    Bob Ross

    If the intention is, "What ought to be is despite what is", I agree. This assumes that what is could be something different, which is a core consideration of a moral statement.

    I would just say that objectivity is that which exists mind(stance)-independently and we come to know it subjectively because we are subjects—what tool can we use that isn’t ultimately contingent on us observing it?Bob Ross

    You cannot come to know something objective according to your terminology. Objectivity is mind independent. Meaning that its existence is what is without any mind ever attempting to correspond to it. Once any attempt at correspondence is made, it is now subjective, or mind dependent. You can say 'an object' exists independently, and we can come to know that object subjectively. Again, since subjectivity is simply the act of a mind, or a subject, trying to know the object, we can eliminate the word subjectivity and simply state "An object exists independently and we can come to know that object truthfully". Nothing is lost by removing the term subjectivity when it is a redundant term.

    I read the rest of your comments and think I understand what you are going for now, so I'll restart from my original critique again. As always, please correct me when I'm off!

    P1: The way reality is does not entail how it ought to be.
    P2: Moral facts are statements about how reality is such that it informs us how it ought to be.
    C: Therefore, moral facts cannot exist.
    Bob Ross

    Now that I believe I much better understand your approach to subjectivity, I do not understand how you arrived at your conclusion here.

    P1 is fine with the clarification that it means "What ought to be is despite what is". This implicitly includes states. For example, reality now vs reality one minute later. There is nothing within the current state explicitly which states it should be some other state. That is for us to judge when comparing this state with another possible state.
    P2 is also fine. But lets clarify what you stated in your own terminology.

    (
    Likewise, a ‘fact’ is a ‘statement which is true’ or, more precisely, ‘a statement which is truth-apt (i.e., a proposition) which corresponds appropriately with reality’.Bob Ross

    Therefore, we can refine P2 to mean:
    Moral facts are judgements that a particular state of reality is preferable over another possible state of reality, and that these judgements are true.

    These two statements alone do not lead to your conclusion that moral facts cannot exist. We're missing some steps! All you've done is create definitions. These definitions do not lead to this conclusion. P1 does not lead to any conclusions about P2. You would need to prove that P2 is false before you reached your conclusion. As is, P2 is merely a definition without an assertion of its truth or falsity.

    If I had to guess what you were originally going for, I think you were neglecting potential states as part of the moral consideration and simply noting that reality at any time/state could not indicate what it should be in the next state. I understand the intention this way, but it doesn't work because morality does not only consider the current state of reality.

    But perhaps the above is irrelevant if we look at your next argument.

    1. Moral judgments are propositional [moral cognitivism]; and
    2. Moral judgments express something subjective [moral non-objectivism]; and
    3. There is at least one true moral judgment [moral non-nihilism].
    Bob Ross

    Lets translate this into simpler terms:

    1. Moral judgements are made by subjects (minds)
    2. Moral judgements are expressions of subjects.
    3. At least one moral judgement corresponds with reality.

    The problem is this isn't anything meaningful. I can replace "moral judgements" with the word statements, and statements meaning "Any thought, word, belief, or expression".

    1. Statements are made by subjects
    2. Statements are expressions of subjects.
    3. At least one statement corresponds with reality.

    Of course, we haven't actually proved number 3 with our setup. The only real conclusion we can make is:
    "Either at least one statement is true, or none are true."

    I believe you prove that at least one statement is true if you amend the language of the subject to be self-referential, which is fine.

    As we can see, all this argument notes is that we can think say or do things, and maybe they correspond with reality. This indicates nothing that should be done. It does not address states of reality as they should be. It does not indicate any criteria as to what defines morality. Is what "should" be done central to the individual, or is there something universal we can all agree on with logic? This is again a problem when you reduce "subjective" to meaning, "Any statement by a subject".

    As a comparison with my knowledge theory, if you recall I noted that all knowledge starts with a discrete experience. Which means that all knowledge, language, etc. comes from an experiencer, or a subject. I did not belabor that point. Its very quickly addressed and moved on from because its just a starting point to fix problems from. The idea that you need a subject to think or say anything is a given. The idea that subjects are what consider any moral question is also a given. What can we logically conclude about morality from that starting point? Is there a logic that we must all rationally agree upon which leads to a morality everyone can logically ascertain? Or is morality simply what each individual wants, an expressed desire for singular or cultural ego?

    Let me address the remaining points where relevant.

    Moral cognitivism is the metaethical position that moral judgments are truth-apt
    P1: If moral non-cognitivism is true, then ‘If I [believe I] ought not drive drunk, then when I am drunk I should call a taxi’ is not a logically valid and intelligible conditional statement.

    P2: ‘If I [believe I] ought not drive drunk, then when I am drunk I should call a taxi’ is a logically valid and intelligible conditional statement.

    C: Therefore, moral non-cognitivism is false.
    Bob Ross

    Let me break this down further:

    1. Moral cognitivism is the idea that there are true moral judgments
    2. Assume moral cognitivism is false, that there are no moral judgements which are true.
    3. I have the moral statement: "When I am drunk, I shouldn't drive and instead call a taxi."
    4. Holding to point 2, this moral judgement is not true.
    5. But point 3 is true.
    C: Therefore moral cognitivism is true.

    The problem is point 5 has not been proven to be true. A logically valid and intelligible conditional statement may very well not be true. What is true is a correlation with reality. A logically valid and intelligible conditional has not been proven to always be true.

    But, you then attempt to prove that there is at least one moral judgement that is true. And if that is the case we can replace point 3 with that true statement and the argument will work.

    P1: If there are no true moral judgments, then one would have to ‘lie down and starve to death’.

    P2: People do not ‘lie down and starve to death’.

    C: Therefore, some moral judgments must be true.
    Bob Ross

    Here was my original statement and your reply.

    P1: If there are no true moral judgments, then one would have to ‘lie down and starve to death’. — Bob Ross

    (Me)This statement is a contradiction. If there are no moral judgements, then there is nothing one has to do. Therefore one would not have to 'lie down and starve to death'.

    (You) Not quite. I was claiming that doing something entails at a minimum the concession that it is morally permissible; so if one can’t even agree that it is permissible to do X, then they can’t do X because they don’t affirm that it is permissible. I think you would have to contend with the collapse of morals into actions to say that one can do something even if they don’t find it morally permissible.
    Bob Ross

    But if there are no true moral judgements, then we don't have to consider that there is anything morally permissible. There is nothing to permit or deny. Meaning my objection still holds.

    Alright, a rather long one from me! I'm still off for the holidays so I have time on my hands. I'm enjoying the exploration Bob, keep at it!
  • A Measurable Morality
    Why P2 and P1 are true is irrelevant to my point, as I can grant those: this argument has no metaethical claims in it. I am almost certain now that you are conflating normative judgments with metaethical judgments.Bob Ross

    Bob, this has nothing to do with the argument. I'm not conflating anything. When the author is not using vocabulary that you then introduce, then you say the author is not meeting the standards of that vocabulary you have introduced, you are committing a straw man fallacy. I am not using metaethical or normative claims in the argument. If you want to see it that way in your own head, that's fine. From my viewpoint, its unnecessary vocabulary that is leading you to misunderstand the simplicity of the argument.

    I would say, if I accepted this as a moral subjectivist, that the shorthand ‘something should be’ and ‘nothing should be’ are both moral statements which express something subjective and when evaluated relative to myself I do believe that ‘something should be’ and do not believe ‘nothing should be’.Bob Ross

    Yes, and there is nothing wrong with that. For the clarity of the conversation, lets us also understand 'subjective' in the normative view, not your own interpretation. Meaning a subjective moralist would be one who believes that what is moral is based on one's personal benefit, or even collective subjective culture. But then I would ask, "Why should someone's personal benefit matter?" This leads to: "Why should humans even exist?" And finally we arrive once again to, "Why should anything exist?" All claims of morality lead to this ultimate question Bob. It is the eternal "Why" from a child until we finally get to the point where there is nothing prior. :)

    Even going down the chain to its ultimate point, you'll also notice I added a very subjective viewpoint as an option in my last post. "Does morality exist?" You can decide it doesn't. This leads to consequences however that I don't think anyone truly believes in. I suppose the real question is, "Does objective morality exist?" If you say no, then of course we're left with either subjective morality or existential nihilism. The argument is not proving that objective morality exists. Its simply proving that all moral questions boil down to this binary, and proving what objective morality must be if it does exist. Lets make sure we're on the right page of for 'objective' as well. We're using the normative definition. To simplify, objective means that any human using logic and deductive evidence must come to the same conclusion regardless of their individual viewpoint of the world. Subjective and objective claims are all things a subject makes, not an object. The word 'object' has nothing to do with them.

    To enter the discussion, you do not have to agree that objective morality exists, you simply have to assume it does. If it does, what logically would it be, and how would it build? So going forward in this discussion, simply assume objective morality exists. We really can't continue to discuss until that happens. Don't worry, it doesn't mean you agree with it personally, we're just exploring the logical consequences if this is the case.

    Avoiding contradictions, as a normative judgment, is not necessarily a judgment that expresses something objective. For example, by contrast to my view, I accept that ‘one ought to abide by the law of noncontradiction’ but I reject that that judgment is expressing something objective.Bob Ross

    First, lets remove 'normative judgements'. I'm not using that vocabulary in my post. My argument is that within a binary argument in which one option must be false while the other is true, proving one option as false necessarily makes the other true. If an objective morality exists, then this is the binary we are left with.

    You have to provide an argument for why I should accept not ‘there should be existence’ but that that moral judgment is expressing something objective.Bob Ross

    And this sums up why we're having difficulty. My point here is not to argue that there is an objective morality or argue against a subjective morality. Its taking an objective morality as assumed, then logically piecing together what that would be if true. Go with that and I think we'll have some fun exploring this Bob.

    This is too vague: what do you mean by ‘morality exists’? That there is at least one true moral judgment? That moral judgments are propositional? That they express something objective?Bob Ross

    That there is an objective measure of what should be.

    I had concluded this long ago, and it suddenly came back to me. This is 'the choice'. Do you decide that morality exists, or not? If not, then we are done

    This seems like your argument collapsed into moral non-objectivism
    Bob Ross

    Its a little more than that. It is a choice between moral nihilism and moral objectivity. I believe that subjective morality also descends into moral nihilism, but lets not have that discussion here. I think we're having that discussion in another of your threads. To keep the discussion on track here, we'll just use the assumption of, "What if there was an objective morality? What would that logically look like?"

    Alright, so assuming that there is an objective morality (It doesn't mean you agree!), lets look at the rest of the argument and see if it has any merit. Great points as well Bob. If we need to revisit at some point whether we need to see if a subjective morality can exist as a viable alternative, I will gladly revisit it. Its just out of the scope of the argument at this time and not what I really want to explore at this time.
  • A Case for Moral Subjectivism
    After reading I think this all comes down to the terms subjective and objective. Now that I've seen your definition, its necessary they be included in your 'pre-requisites' section. If you do not define them specifically, then people are going to assume they are the traditional definitions of subjective and objective. The argument won't go anywhere because they'll think you mean the normative terms, not your revisions.

    Can you clarify what the (stance) means as well?

    As is, your statements about subjective and objective veer wildly from their original intent. The terms objective and subjective generally refer to statements. Thus there is an objective statement and a subjective statement. When you state the term objective means "that which is mind independent", what is 'that'? Is it existence?

    Even further, this begs the question that your definition of subjective and objective are true. Why do we need to redefine these terms? Is it so you can use the word 'subjective', even though it would have nothing to do with the original meaning of the term subjective? This would be a widely misinterpreted argument to give to others if you've deviated strongly from the terms' original meaning without very carefully clarifying what you mean.

    If you mean to simply clarify the difference between an object and a subject, this can be done without changing the meaning of the original words. An object can make no objective or subjective judgements. Only a subject can. The reason we have the terms objective and subjective are to give meaning to the judgements a subject makes. When you make objective and subjective as 'not a subject' vs 'a subject' it just changes the entire meaning of the terms. If you want to make that argument, I would suggest making the argument with subjects and objects and not use the terms objective or subjective at all to ease confusion and clarify the argument.

    I'll wait for you to clarify the exact intent of your use of subjective and objective. Your argument may very well be correct if I understand the meaning behind your terminology. Once I understand, I'll re-examine your argument with that in mind and see if I reach some different conclusions.
  • A Measurable Morality
    Certainly, let me see if I can break it into a simple and clear logic statement Bob.

    1. Good is what "should" be.
    2. If something 'should' be, there is a reason for it.
    3. If there is a reason for something, that reason may also have a reason for why it 'should' be.
    4. All chain of reasoning reduces down to the final question, "Should existence be, or not"?
    5. As this is a binary, only one can be correct.

    6. Attempt to claim that 'nothing' is what should be.
    7. If it were the case that nothing should be, and it were possible to find a reason, this reason must exist.
    7. There can be no reason behind why nothing should be, as there is 'no reason' behind 'nothing'.
    8. Therefore it is not possible to claim that it is good for nothing to exist through any reason. This leaves the binary that existence is what should be.

    But, you may not be satisfied with this, as we need to examine the other binary.

    9. Attempt to claim that 'something' is what should be.
    10. If it is the case that existence should be, there needs to be a reason behind it.
    11. For there to be a reason, there must be existence.
    12. Existence is, and has no prior reason for being besides the fact that it is. As such, it is the foundational good. It is the prime reason behind all questions of what should be. It is the prime reason upon which all other moral questions are built upon.
    13. Thus, "Should existence be?" The answer is yes. If it is not, then nothing should be and there is no morality. But this leads to a contradiction. What should be for morality to exist? Existence.

    Now let me address your points to see if I can continue to clarify this.

    I would like to point out that the answer to this is subjective (by my lights) and if it isn’t then I would need to know how you know that moral properties subsist in something mind-independent and what that is.Bob Ross

    It is not subjective because it is necessary to avoid a contradiction in the question of morality, and necessary for morality to exist.

    1. It is entirely possible to affirm that ‘nothing should exist’ without presupposing that anything exists, and I am not sure why you think this is false. Saying ‘nothing should exist’ entails that there shouldn’t be anything, and this certainly does not presuppose anything existing.Bob Ross

    No, I am stating it is not possible to affirm that 'nothing should exist' without a reason existing. 'Nothing' cannot justify that existence should not be.

    Just because we cannot claim “nothing should exist” without accepting a contradiction it does not follow that there are any moral properties which are reducible to existence nor that any exist (mind-independently) at all.Bob Ross

    Yes, the moral property is, "There should be existence". Remember, the question is a binary. Should there, or should there not be existence?

    I don’t think this is good epistemology: if you have two exhaustive options, A and B, and A cannot be justified as true, then it is not justified thereby to affirm B as true. B needs support for why it should be regarded as true or A needs to be demonstrated as false.Bob Ross

    You are correct. I've been approaching this a binary with an implicit argument. But its really not. I'll make that explicit not. First, let us clarify that this is a question of total nothingness. Should there be at least one thing, or only nothing.

    A. Only nothing should be. - If this is true, then 'Something should not be'.
    B. Something should be - If this is true, then 'Only nothing should be' is false.

    Here's the implicit I am now making explicit because there is a second binary.

    A. Morality exists
    B. Morality does not exist

    If morality does not exist, then the original binary is irrelevant. Neither nothingness nor somethingness should exist. The first binary only has relevance with the implicit notion that "morality exists".

    So the question of "Should there exist at least something, or only nothing" implicitly has the assumption that morality exists. If we say, "Yes," then the foundational basis for morality is existence, because existence should exist for morality to be. But if the answer is no, then there is no morality.

    I had concluded this long ago, and it suddenly came back to me. This is 'the choice'. Do you decide that morality exists, or not? If not, then we are done. There is no justification for anything, including the existence of yourself. There is only existential nihilism. But of course, if you do not end yourself, then you are saying you 'should' exist. In which case you are claiming there is morality. In which case, the only logical foundational basis for this morality is that there should be existence.

    If however you do choose that morality exists, then logically, the only conclusion is that existence should be. For without existence, morality cannot exist.

    I'm glad for your pointed questions, as this had brought back an issue that needed to be addressed. Hopefully this clarifies the initial set up a bit more.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas
    what if you were thinking about opening a factory that you knew would kill 1,000 people a year from the pollution, do you think that’s permissible to do? Does it depend on how many people you think will be saved from whatever you are manufacturing?Bob Ross

    Yes, it does depend on how many people are saved, and a host of other factors. How many get sick? Does this sow distrust and chaos in society? There are a ton of factors.

    At the end of the day I'm weighing the life of one child vs the lives of every other human being on this planet. The benefit vs cost is overwhelming in the case of torturing the child. Now, if we could also have humanity live and not torture a child? Sure. Just like if we could get the benefits we do in producing things minus the pollution. Or be able to eat animals without enacting any suffering on them at all.

    Its not that we don't wish for a better situation, but the situation as given is the horrible outcome we must pick vs the even more horrible outcome of the elimination of the entire human race. This of course is all tantamount to "What is good?" Without an answer there, its just opinion vs opinion.
  • Are words more than their symbols?
    The multiple meanings of words suggests to me that people have suppled various meanings to the words rather than the word supplying various meanings to them.NOS4A2

    This is true. A word without any meaning is simply a noise. Once meaning is applied to a word, then communicated to others it becomes part of a shared language between the two. If this expands out, this can become part of the shared language of many people like slang. Eventually it can be recognized as a valid word with definitions as part of a full blown language.

    The context or “use” may hint at your intention, your meaning, but the meaning itself is not present in the word, context, or use itself.NOS4A2

    If context is the involvement of people's intentions, environment, culture and state of being, I'm not sure what's left after its elimination. Perhaps what you are intending is that a person's intention to use a word is not necessarily understood by another. Which is fine. There is the meaning as intended to be conveyed, the meaning as the other person accepts the conveyance, and the meaning as both understand and misunderstand each other.
  • Are some languages better than others?


    Lets approach this as an engineer would. What do you mean by "better"? Do we want a language to be terse or verbose? The former is easy to learn but lacks nuance, while the later is more difficult to learn but has more fine tuned expression.

    Should a language be strictly enforced or lax? The former creates a very strict and uncreative language while the later allows creative evolution.

    If you can clearly define what is better, then you can determine if there is a better language for those parameters. Of course, claiming something is better does not prove that it is better either. Just some things to consider before there can be a clear answer.
  • Are words more than their symbols?
    The basic question is this: are words more than their symbols?NOS4A2

    Absolutely. You do not need an inner monologue to conclude this. First, there are many words that have multiple meanings through definition alone.

    The word 'crane' can mean a bird, or it can mean a machine that you use to lift heavy objects. What this logically leads to is the meaning of the word is based on 'context'. Context is based on the environment, your previous words, and conveyed intentions. With context, we can take the word crane and use it for something it was never intended to, like a pun or a person's name.

    "Crane was so good at operation, it was is the crane flew."
  • A Digital Physics Argument for the existence of God
    First, I love original attempts at proof of God arguments! Well done. Lets see if it holds.

    1. Any simulation of a world either operates mechanically in physical space (e.g., in a computer) or is the result of information processing in a mind (e.g., a programmer’s mind).

    Can you clarify what simulation means? How does this contrast with reality? The idea of a simulation entails an emulation of what is real correct?

    For now, the only thing I can conclude is that you are currently claiming that "Our current reality is a simulation of the world."

    2. The success of digital physics and the holographic principle imply that physical space is an emergent 3D representation of information processing.

    So far you haven't declared what physical space is, we're assuming this is a simulation. That means we have to add an adjective for this statement to still be clear. "...imply that simulated physical space..."

    With this, you're still good.

    3. Quantum cognition and decision theory have shown that information processing in a mind exhibits quantum principles known to underlie the emergence of physical space.

    Once again, add "simulated physical space" because you have not yet declared what non-simulated space would be.

    4. From (2) and (3), the information processing from which physical space is emergent is scientifically indistinguishable from the information processing that occurs in a mind.

    As long as we retain "simulated physical space", this seems fine.

    5. Restating (1) in terms of (4), our world is either scientifically indistinguishable from the result of information processing in a mind, or it is the result of information processing in a mind.

    Finally we have to add, "our simulated world..." and this holds.

    6. Therefore, our world is the result of information processing in a mind, this mind we call God.[/quote]

    Finally you can state: "Therefore, our simulated world is the result of information processing in in a mind, this mind we call God."

    We can call it God if we want, but the mind could also be called a "human" or "computer". So, very cool idea, but as you can tell without first contrasting what a simulation is vs what a non-simulated world is, its mostly circular. I've done a couple of "Prove God" posts in my past if you're interested. https://thephilosophyforum.com/discussion/8924/a-fun-puzzle-for-the-forums-the-probability-of-god/p1
    https://thephilosophyforum.com/discussion/12098/a-first-cause-is-logically-necessary/p1
  • A Case for Moral Subjectivism
    Hello Bob, I'm happy to explore morality with you on multiple fronts here, as its a very deep topic and requires a lot of consideration from all possible sides. This is a good breakdown of your theory and seems very well written and clear. However, I see some issues with a few of the statements. Lets start at the top.

    First, I agree with your pre-requisite to Meta-ethics section! Its good grounds to start and needed for the discussion. If I were to say one thing, it is to go back and clearly define what you mean by objective and subjective as well. Onto the discussion!

    P1: The way reality is does not entail how it ought to be.
    P2: Moral facts are statements about how reality is such that it informs us how it ought to be.
    C: Therefore, moral facts cannot exist.
    Bob Ross

    In very simple terms, this doesn't work because you forgot the possibility of different states of reality. If we took a frozen snapshot of existence, or how things are, without any other comparisons; you would be correct. But if we have seen multiple states of existence, we can compare different states and claim, "That state of reality is superior to this state of reality."

    Lets flesh out your statement so that its conclusion can be true.

    P1: The way reality is at any moment, in isolation of any other consideration of other potential states of reality, does not entail how it ought to be.
    P2: Moral facts are statements about how reality is such that it informs us how it ought to be. This requires a consideration of states of reality in comparison to the current state of reality.
    C: Therefore, if we consider a state of reality in isolation of all other potential states of reality throughout time, moral facts cannot exist.

    And I would agree with this. But lets include other potential states of reality.

    P1: The way reality is at any moment, in isolation of any other consideration of other potential states of reality, does not entail how it ought to be.
    P2: But, if we include other potential states of reality, we can compare them to declare that one state is better over another.
    P3: Moral facts are statements about how reality is such that it informs us how it ought to be.
    C: We do not have the criteria yet for "what is better" so cannot determine at this time if it is objective or subjective.

    So I do not see the original conclusion: "Therefore, moral facts cannot exist." once you introduce comparative potential states of reality. Still, lets continue onto your argument for subjective morality, as the above argument is simply a clarification of what must be considered when addressing morality, and does not make any claims to whether moral claims are subjective or objective.

    1. Moral judgments are propositional [moral cognitivism]; and
    2. Moral judgments express something subjective [moral non-objectivism]; and
    3. There is at least one true moral judgment [moral non-nihilism].
    Bob Ross

    Lets agree with points 1 and 2 and see if it necessarily leads to your conclusion.

    First, this is really going to come down to your definition of what is objective and subjective.

    "Something is subjective if it is dependent on a mind (biases, perception, emotions, opinions, imagination, or conscious experience).

    Something is objective if it can be confirmed independent of a mind."

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Subjectivity_and_objectivity_(philosophy)

    I think these are fairly uncontroversial and straight forward definitions, so lets start here.

    Lets now go back to your definition of truth which I agree with:

    ‘truth’ is the ‘correspondence/agreement of thought with reality’Bob Ross

    Now, is truth subjective, or objective? If it is subjective, then it cannot be determined independently of a mind. If it is objective, then it can be confirmed independently of a mind.

    If truth is merely the correspondence of thought with reality, then it needs no mind. Truth is simply a 'state'. "Thought is in correspondence with reality". If we were able to be aware of this, we might call it knowledge. But truth does not require knowledge. Truth is simply a state of being that is unconcerned if there is an observer there to realize it.

    Thus truth is best described as "objective'. With this, we can now examine your conclusion.

    3. There is at least one true moral judgment [moral non-nihilism].[/quote]

    If there is a true moral judgement, then it must be an objective moral judgement. If moral judgements are subjective, and only subjective, your conclusion does not follow. For there to be a true moral judgement, a moral judgement must be objectively in line with reality. But if there is a moral judgement that is in line with reality, it is objectively true, not subjectively true. The subjects opinion to the matter is irrelevant.

    But, can we salvage the intent of your theory? Lets try.

    (Subjectivity and objectivity continued from the wiki citation)

    "If a claim is true exclusively when considering the claim from the viewpoint of a sentient being, it is subjectively true. For example, one person may consider the weather to be pleasantly warm, and another person may consider the same weather to be too hot; both views are subjective. The word subjectivity comes from subject in a philosophical sense, meaning an individual who possesses unique conscious experiences, such as perspectives, feelings, beliefs, and desires, or who (consciously) acts upon or wields power over some other entity (an object).

    If a claim is true even when considering it outside the viewpoint of a sentient being (how ?), then it is labelled objectively true. Scientific objectivity is practicing science while intentionally reducing partiality, biases, or external influences. Moral objectivity is the concept of moral or ethical codes being compared to one another through a set of universal facts or a universal perspective and not through differing conflicting perspectives. Journalistic objectivity is the reporting of facts and news with minimal personal bias or in an impartial or politically neutral manner."

    Lets examine the idea of 'subjective truth'. Person A states, "Its hot" while person B states, "Its cool". From their perspectives, this is true. But how is it true? How is it 'in correspondence with reality" if we've claimed truth is objective?

    Its because we've left out the implicit information within their statements.

    Person A: From my subjective experience, I feel its hot.
    Person B: From my subjective experience, I feel its cold.

    These are both subjectively true, because it is objective. The feelings of a subject in reference to itself are objectively true. What one's subjective experience entails, is objectively true. We have a non-truth when this happens:

    Person A: From my subjective experience, I feel its hot, therefore I will claim it is hot for everyone else.
    Person B: From my subjective experience, I feel its cold, therefore I will claim it is cold for everyone else.

    At this point, the conclusion is not objectively true. Its a subjective belief.

    How do we tie this then back into a subjective morality? Lets examine your claim about subjective morality:

    Within moral subjectivism, the moral judgment is a belief which is the upshot of one’s psychology and it is proposition which is indexical—e.g., ‘I believe one ought not torture babies for fun’ is a moral judgment, and the belief about the belief attempts to determine the truth of the claim: either I believe one ought not to torture babies for fun or I don’t.Bob Ross

    Bob Ross: From my subjective viewpoint, I believe moral judgements are based on psychology, therefore all moral judgements are based on psychology.

    As we can see, this is a subjective claim, and not objective. Just because you personally believe moral judgements are based on psychology, this does not make it true objectively or subjectively. While you could create a subjective truth by simply claiming, "From my subjective viewpoint, I believe moral judgements are based on psychology.", it is your claim that this is a truth that all people must objectively conclude about morality that makes it objectively and subjectively false.

    I also wanted to address a couple of your points/counterpoints, but not go too long on this initial reply.

    For there to be true moral judgments, is just to say that we have good reasons to believe that some of the truth-apt (cognitive) moral judgments we have are true and thusly binding.Bob Ross

    Your own definition of truth counters this statement. Your definition of truth indicated no necessity that a person have knowledge or justification of something being true. A true moral judgement simply needs to be in correspondence with reality. The only thing you can state with your definition of truth is:

    "For there to be true moral judgments, is just to say that our moral judgement corresponds to reality."

    Another point:
    P1: If there are no true moral judgments, then one would have to ‘lie down and starve to death’.Bob Ross

    This statement is a contradiction. If there are no moral judgements, then there is nothing one has to do. Therefore one would not have to 'lie down and starve to death'.

    Finally:
    P1: If there are true moral judgments and they are not an expression of something objective, then they must be an expression of something subjective.Bob Ross

    Except that if something is true, it is in correspondence with reality objectively. The subjective knowledge or lack of knowledge is irrelevant. Therefore if there are true moral judgements, then they are objective.
  • A Measurable Morality
    Thank you for your patience Bob. I'm back from vacation!

    I am assuming you affirm #1 and #3, but I am inquiring about #2. You still have not provided what ‘goodness is’ in the sense of what those moral properties subsist in or of or are reducible to. E.g., is goodness identical to ‘well-being’, ‘happiness’, ‘existing’, ‘psychological approval’, ‘societal approval’, ‘conative emotions’, etc. ?Bob Ross

    Goodness is simply material existence and its expressions. It has nothing to do with culture, intention, emotions, and would be whether humanity had opinions about it or not.

    If you claim ‘goodness’ is identical to ‘what should be’, but where do properties of ‘what should be’ subsist in or of? E.g., are they identical to ‘well-being’, <...>, etc.?Bob Ross

    No, remove humanity from the equation for now. This is about morality first from a foundational level of pure existence. I can build up to human morality, but without the foundation established first, anything we say about human morality will fail.

    Moreover, I think ‘existence is good’ is pretty vague: is it ‘existing is good’, ‘preserving existence is good’, or/and ‘creating more existence is good’ (I’ve read you claiming things similar to all three)? For now, I will continue using ‘existence is good’ because the worry I am expounding isn’t really contingent on getting that clarification.Bob Ross

    "Existence is good" is the foundational morality. That's the material existence as a concept. Think of this like a dot on a line. A dot contains no mass, no attributes, or anything but the representation of a point in an infinite plane. When we introduce another dot, we have the existential expression of that dot compared to another dot. The most basic is "a distance of five dots". We now have a dot as relational to another dot. It has a length now and a comparative mass. It is now the expression of existence, not simply the material. With expressions of existence through relation, there now comes the question of, "How should existence express itself?" This is the question of morality.

    First we must have the foundational good of existence itself. Then we need an expression of existence between another existence. Now we can ask the question "Why should one expression of existence manifest itself over another potential expressed existence?"

    If the property of goodness is being predicated of ‘existence’, then ‘the good’ is not ‘existence’ because it is not identical to it: so what it is?Bob Ross

    It is the necessary logical foundation for good. It is the end result we come to when we ask the question, "Why should X exist?" This is because it all reduces to the ultimate question of "Why should anything exist?" This leads us with the binary of existence, or non-existence. I cannot justify non-existence as what should be without there being existence to make the justification. I cannot justify existence without there being existence to make the justification. As the justification of existence being better is a contradiction, the only remaining conclusion is that existence is necessary for me to state that anything 'should' be, and is the foundational good. The foundational good is not a question of the expression of existence in relation to another existence, but the fact of there being existence instead of nothing.

    Can we build from here to questions of morality within humanity? Absolutely. But we must settle the foundation first. If it helps to see where we are going, simply see if you can justify that non-existence is preferable to no existence at all. If you cannot, then what I've stated is the only alternative, and what we have to build on.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas
    So, I merely created a thought experiment taking this to its extreme: what if, right now, we had to perpetually torture a child (and I will let you use your imagination on what exactly is done to them) to prevent the immediate annihilation of the entire human species: is, at the very least, it morally permissible to do it, then?Bob Ross

    Absolutely yes. We torture our and kill our food every day for our own survival. Yet I still eat to live. I torture bugs beneath my feet that I accidently step on in the grass and leave them to slowly die from a crushed exoskeleton. Does that mean I stop walking? No. We throw pollution up into the air that kills thousands of animals and even people every year. Many don't die, but simply become perpetually sick. Yet this pollution saves hundreds of thousands more from death and suffering.

    You don't have to go to extremes. Just look how we live today.
  • Metaphysically impossible but logically possible?


    Something to consider is that logic and metaphysics require a linguistic or numerical representation. These things can be defined incorrectly but be 'correct' while using this poor definition that has no basis in reality. So one could have an incorrectly defined logic but a correctly defined metaphysics that matches to reality.
  • A Measurable Morality
    Good points Bob, this is what I need to hone the idea down.

    The first issue I have is you are claiming ‘existence is good’, where ‘is good’ is predication, and do not seem to offer any account of (1) why it is good nor (2) what goodness actually is.Bob Ross

    Certainly. The initial idea of good is what should be. So we go down the line. Should humanity exist? Animals? Minerals? Until finally we get to the most regressive question of all. Should there be existence at all?

    We are then faced with a binary. To exist, or not to exist, that is the question! But I realized something at that point. "Should" is not a possible word at that point. Should implies some other factor behind why something happens. But there is no underlying reason for existence being. It simply is. We are at the foundation level of an issue. And a foundation issue has nothing underneath it to support it. It is the support upon which everything else rests. Morality has often been about how we should set the state of existence, but it has ignored the foundation. Is existence itself good?

    Thus the question of what should be, comes to a foundation issue. Either existence should be, should not be, or simply is. If it should be, then there must be an underlying reason why it should be. But there is no underlying reason behind existence. There is no other to point to. It either is, or it isn't. Should existence not be? Once again, that would imply there is something behind that reason, some other that notes it should not be. But that too would be an existence.

    So what are we left with? What is. The foundational good. By existing, we have something that underlies all 'shoulds'. Morality is how we can judge relative good. And what is that relative good based on? What is. Existence.

    I know you don’t like ‘isms’, but I am being careful not to attribute claims which are not directly implied of your view. If I do make that mistake, then please let me know.Bob Ross

    Its not that I dislike isms per say. I dislike them if they are not clearly and consistently used in a useful manner for discussion. In case you haven't noticed, there is a pattern in all of my philosophy. Foundationalism. There comes a point in every question in which a foundation must be reached. That foundation has no other reason for its being, because it is the foundation. It is the recognition and proof that it is a foundation which allows us to then build upon it. The discrete experience. The notion that there is no external reason for existence being.

    When faced with a foundation, we cannot use certain methods that do have foundations behind them. The idea of 'should' rests on there being a foundation that provides the 'why'. I'm noting that in the question of what should be, we come to the foundation of existence itself. I call it "good", but it is really the foundational good. It is what all 'shoulds' reference, but itself needs no underlying reference for why it should be. It simply is.

    This of course is difficulty to wrap one's head around. There is on first glance the notion of 'choice'. After all, we still want to say it should or shouldn't be. But we can't ask that question of a foundation. It is where all questions of 'should' come from. It is not that I am completely satisfied with how its worded or approached either. As I noted, this is a much more exploratory idea than my other work. Basically in the chain of "why should something be", I arrived at this foundation which had no 'should' prior.

    I call it "good" because what else can I call it? To say it is not good means it should not be. And yet there is nothing behind it that states it should be either, it simply is. Thus the foundational good.

    I'm heading out for the holidays and won't be online again until Monday at minimum next week. Sorry Bob if this didn't address everything, but I'm out of time. I look forward to answering more questions then!
  • A Measurable Morality
    P1: If there is something instead of nothing, then there should be something.

    P2: there is something instead of nothing.

    C: TF, there should be something.
    Bob Ross

    No. I am saying there is something instead of nothing. I say that existence is what is good. If existence is what is good, then the more existence there is, the more good there is.

    I say "there should be an apple on that table" and you go "ahhh, but there has never been an apple on a table, and we cannot even ask the question 'should there be an apple on that table' without there first having been an apple on at least one table!".Bob Ross

    No, it is more that for us to discuss whether there should be an apple on that table, an apple must first exist and a table must first exist. The relation is a "should", the apple and the table in isolation are what exist.

    . We cannot say, "should" they exist, because that would imply some other existence that dictated that they should or should not be

    I don’t see why this would be true. The question ‘should they exist’ is despite whether there is anything that could exist more fundamentally than them: it could be the case that there is nothing more fundamental than a quark and it be immoral that they exist—no?
    Bob Ross

    No, because you would need to give a reason why it is immoral for a quark to exist. If the quark is the only existence, what other existence dictates that it is immoral? The discussion of what the quark does in its expressed existence is the moral issue. And the only way for a quark to express its existence is for there to be something else that exists that it can relate too.

    just like how I can validly ask ‘should this baby have been tortured for fun’ even if there is no actual way in which reality could have been such that the baby wouldn’t have been tortured for fun. What is is despite what ought to be.Bob Ross

    This was a little wordy and too far out there. Lets try to focus on the fundamentals. Why is existence good?

    Likewise, it seems like you are saying existence dictates what is good, which would imply that it is not itself predicated as good but rather is identical to 'the good'. It seems to be a standard of morality for you, but then you also say it isn't because there is nothing factual which makes it 'the good'. I am sort of confused about that.Bob Ross

    I do not want to say identical. I want to say an attribute of existence is its goodness. It is in relation to other existence, that is of course also existence itself, that we can state there are varying degrees of goodness. If you are having trouble understanding this, reread the parts where I cover expressed and potential existence.

    You seem to be saying that what should be the case is tied to what is actually the case.Bob Ross

    What should be the case is completely dependent on what is the case.

    I totally agree that normative judgments cannot exist without something factual to judge about, but I am failing to see how the normative judgments themselves are grounded in something factual, including how existence is non-subjectively goodBob Ross

    Because the foundation of good is what is. How it can express itself is what is. How it should express itself is the second step of what is good. Is there a better term for this? I don't know.

    By my lights, something that ought to be the case is a separate consideration from how things are currently arranged or how they exist.Bob Ross

    True. The situation is thus: X is good. Therefore more X is more good. Thus we should have more X.
    Perhaps the language would be better if I stated this:

    Existence is good. Morality is the question of how we should obtain the most existence possible.

    To me, if ‘existence is good’, I would say that is true subjectively and if it is not, then I am not sure how that is the case (yet).Bob Ross

    Actually, yes, you can claim that existence is bad. You can claim, as an existence, that nothingness is better than existing. All of my previous philosophy is tying in here now Bob. We as people can label any 'thing' anything we want. The question is whether that label works in application.

    If existence is bad, then existence should not be. Which means we should work to destroy all of existence including ourselves. Do we have any justification that existence is bad? We cannot use any other existence to compare to, as we are speaking about any existence. Perhaps we could find a situation of relational existence which is bad, but when compared to nothing, there is 'nothing' which implies that existence itself is bad.

    In other words, feel free to propose that non-existence is good, then see if you can reasonably apply it.

    You are essentially saying (as far as I understand) that we need something to exist to create prescriptions, therefore there is a true moral judgment that states ‘existence is good’. In other words:Bob Ross

    What I'm trying to do is answer the foundational question: "Why should there be something over nothing?" That has to be answered first before we discuss about how individual existences should express themselves in relation to others.

    The answer is there should be something over nothing, because there is. Because without something, there is no question of what should be. To have nothing, is to have no morality. Nothing cannot imply that it should 'be'. Only existence can. Without existence, there is no good. Therefore it is better for there to be something rather than nothing. Therefore as a fundamental, existence is good.

    I don’t think it is true that ‘existence is good’ because morality presupposes existent entities: I just don’t see how that inference is being made.Bob Ross

    Then presuppose there is no existence. Can that be good? If so, how and why? The question of this fundamental is difficult to grasp because it is foundational. We cannot look to something beyond existence itself to justify why it should exist. We can only relate it as something vs nothing.

    My point is not to make a case for nothingness being good: I am merely pointing out that, to me, it isn’t incoherent to claim this because I don’t see why normative claims presuppose that existence is good.Bob Ross

    But you must when the only question is whether it is good for there to be existence, or good for there to be nothing. It isn't incoherent to make any claim. It is whether one can justify that claim in application. Can you justify that nothing is good, while something is not? If you cannot, then we take what little justification we can that 'something' is good and see if we can build something else from that.
  • A Measurable Morality
    I’m sure there are plenty of people out there who still believe in quaint notions like ‘foundational good’. I wouldn’t say they are simply wrong. I would say that if you delve into the presuppositions such a notion relies on you recognize that what appears as eternal is only eternal within the context of a relative cultural context.Joshs

    Please relate this to the OP. Its not a 'quaint notion', its a step by step process. Please demonstrate why it is incorrect.
  • A Measurable Morality
    Isn't the point that morality grows out of a sense making process?Tom Storm

    No. I think this is getting too far away from the topic as well. Please relate it to what is posted. This is not an abstract discussion, this is a discussion about the specific post.
  • A Measurable Morality
    This isn’t self-interest, its shared interest, which is not simply the sum of selfish drives.Joshs

    Then what if two separate cultures or civilizations want different things? Are we saying the victor is in the right? No, this is still not a very good argument, just nice language.

    To say we prefer coherence over chaos is a kind of circularity. The sense of identity disintegrates in chaos and incoherence, so of course we perceive existence as ‘good’.Joshs

    Read the post again. I am not saying existence is preferred. It has nothing to do with our preferences. I'm saying existence is the foundational good.