Ok, I agree that you can make this distinction in some cases. But if someone is stabbed and dies immediately on the spot, then I think it is plausible to say that his murder and death denote the same event.It might be easier if we imagine that Caesar was stabbed on a Monday and died on the Tuesday. "the death of Caesar" refers to what happened on Tuesday, whereas "the murder of Caesar" refers to what happened on Monday as well. — Michael
You should change the descriptions to "the death of Caesar" and "the murder of Caesar", and then I think it will make more sense to think that they denote the same event (and you cannot really decide this just by analyzing the descriptions themselves, since it is after all possible for two different descriptions to denote the same event; e.g. "the death of Caesar" and "the death of the conqueror of Gaul"). — Fafner
Since "murder" just means something like "violent death", then on your view it would follow that a person can die twice (if "murder" and "death" are two distinct things that happen to everyone who's murdered), which is be a pretty bizarre thing to say in my opinion.
I'm not claiming that dying and being murdered are always the same thing. I'm only claiming that in the particular case of Caesar the two descriptions happen to denote the same event (since they are non-rigid designators etc.). And there's nothing problematic in saying this. I'll try to illustrate this through your example. Crimson is a type of red, but it doesn't follow that a crimson apple has two distinct colors: crimson and red, but it has only one color that falls under two different descriptions (and this is consistent with the fact that being crimson and being red sometimes do refer to distinct colors).
But what if somebody meant his murder by "his death?" Wouldn't the reference be the same in that case? — Mongrel
Likewise, (1) the fact that Pat is shorter than Chris isn't the same as (2) the fact that Pat is shorter than the Eiffel Tower. And neither of those facts are the same as (3) the fact that Pat is 5 feet tall. For all that, the properties ascribed to Pat in (1), (2) and (3) stand pairwise as determinable to determinate. — Pierre-Normand
I'm not necessarily disagreeing, but I have two questions (which are related): a) are you claiming that one can know the Fregean reference solely by virtue of knowing the meaning of the relevant predicates? (which clearly you can't since you cannot know apriori whether "Caesar" and "the conqueror of Gaul" denote the same person) and b) Is "the conqueror of Gaul" a rigid designator on your account? Because if it is not (and it is plain that it isn't) then I think your criteria for the non-identity of 'x' and 'y' (in the quote) becomes vacuous. Because consider that it is a contingent fact that "Caesar" and "the conqueror of Gaul" denote the same person (and you can further substitute 'Caesar' with another description to eliminate all names); but this you can know only aposteriori, so it means that on your criteria 'x' and 'y' (if 'x' and 'y' are definite descriptions) denote the same entity if their terms happen to denote the same entity, and of course everyone will agree with that...I'm rather saying that 'x' and 'y' refer to distinct events if [their predicates] have different Fregean references. — Pierre-Normand
I think that in the end it is an arbitrary matter whether we call it the same event or two different events, since we sometimes talk about the two interchangeably and sometimes not, so I don't think you can really prove that it must be the one way and not the other (and I took this example from Ramsey's paper, who might've chose a different less controversial example (and you can easily think of some like "the death of the conqueror of Gaul") - but the point remains that there's not principled apriori criterion to distinguish between co-refrential and non-coreferential descriptions).I wouldn't say that Caesar died twice. I would say that he died because he was murdered. The 'violence' that is constitutive of the event's being a case of murder is the mens rea of the murderer(s). This mens rea isn't a constitutive part of Ceasar's dying. Hence, since the two events don't have the same constitutive parts, they are not the same. That is true (in this case, anyway) even when we restrict attention to what occurred in the actual world (and a fortiori if we consider the modal properties of those events). — Pierre-Normand
No, they are not the same facts, but the two descriptions (containing 'crimson' and 'red') do denote the same thing or entity in your example (an apple with a single color) :)But the fact that the apple is red isn't the same as the fact that the apple is crimson, is it? — Pierre-Normand
You mean the reference of the event she is thinking about and the reference of her utterance? — Pierre-Normand
There is the capacity to inaugurate new uses, new meanings that may very well break with 'convention' - all the while being amenable - in principle - to becoming conventional. — StreetlightX
Really? Surely there is at least one interpretation of Wittgenstein that allows first person data about the experience of speaking. — Mongrel
But don't you agree that sometimes there's value in asking if a statement is informative? To me that's a marker for ordinary language use vs unnecessary philosophical shenanigans (and sometimes other forms of bullshit.) — Mongrel
Right and wrong is just settled via success in communication, right? — Mongrel
Is that down to philosophical fashion? Or is there something we know that most of cognitive science doesn't? — Srap Tasmaner
There's also a very good paper by john McDowell "The Content of Perceptual Experience" (appears in "Mind, Value and Reality"), that argues for a very similar idea to Hornsby.Another paper that is quite relevant to anti-representationalism is: Jennifer Hornsby, Personal and sub‐personal; A defence of Dennett's early distinction, Philosophical Exploratons, 3, 1, 2000 — Pierre-Normand
There's also a very good paper by john McDowell "The Content of Perceptual Experience" (appears in "Mind, Value and Reality"), that argues for a very similar idea to Hornsby. — Fafner
Wrong. "It is raining" is more specific (provides more information) than "the weather outside". Would you answer the question, "What is the weather outside?", with the "the weather outside"? You would use the string of scribbles, "the weather outside" when you know that the reader knows what the weather outside is, or you would use it as part of the sentence, "the weather outside is rainy." It all comes down to understanding what is it the listener already knows in order to speak efficiently (by not wasting energy speaking or writing to inform someone what they already know). If "the weather outside" and "it is raining" means the same thing, the saying, "the weather outside is rainy" would be a redundant sentence, but it isn't in the mind of the listener that doesn't know the weather outside.I think this is a useful example of how meaning is different to reference. Both "it is raining" and "the weather outside" can refer to the same thing (if it's raining), but don't mean the same thing. So it is wrong to say that the meaning of a word (or a phrase) is the thing it refers to.
The same with my earlier example of "the son of of Edward VIII" and "the father of Elizabeth II".
So neither of Harry's proposed accounts of meaning (the other being concerned with intention) works at all. — Michael
Both examples only refer to the same thing for those that know what it is that it is referring to. For those that don't know, one is more informative than the other. — Harry Hindu
If "the weather outside" and "it is raining" means/refers to the same thing, then saying, "the weather outside is rainy" would be a redundant sentence, but it isn't in the mind of the listener that doesn't know the weather outside. — Harry Hindu
I keep thinking, as I suggested in the other thread, that what we want here is sets of propositions ordered by entailment, but it looks like that would have to be relative to a set of assumptions or background knowledge or something. I want Pat's being 5 feet tall to buy you, as a single fact, everything it entails. A separate fact for everything Pat is taller or shorter than seems less than optimal. — Srap Tasmaner
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.