Yes, it can bend your mind. But it doesn't have to. Plus and quus are the same in some instances and not in others. So you can tell which is being followed, provided you consider the full scope of the rule, not just a selected part of it.There's no fact regarding which rules. It's a mind bender for sure. — frank
I don't think we really conflict. I do want to say that it is a fact that someone doing 2+2 is doing something different from someone who is doing 2⊕2. It is true that there is no difference in that application. But if you consider the range of the applications, the full facts of the matter become apparent. To consider that individual case or even a limited range of cases is misdirection.There is no fact of the matter if a fact is something we discover. Not if a fact can be something we do. You know how to do plus, as opposed to quus. If you want, you might say that it is a fact that you do 2 plus 2 and not 2 quus 2 — Banno
↪Joshs Seems we pretty much agree, except that I don't think calling this an "intuition" is at all helpful, since it hints at private mental phenomena. It's not about intuition, it's about action - following a rule is something we do, not a "special sense — Banno
213. "But this initial segment of a series obviously admitted of various interpretations (e.g. by means of algebraic expressions) and so you must first have chosen one such interpretation."—Not at all. A doubt was possible in certain circumstances. But that is not to say that I did doubt, or even could doubt. (There is something to be said, which is connected with this, about the psychological 'atmosphere' of a process.) So it must have been intuition that removed this doubt?—If intuition is an inner voice—how do I know how I am to obey it? And how do I know that it doesn't mislead me? For if it can guide me right, it can also guide me wrong. ((Intuition an unnecessary shuffle.))
… It would almost be more correct to say, not that an intuition was needed at every stage, but that a new decision was needed at every stage.
But I don't think that "invent" is the appropriate description. The story of the irrationals shows that when we set up the rules of a language-game (and that description of numbers is also an idealization), we may find that there are situations (applications of the rules) that surprise us. Hence it is more appropriate to say that we discover these. When these situations arise, we have to decide what to do, in the relevant context - note that there can be no rules, in the normal sense, about what decision we should make, so I would classify these decisions, not as arbtrary or irrational, but as pragmatic and so rational in that sense. — Ludwig V
If we're talking about mathematics as a whole, I agree with you. I'm just suggesting that a bit of flexibility in our language within mathematics is helpful. The important point is that when we develop/invent rules and make decisions about how to apply them, we are not totally "in charge". Put it this way - our agreements can lead to undesired consequjences and disagreements, which need to be resolved. We don't invent those - we would much rather they didn't happen, so we don't invent them. We do resolve them. That's not a problem, in itself; it's just part of our practice.I like "invent" better because it underlines the fact that, as I see it, mathematics is a human invention, a language, and not a fundamental aspect of the universe. — T Clark
Thanks.As for the rest of the quoted passage, — T Clark
I agree. Intuition isn’t really what I was after. Wittgenstein said it better. — Joshs
Many of Wittgenstein's contemporaries said it better than Wittgenstein by formally distinguishing assertions from propositions. In particular, Frege introduced turnstile notation to make the distinction between propositions on the one hand, and assertions about propositions that he called judgements on the other. — sime
The important point is that when we develop/invent rules and make decisions about how to apply them, we are not totally "in charge". Put it this way - our agreements can lead to undesired consequjences and disagreements, which need to be resolved. We don't invent those - we would much rather they didn't happen, so we don't invent them. We do resolve them. That's not a problem, in itself; it's just part of our practice. — Ludwig V
I consider the most important and radical implication of Wittgenstein’s later work to be his critique of Frege’s theory of sense as reference. — Joshs
Frege remained mired in a formalistic metaphysics centered on logic, without ever grasping f Wittgenstein’s distinction between the epistemic and the grammatical. — Joshs
A critique of Frege's theory of sense and reference by Wittgenstein isn't possible, because Frege never provided an explicit theory or definition of sense. Frege only demonstrated his semantic category of sense (i.e. modes of presentation) through examples. And he was at pains to point out that sense referred to communicable information that leads from proposition to referent - information that is therefore neither subjective nor psychological — sime
I'm just suggesting that a bit of flexibility in our language within mathematics is helpful. The important point is that when we develop/invent rules and make decisions about how to apply them, we are not totally "in charge". Put it this way - our agreements can lead to undesired consequjences and disagreements, which need to be resolved. We don't invent those - we would much rather they didn't happen, so we don't invent them. — Ludwig V
Again, perhaps it's about what we do, how we act as members of a community.If not subjective nor psychological, then what? — Joshs
Perhaps there was good reason for this - that sense might be shown but not stated, if in being state it ceases to be intensional, becoming extensional.Frege never provided an explicit theory or definition of sense. Frege only demonstrated his semantic category of sense (i.e. modes of presentation) through examples. — sime
Can it be that it it is the concept of "beyond our grasp" that is beyond our grasp?
(My old friend Ludvic suggested this to me.) — unenlightened
Second page, and still no pi/pie joke... — Banno
.Desperate for experience, Jim, inspired by Oz's description of a vagina, has sex with a warm apple pie, but is humiliated when caught by his father — https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/American_Pie_(film)#Plot
That's a very hard question to answer. My best short answer is, I think, that what I'm saying is meant as a refinement of what Wittgenstein said, not a contradiction. So I'm pretty sure that the distinction between invention and discovery here (in mathematics) can be expected to apply (be useful) wherever we are talking/thinking about rules, language games, practices and forms of life. (Is it forms of life, or ways of life? I'm not sure). More than that, it is reflected in philosophy, as competing theories about mathematics. I've come to the tentative conclusion that neither realism nor constructivism are true, though both have some truth.In what way is the invention of a mathematical rule different from the creation of a language game/form of life? — Joshs
Yes, but isn't there a rider here, in that W eventually sees the distinction between empirical assertion and a grammatical remark as a matter of what sentences/statements/propositions are used to do - (which, after all, is what meaning means). So "This is red" can be an empirical proposition and an ostensive definition.When Moore says ‘this is my hand’, Wittgenstein argues that he confuses an empirical assertion with a grammatical proposition. — Joshs
Well, "discovers" is a bit odd here. What could count as Moore not knowing that that this is his hand? (I can imagine circumstances in which we might not realize that that is his hand, but they are quite special.) However, Moore thinks he is making an empirical statement and that's not wrong. But it seems to leave (does leave) room for sceptical doubt. Wittgenstein wants to eliminate doubt, so I take him to be pointing out that this case, when we attend to it properly, also draws our attention to the conditions for the possibility of doubt.Moore’s gesture is pointing to the grammar , the rules, of a language game that Moore ‘inherited’ from his entanglement with his culture, but which rules are invisible to him. Moore ‘discovers’ that this is his hand, but doesn’t realize that his discovery only makes sense within the language game. — Joshs
Philosophers almost always speak as if we are in charge (control) of language - and practices. (I think they hesitate a bit about "forms of life" and that does seem to gesture at something that we are lumbered with, rather than something we invent or are in charge of). But we learn language as something given - how could we not? After we have learnt language we realize, with Humpty-Dumpty's remark in Alice (in Wonderland or through the looking-glass? I don't remember.) that "Words mean what I want them to mean. It's a question of who's in charge." But although in practice we can modify language in some ways, much (most) of what goes on is not under anybody's control. Words don't mean what I, or anybody else, wants them to mean, even though thousands, even millions, of individual decisions make up what goes on.Isnt this form of life an invention, but one that Moore was not ‘in charge of’? — Joshs
Mathematics etc. are not quite the same kind of thing as our everyday conceptions of the world. They are more "artificial" than natural language. So I'm happy to agree that we can and we should say exactly that. But I'm after a third category. Our agreement about how to apply a rule defines the rule. So you would think that no difficulty could arise. But sometimes we don't agree, and sometimes our rule throws up peculiar results. (And we can agree when either of those things happen). Negotiation is necessary - changes to the rules, additional rules, etc. These situations do not neatly fit into the usual disctingction between the rules (concepts) and applications of the rules (experience).Couldn’t we say that scientific paradigms are invented , and the facts that show up within them are discovered? — Joshs
I.E. its a conceptual game of identifying 'gaps' in a systemic series of abstractions with governing rules then giving that 'gap' a new symbol as well as new rules as to how to manipulate these 'gaps'.I'm unsure why this post hasn't gotten any replies, because this gets at the heart of the matter for why pi continues indefinitely.
A perfect circle simply doesn't exist. It can't be made by man, and not by machine. We can get close, but no matter how close we get, it will never be perfect, much like how a digital rendition of an analog signal can also never be perfect.
If we 'zoom in' one pixel (or one decimal) further, the imperfection shows. — Tzeentch
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.