I think JTB is intended as a test for knowledge — J
Given that we believe the sentence, we believe that it is true. Do you mean more than that?I agree with you. But does that mean that the definition must take the truth or falsity of the sentence as given, in some way? — Ludwig V
Our evaluation might be better....my evaluation... — Ludwig V
You are right that there is at least one sense in which justification and truth rise or fall together. But Gettier's argument assumes that they do not, that is, that it is possible to be justified in believing that p and for p to be false. — Ludwig V
But if I'm evaluating whether someone knows that p, I must make my own evaluation of the truth or falsity of p, — Ludwig V
This has the awkward consequence that I can never learn anything from anyone else. — Ludwig V
Q1. Do I have knowledge of X (a proposition)? — J
what use is JTB if it can't show us how to tell whether we know something or not? — J
No. We do have knowledge - we know things.I think what you're suggesting is that instead we should say, "I don't know if X is true. Such knowledge is impossible without circularity. But if it's true, then I know X. And if it isn't, then I don't." — J
It doesn't tell us if they are true or not, so much as if they are known or not.JTB is supposed to help us evaluate knowledge claims -- keep us epistemologically honest. And on this construal, it can't. — J
Above, it told us that Jim was mistaken. He claimed to know something that was not true.what use is JTB if it can't show us how to tell whether we know something or not? — J
Wouldn’t we have to be able to separate J, T or B from the others to think we know something when in fact what we know is missing J, T or B? Or are all three destroyed, along with K, when we are in error? — Fire Ologist
We know analytic statements are true.
— Janus
But do we know this apart from the right justifications? I don't see how. Even something as clear as modus ponens can and must be explained and justified; we don't say "I just know it." — J
If something is true by definition or if something is logically self-evident, or if the proposition concerns something being directly observed, then I would say we need no further justification. — Janus
But all three of these things -- truth by definition, logical self-evidence, and the reliability of direct observation -- are ways of demonstrating justification. To understand this, imagine explaining any one of them to an intelligent child. They all involve steps, cogitation, judgment, insight. We don't simply see why they are true, or at least not usually. In fact, as you know, the reliability of direct observation can be challenged, and the challenge is precisely for a justification as to how such observations lead to truth. — J
It's not all that strange. A standard use of "justify" does indeed assume that if P is false, then there is no justification for believing that p. But this has the consequence that I can only be said to know P if I have a conclusive justification for P. That means that I do not know, for example, that the earth goes round the sun. So that definition can be said to be too strong. So many people believe we should relax the criterion and allow that I do know that the earth goes round the sun, even though I only believe it on authority. It is tempting to say that it follows that I can be justified in believing something even though it is false and Gettier explicitly says that is his assumption.Well, I think Gettier creates a strange division between justification and truth, but the Gettier cases I am familiar with involve a proposition that is true, not false. — Leontiskos
There's a wrinkle here that Gettier does not mention. It is clearly wrong to believe something that is known to be false and conclusive proof over-rides any non-conclusive justification. But where there is no conclusive evidence, one has to go with the evidence one has, and that does mean that one can be justified in believing something that turns out later to be false. That's a weakness in most of the cases. However, most people seem to go along with his (unstated) assumption that we must continue to call him justified when we know, but he does not, that his belief that Jones will get the job is false.First, in that sense of "justified" in which S's being justified in believing P is a necessary condition of S's knowing that P, it is possible for a person to be justified in believing a proposition that is in fact false. — Analysis. vol. 23 (1966)
Smith wrongly, but not without justification, believes that Jones is the man who will get the job, but the truth is that Smith will get the job. So Smith is using "the man who will get the job" to refer to Jones, but we (and Gettier) are using it to refer to Smith. That makes two different statements expressed in the same words. There is no problem. (This solution does not apply to all Gettier cases).(e) The man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket. — Analysis. vol. 23 (1966)
JTB requires me to accept a claim to knowledge only if I know it is justified and true (and believed). But that means that I have to know p as well as the person claiming knowledge.This has the awkward consequence that I can never learn anything from anyone else.
— Ludwig V
Why think that? — Leontiskos
That's not an unreasonable idea. Nonetheless, if it turns out that we are wrong, we are expected to withdraw the claim to knowledge. I may be said to know that my car will be safe in the car park, and that may be well justified. But it is is stolen, I have to admit that I was wrong.This is yet another thing from the prolific David Lewis, contextualism, the short version of which used to be that we do know things in everyday life that we don't know in the philosophy seminar room. — Srap Tasmaner
It is obvious to us. But we have learnt how to do reasoning as part of learning language and interacting with people.the truth of things which are true by definition and logical self-evidence is simply obvious, and just needs to be pointed out to be established in conscious understanding. — Janus
What bothers me is the interface between belief and reality. "It must be true" is the something more that is required. But once I have assessed the evidence, what more could there be? so I have difficulty in seeing what this amounts to. The best I can come up with is that claims to knowledge, like any other claim, have to be withdrawn if they turn out to be false. There may be cases in which the truth or otherwise of the proposition in question is finally and conclusively determined, but most of the everyday stuff doesn't come up to that standard. So the caution remains in place.It's not enough, for the sentence to be known, that we believe it to be true. It must also be true. — Banno
"truth," "relevance," "significance", these aren't mapping onto features of the world so much as they're tools we use for various purposes in different contexts.
— Joshs
How can they be tools if they do not in some way "map" onto the world? — Banno
Q1a. Yes.
Q1b. Yes.
Q1c.Yes - follows from Q1a: if you believe it, you believe it to be true. — Banno
JTB is supposed to help us evaluate knowledge claims -- keep us epistemologically honest. And on this construal, it can't.
— J
It doesn't tell us if they are true or not, so much as if they are known or not. — Banno
Smith wrongly, but not without justification, believes that Jones is the man who will get the job, but the truth is that Smith will get the job. So Smith is using "the man who will get the job" to refer to Jones, but we (and Gettier) are using it to refer to Smith. — Ludwig V
JTB requires me to accept a claim to knowledge only if I know it is justified and true (and believed). But that means that I have to know p as well as the person claiming knowledge. — Ludwig V
They’re not tools for mapping onto objects, but for enacting new forms of sense in our material and discursive interactions with the world. A hammer doesn’t “map” onto nails. Its usefulness lies in how we employ it to drive nails.Truth is a tool that in some contexts we use to check agreement with facts. In other contexts, we use it to contrast honesty vs lying; in others, to resolve disputes. In addition to the sense of truth as empirical/factual, one can think of grammatical/conceptual truth, performative/expressive truth, aesthetic/evaluative truth, narrative/interpretive truth and many other senses of meaning of that ‘same’ word.
Wittgenstein would emphasize that these aren't competing theories of truth but different tools serving different purposes in our linguistic practices. The mistake is assuming all these uses must share some common essence. There’s no one metaphysical object “truth” that the word latches onto. — Joshs
Well, yes, You seem to be expecting something from the JTB account that it does not provide. It's not a theory of truth.But Q1c was not about belief, but rather truth. Yes, it follows from believing something that I also believe it to be true, but that's not a reply to Q1c, which asks "Is it true?" Nothing I believe can supply the answer; it depends on the facts. — J
It's not enough, for the sentence to be known, that we believe it to be true. It must also be true. — Banno
What bothers me is the interface between belief and reality. "It must be true" is the something more that is required. But once I have assessed the evidence, what more could there be? so I have difficulty in seeing what this amounts to. The best I can come up with is that claims to knowledge, like any other claim, have to be withdrawn if they turn out to be false. There may be cases in which the truth or otherwise of the proposition in question is finally and conclusively determined, but most of the everyday stuff doesn't come up to that standard. So the caution remains in place. — Ludwig V
But Q1c was not about belief, but rather truth. Yes, it follows from believing something that I also believe it to be true, but that's not a reply to Q1c, which asks "Is it true?" Nothing I believe can supply the answer; it depends on the facts.
JTB is supposed to help us evaluate knowledge claims -- keep us epistemologically honest. And on this construal, it can't.
— J
It doesn't tell us if they are true or not, so much as if they are known or not. — Banno
That's what I don't see how to separate. We both agree that only true things can be known. So if JTB tells us that X is known, it must also tell us at the same time that X is true. — J
But Smith is using "the man who will get the job" to refer to Jones. Since Jones will not get the job, Smith's deduction is based on a false premiss and the conclusion is not justified (but not refuted either).The reason I don't think it works is because if Smith were using "the man who will get the job" to refer to Jones, then there would not be an entailment involved. — Leontiskos
I don't follow this at all. Smith is not considering two propositions, but only one, and that proposition is false and so does not entail that the man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket, so Smith's belief is justified only in a weak sense. It might be sufficient for the J clause in the JTB, but it is certainly not sufficient for the T clause.In that case rather than there being an entailment, Smith's two propositions would just be saying the same thing with different words. — Leontiskos
It all depends on how you interpret the sentence "The man who will be appointed has ten coins in his pocket". As it stands here, the reference of "the man who will be appointed" is not fixed, or rather is fixed differently in the context of Smith's beliefs (where it refers to Jones) and in the context of the God's eye view of the narrator (and the audience) of Gettier's story (where it refers to Smith). In the context of Smith's beliefs (e) is justified but false, and in the context of the narrator and the audience, it is true. I don't know what criteria you have for "same proposition", but it seems to me that if a given sentence is true in one context and false in another, that sentence is expressing different propositions in each context. Certainly the same proposition cannot be true and false at the same time.But imagine, further, that unknown to Smith, he himself, not Jones, will get the job. And, also, unknown to Smith, he himself has ten coins in his pocket. Proposition (e) is then true, — Analysis. vol. 23 (1966)
Yes, perhaps I was a bit hasty there. Though if someone tells me that the earth goes round the sun, I can demand their proof and they can, no doubt, provide it - the data exist and the interpretation can be explained to me. But I would have to trust the data, or, perhaps collect a fresh set of data.I don't think this is right. Someone can "justify" a claim to you and thereby show you that it is true. Thus one can learn from another on JTB precisely through the other's justification. — Leontiskos
That's a bit sweeping, isn't it? Certainly, an absolute guarantee of an empirical truth seems to be built in to their definition as contingent. But, if the conditions are met, surely we can guarantee the truth. Then there are the embedded or hinge propositions, which seem beyond the possibility of any coherent or rational doubt. Perhaps our choice is not between fallibilism or infallibilism across the board. After all, not all propositions (candidate truths) are of the same kind.Again, in fallibilism, no justification (which is always epistemological in its nature) can guarantee the ontological occurrence of some given truth in question. — javra
You seem to be expecting something from the JTB account that it does not provide. It's not a theory of truth. — Banno
To try to reduce possible confusion, how this works in practice: “I know that the planet is physical and roughly spherical,” is a claim of JTB. — javra
Again, in fallibilism, no justification (which is always epistemological in its nature) can guarantee the ontological occurrence of some given truth in question. — javra
That's a bit sweeping, isn't it? Certainly, an absolute guarantee of an empirical truth seems to be built in to their definition as contingent. But, if the conditions are met, surely we can guarantee the truth. Then there are the embedded or hinge propositions, which seem beyond the possibility of any coherent or rational doubt. Perhaps our choice is not between fallibilism or infallibilism across the board. After all, not all propositions (candidate truths) are of the same kind. — Ludwig V
This is a very helpful analysis. It sharpens the question, — J
I don't know whether every proponent of JTB would be happy with this, though. — J
To try to reduce possible confusion, how this works in practice: “I know that the planet is physical and roughly spherical,” is a claim of JTB. — javra
Here, I wonder whether you misstated your target sentence. Are you talking about a JTB claim for "The planet is physical and roughly spherical" or for "I know that the planet is physical and roughly spherical"? A great deal depends on this, so I'll wait until you reply before going on. — J
I don't follow this at all. Smith is not considering two propositions, but only one, and that proposition is false and so does not entail that the man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket,... — Ludwig V
Regarding the "false grounds," the key to the Gettier case is the difference between a material conclusion and a formal conclusion...
...Taken further we might say that a valid conclusion is different from a sound conclusion, and therefore John and Ben have reached different conclusions. — Leontiskos
Yes, perhaps I was a bit hasty there. Though if someone tells me that the earth goes round the sun, I can demand their proof and they can, no doubt, provide it - the data exist and the interpretation can be explained to me. But I would have to trust the data, or, perhaps collect a fresh set of data. — Ludwig V
That's true (sorry!) — J
If—as any fallibilist will maintain—all possible epistemological appraisals can only be fallible, then our appraisal of a belief being either true or not will always be liable to some possibility of being wrong (with the likelihood of this possibility varying by degrees). — javra
The counterargument could be phrased this way:
1. Truth is always known via justification, and ensured by justification
2. Justification can never overcome the possibility of the one-in-a-million anomaly
3. Therefore, truth is never certain
This form of skepticism is a bit like the claim that epistemology is like a game of pool and no matter how good you are, there is always a chance that your shot will not pocket the 9-ball. Accidental contingencies are always involved, and therefore the best one can hope for is a good probability (or an ↪inference to the best explanation). Such a skeptic would say, "The only way to guarantee that the 9-ball is pocketed would be to pick it up with your own hand and place it into the pocket directly, but that would be cheating." — Leontiskos
1. Truth is always known via justification, and ensured by justification
2. Justification can never overcome the possibility of the one-in-a-million anomaly
3. Therefore, truth is never certain — Leontiskos
it could have been better written. — javra
the proposition of “the planet is physical and roughly spherical” is taken to be an instance of knowledge, thereby being [a] JTB claim — javra
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.