we don't have Objective access, so everything you say about "the world" is necessarily speculative, and will always be so. — Pattern-chaser
So, please justify your claim. — Dfpolis
we don't have Objective access, so everything you say about "the world" is necessarily speculative, and will always be so. — Pattern-chaser
The question, then, is whether or not there is an analogous de dicto reading of "water is H2O" such that a counterfactual chemical composition of water is not a contradiction. Given that you've accepted that it's possible that scientists are mistaken in their claim that water is H2O, isn't that an acceptance of such a de dicto reading (else it would be as incoherent as suggesting that we could be mistaken in thinking that Donald Trump is Donald Trump)? — Michael
most philosophers do not think that possible worlds are literally real worlds that they inquire about. They think of possible worlds as more akin to logically consistent stories about how things might be. — PossibleAaran
Some philosophers think that Philosophy involves making "discoveries" about "possible worlds" — PossibleAaran
I think possible worlds talk is usually intended as talk about logical possibility. I can't remember an article in which that isn't quite clear. — PossibleAaran
philosophers will use technical language where plain language would do, and this has the effect of making philosophy seem incredibly convoluted to those outside of it, and even leads to errors for those within it. I think possible worlds talk is like this. — PossibleAaran
The justification is that we don't have Objective access to "the world". — Pattern-chaser
Given that they co-refer or not, they express necessarily true or necessarily false propositions. That you are unaware of which it is, and that this depends on the meaning of the words, is where the feeling of contingency comes from. For it is contingent whether the sentence expresses a necessarily true or necessarily false proposition. — Snakes Alive
That is exactly my approach. To say that something is possible or necessary without relating the statement to the reference set S is to say nothing at all. In ordinary speech the reference is omitted, but the implication is that S is the set of everything we currently know about the world and how it operates. That then leads to the definition I gave above that an impossible event is one such that, if I learned that it happened, I would be astonished and have to radically revise my worldview.My current definition of possible is:
p is possible with respect to a set of propositions, S, if p does not contradict the propositions of S. — Dfpolis
...I do not find it worthy of belief. — Dfpolis
It seems to me that this analysis is incomplete. It's surely true that Donald Trump is Donald Trump, no matter what you call him. So, if you read the terms in "Donald is Mr. Trump" formally (as referring to the person), this is simply an instance of the Principle of Identity and so necessarily true. The problem is that is not the only reading. One could read it as "The name 'Donald' refers to the same person as the name 'Mr. Trump.'" In that case, it speaks of a contingent reality, for naming conventions are contingent -- this person could well have another name, like "John Smith" -- or even "David Dennison." — Dfpolis
I have no doubt that the two readings express different judgements (intentional existents). Still I have several questions/
Can one distinguish two identically written propositions without reference to the intentional states they express? If one can't, isn't linguistic analysis (formal or informal) derivative on intentional analysis?
Alternately, to what does "proposition" refer, if not to judgements? — Dfpolis
I think that the underlying problem here is the assumption that proper names refer to things, rather than to intelligible aspects of reality. "Clark Kent" refers to Jorel's son in his guise of newspaper reporter, not to Jorel's son simpliciter. "Superman" refers to Jorel's son in his guise of the man of steel. By ignoring the aspect under which Jorel's son is designated, the notion of rigid designator distorts the intent of the designating agents.
It is not even true that Jorel's son in the guise of newspaper reporter is Jorel's son in the guise of the man of steel -- even though both designate Jorel's son. In other words, when one learns that Clark Kent is superman, the conditions of designation of each term change. What "Clark Kent" means to the speaker after leaning that Clark Kent is superman is more than what it meant before.
So, while "Clark Kent" is materially the same before and after the revelation, it is formally different. This is seen by examining its scope of application. Before the revelation, the speaker would not apply "Clark Kent" to Jorel's son in the guise of the man of steel, but would after the revelation.
I conclude that the analysis of rigid designation is defective because it it mischaracterizes what proper names refer to. They do not refer to objects, but to intelligible aspects of objects.
However, the cognitive significance of a sentence, i.e. what we're capable of learning from the fact that the sentence expresses a true proposition, outruns its literal semantic content. — Snakes Alive
So, I do not see how it is possible to say that what we learn "outruns" the literal semantic content, when what we learn (the intentional state elicited) we learn from the literal semantic content. What cpuld you possibly mean by "literal semantic content" other than the intentional state that a literal reading elicits? I — Dfpolis
This is like saying that a map with a misprint is not worth anymore than a possible map. — Dfpolis
P is possible with respect to a set of facts or propositions, S, if P does not contradict S.
I do think "facts" should be restricted to intelligible reality. — Dfpolis
There is no claim of infallibility here. If you think there is, explain how.
The actual world is actual because it acts to inform us. Merely possible worlds do not act, let alone act to inform us. Instead, we inform (or perhaps misinform) them. — Dfpolis
First, it is unnecessary. As we can have no epistemic access to any world but our own, actual world, anything we can learn, we can learn from the real world.
We have no access to any possible world. We only have access to our imagination, which can easily be inconsistent. What we know of the actual world cannot "easily fail" if we exercise due diligence. It fails occasionally, but it is usually interpretations and constructs that fail rather than experiential data. — Dfpolis
I said that a sensory object's modification of our sensory state is identically our sensory representation of the object. I said that the object informing the subject is identically the subject being informed by the object. — Dfpolis
It is the name of the concept because the employment of the tool requires one to construct, or at least recognize, worlds that are possible. — Dfpolis
This is inadequate as, unless P is actually true, there is no world in which P is the case. What you need to say is "P is possible if there is at least one possible world in which P is the case" -- and that is circular. — Dfpolis
Still, they are not our world, as, if they are different in any way, they are not identical to our actual world. Any world that is not identical to our world is a different world. As each is a different world, each (actual or potential) object in them is a different object from any object in out actual world. — Dfpolis
When I use the notion of a rigid designator, I do not imply that the object referred to necessarily exists. All I mean is that in any possible world where the object in question does exist, in any situation where the object would exist, we use the designator in question to designate that object. In a situation where the object does not exist, then we should say that the designator has no referent and that the object in question so designated does not exist — Kripke
Objects are individuated by the network of relations that contextualize them. If you change one relatum, you change the object's individuation conditions. So, the individuation conditions may not return the same object. E.g. if I am the oldest child in the real world and in the possible world I have an older brother, the individuation condition of being the oldest child will not return me. — Dfpolis
Counterfactual propositions can be judged on the basis of real-world potencies. Steve would have enjoyed the trip even if he did not go on it because he is actually disposed to enjoy such trips. If we did not know his relevant dispositions, we could not say whether he enjoyed the trip or not. So, there is no need for possible worlds talk to deal with counterfactuals. — Dfpolis
I was thinking of propositions as Fregean propositions: or as ways the world (or aspects of the world) might conceivably be thought to be. — Pierre-Normand
Of course, the very same proposition P can be the content of different sorts attitudes other than judgements, such as the hope that P, the fear that P, the conjecture that P, the antecedent of the conditional judgement that if P then Q, etc. — Pierre-Normand
It seems to me that proper names (and every other sort of singular referring expression or device, such as demonstratives, indexicals, definite descriptions, etc.) can be construed both as referring to particulars and to intelligible aspects of reality. — Pierre-Normand
There is no way, on my view, to refer to any empirical object other than referring to it as an intelligible aspect of reality. — Pierre-Normand
we can't refer to (or think of) a determinate object without subsuming it under some determinate sortal concept that expresses this object's specific criteria of persistence and individuation. — Pierre-Normand
that although the references of both names don't change (and still remain numerically identical to each other), the user of those names, who previously was using them with distinct senses, now comes to be able to (and indeed becomes rationally obligated) to use them both with the same Fregean sense since she can no longer rationally judge something to be truly predicated of one without her also judging it to be truly predicated of the other. — Pierre-Normand
It seems to me that you are using "materially the same" and "formally the same" roughly in the same way in which a Fregean would use "having the same reference" and "having the same sense", respectively. — Pierre-Normand
I am unsure how this follows since I don't hold the world (or objects) to be something other than the intelligible world (or intelligible objects). We don't have empirical or cognitive access to pure noumena. — Pierre-Normand
Does this sentence literally mean that "gato" means "cat?" No – it just means "the cat is sleeping." However, from the true utterance of that sentence in that context, I learn something other than the literal content of the sentence, viz. something about how the words used to express its literal content are used. — Snakes Alive
And indeed in saying such a thing, my primary intention may to to impart this information, not the (trivial) necessary proposition. — Snakes Alive
Putting, "the hope that p" in the same category as p is surely an error. Why? Because <the hope that p> is a concept, while <p> is a judgement. Judgements make assertions about states of affairs and so can be true or false, but concepts make no assertions and can be neither true nor false, only instantiated or not. Thus, the judgement <p> has a very different logical status than the concept <the hope that p>. — Dfpolis
I would say that, in normal intercourse, the contingent meaning is the literal meaning. In fact, until the contingent meaning is grasped, the trivial necessary meaning cannot be grasped. — Dfpolis
You have not commented on my claim that proper names need not refer to individuals simpliciter, but to individuals as known -- because covert guises do not elicit the idea expressed by the name. — Dfpolis
Sorry for the late response, busy few days. — MindForged
Except that our justification about what's possible and what's not is usually grounded in the same thing as what we justify our belief about the actual world. — MindForged
P is possible with respect to a set of facts or propositions, S, if P does not contradict S.
I do think "facts" should be restricted to intelligible reality. — Dfpolis
This makes total nonsense of everyday uses of modality. — MindForged
gnoring the fact that outside of modal realism possible worlds aren't postulated to be literal places, your criticism is clearly that lack of epistemic access to possible worlds is a problem for using possible world semantics. — MindForged
My point was that we don't have direct access to the actual world either — MindForged
So if I'm eight years old and I say "I could be a doctor", this can be understood as saying that there is some possible world (however you understand those to be) where I am in fact an MD. — MindForged
And then say I eventually do become a doctor, meaning the actual world is one such possible world where my claim turned out true. Well that's perfectly obvious justification for my original modal statement being thought true. — MindForged
Whether it's conceivability or similarity or perception, there are any number of proposed ways one can access possible worlds — MindForged
"access" here is not causal, other worlds aren't "out there" acting on us in the actual world any more than other abstract objects act on us to give us access to them. — MindForged
There's no reason to suppose that our sensory representation of an object is identical to how our sense's are modified by the object in question — MindForged
It's not identical, you're simply pointing out an inverse relationship — MindForged
But the point being made is there's absolutely no way to know that our representation of the small amount of sensory data our representational apparatus uses to construct our perception is infallibly done. — MindForged
Without that infallibility, we don't have even quasi-access to the world. — MindForged
Oh my god, so your argument is, literally, that the world "possible" is there. — MindForged
P is possible if there is at least one world in which P is the case — MindForged
— Dfpolis
Still, they are not our world, as, if they are different in any way, they are not identical to our actual world. Any world that is not identical to our world is a different world. As each is a different world, each (actual or potential) object in them is a different object from any object in out actual world. — Dfpolis
The worlds aren't identical, that wasn't my claim. But the object with the name "Venus" is picked out by the same name no matter the world. — MindForged
Still, they are not our world, as, if they are different in any way, they are not identical to our actual world. Any world that is not identical to our world is a different world. As each is a different world, each (actual or potential) object in them is a different object from any object in out actual world. — Dfpolis
The worlds aren't identical, that wasn't my claim. But the object with the name "Venus" is picked out by the same name no matter the world. — MindForged
"The oldest child [in a particular family]" is description, not a proper name, — MindForged
"Disposed" is a modal notion itself, meaning to be "inclined towards" or something one might do given their characteristics. — MindForged
I am not subsuming the hope that P under the same category as P. — Pierre-Normand
judgements are intentional attitudes ... the very same proposition P can be the content of different sorts attitudes other than judgements, such as the hope that P, the fear that P, ... — Pierre-Normand
Judgements don't make assertions. People make judgements and assertions, and they can assert the contents of the judgements that they are making. They can also assert the negation of a judgement that they are making, in which case they are lying. — Pierre-Normand
It's true that we are sometimes unaware of what names mean — Snakes Alive
In this account p, the hope that p, the fear that P, etc. are all equally in the category of attitudes. Have I misunderstood, or have you changed your position? — Dfpolis
it can be the very same thing (that P) that is being feared, hoped or judged. — Pierre-Normand
To judge <A is B> is to think that the source of concept <A> is identically the source of concept <B>, so the cupola(sic) in the proposition expressing a judgement expresses identity, not between A and B, but in the source of A and B. Similarly, to judge <A is not B> is to think that the source of concept <A> is not identically the source of concept <B>. — Dfpolis
Yes. My point is that judging is not an attitude. It intends a real state in a way that the attitudes you enumerate need not. — Dfpolis
The 'is' of identity isn't the copula. — Pierre-Normand
its function isn't to signify the numerical identity between the references of "the apple" and of "green" — Pierre-Normand
But if they are object dependent, as Kripke argue is the case for proper names, then they are rigid designators and the identity expressed by "A is B" is necessary. — Pierre-Normand
I think I am attacking Kripke's claim directly.
Two things can be can be dependent on the same, singular object, but still depend on different aspects of that object. If so, then what they depend on may be physically inseparable, but logically distinct. We can't physically separate Clark Kent from Superman, or Hesperus from Phosphorus, but we can see that being a reporter is not being a man of steel, and that appearing in the evening is not appearing in the morning.
So being dependent on the same singular object is insufficient to establish conceptual identity. — Dfpolis
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.