• frank
    15.8k
    I think that if we try to pick out certain essential properties we might end up just where Quine warned: that essence is just a matter of how we describe a thing.

    I could try to lay out Quine versus Kripke on the issue.
  • Banno
    25k
    I'm not at all comfortable with this reemergence of essences.

    SO water was first identified by a bunch of "phenomenological" characteristics. Then it was found that water was Hydrogen Dioxide. This chemical structure is an a posteriori necessity.

    Should we come across a substance with the same phenomenological characteristics, and find that it has a different chemical structure, then the correct grammar according to Kripke is to say that we have a different substance, one that is not water but looks and feels the same. PArt of the essence of water is being hydrogen dioxide.

    One the face of it, this is fine.
  • Banno
    25k
    Quine rejected essentialism and necessity because they clouded other philosophical issues. Has Kripke's grammar removed the clouding?
  • frank
    15.8k
    Quine rejected essentialism and necessity because they clouded other philosophical issues. Has Kripke's grammar removed the clouding?Banno

    Could you say more about "clouded other philosophical issues"?
  • Banno
    25k
    Hm. I'm no expert on Quine. Given that he went so far as to deny individuals that were anything more than clumps of properties, while Kripke made the individual central, there may be a large gap here.

    Then we add Davidson.

    There's a lot here.
  • Banno
    25k
    Kripke discusses heat.

    The phenomenology and the science are not so clear...

    Just saying.
  • creativesoul
    11.9k
    He says that it is not the case that cats could turn out to be robots. That if it turned out that cats were automata, we should say that what we had thought to be cats were not cats, but robots.

    TO be a cat is necessarily to be an animal.

    SO if it turned out that the fellow we thought to be Nixon was actually an automata, then we were wrong to think he was Nixon
    Banno

    This seems quite wrong...
  • Banno
    25k
    P.125...

    So, how is it wrong?
  • Banno
    25k
    I can quite believe that cats are little demons...
  • creativesoul
    11.9k
    If it turns out the fellow we thought was Nixon was an automata, then we weren't wrong to think he was Nixon. Rather, we were quite wrong to think Nixon was anything other than an automata. He wasn't a fellow at all, unless automatas can be fellows. They can certainly be Nixon if that was the case.
  • Banno
    25k
    SO you claim that Kripke is wrong?
  • frank
    15.8k
    A description can be a rigid designator, right? The man who won the election can be a rigid designator.

    There's a joke among biblical scholars about whether Paul actually wrote all those letters and the answer is: no, it was some other guy named Paul.

    Point is, for a Biblical scholar, Paul is shorthand for a description: the guy who wrote those letters. This is an on-going issue in the ancient world where writers frequently present their work as if it was of someone famous. The name is linked to a description whereas for a fundamentalist, the name picks out an individual possibly unbound from any definite description.

    This is one of the many reasons that context will help determine if there really are some properties we should think of as essential to the entity spoken of.

    Is Kripke wanting to discover essential properties without consideration of context? If so, I don't think that will work. He's right that we cant dispense with the concept of essence because we're clearly using it in ordinary speech. That intuition should direct us toward the intricacies if ordinary speech, though.
  • creativesoul
    11.9k


    So, if it turns out that the celestial body we thought to be Pluto is not a planet, then we were wrong to think it was Pluto?

    Yeah, something is most certainly amiss with that accounting practice.
  • creativesoul
    11.9k
    SO you claim that Kripke is wrong?Banno

    I'm claiming that that bit is wrong. If we have called someone or something "X", and we later come to learn that X is not what we thought it was, it's still X. It's just that X is not what we thought it was.

    We are not wrong to call a specific celestial body in the evening "Hesperus". We are wrong to think Hesperus is a star.
  • Janus
    16.3k


    I don't have much time, so I'll keep it short. I haven't thought this through extensively; but it occurred to me that there are three ways in which we can refer to things: by descriptions, even though that referring may not be precise. The imprecision may occur, more often not in my own idea about what I refer to, but in what is conveyed to others.

    We can refer to things by pointing at them. I am thinking of referring in general as (my) attending to and my drawing (other's) attention to things (in cases where I am referring to things).

    Then apart from pointing to and describing, we have referring to (attending to and drawing attention to) things (mostly people and places, but also pets and even houses and so on) by designating (properly naming) them. Kripke refers to this by describing it as baptizing.

    In order to know what entity is being referred to by a proper name, the entity must be either pointed out to me (in its presence or by photograph or drawing or voice recording or whatever), or described to me in such a way that I am able to single it out from all others. The latter could be achieved by a false description if that description is believed by a sufficient number of other members of the linguistic community to which I belong; this is the case with historical figures, where there is no longer any possibility of meeting them.



    Another interesting point that occurred to me is that general terms for things are really proper names for generalities; for example 'tree'. 'person', 'dog' and so on, and there is usually no problem determining the reference in these cases of naming, but when there are problems (as in the 'Thylacine/ dog' example given by Banno) the problems are on account of definite descriptions (the Thylacine is a marsupial so it can't be a dog or a tiger and so on).
  • Janus
    16.3k
    He says that it is not the case that cats could turn out to be robots. That if it turned out that cats were automata, we should say that what we had thought to be cats were not cats, but robots.

    TO be a cat is necessarily to be an animal.

    SO if it turned out that the fellow we thought to be Nixon was actually an automata, then we were wrong to think he was Nixon
    Banno

    This conflates proper names for particular entities with names for general types of things. We would only be wrong to think that he was Nixon, if we stipulated that it is wrong in general to give automata proper names. What we would have been wrong about in this case is in thinking that the name 'Nixon' designated a person.
  • Banno
    25k
    Not conflate... but they are treated in much the same way. Kripke openly says this.
  • Banno
    25k
    A description can be a rigid designator, right? The man who won the election can be a rigid designator.frank

    Not as I understand it. A rigid designator picks out the very same individual in all possible worlds. But a description might change from world to world.
  • Shawn
    13.2k
    A description can be a rigid designator, right? The man who won the election can be a rigid designator.frank

    That's actually a good question. Does anyone want to address it?
  • Janus
    16.3k


    As Banno pointed out, a different person might have won the election. So the man who won the election is a rigid designator only in the actual world...but then that's not how Kripke wants to define 'rigid designator', it seems.

    On the other hand, Nixon might not have been called 'Nixon'. So, Nixon is the man who in this world is called Nixon, and also won the election. Personally, I don't think possible world semantics is of much help at all.
  • Shawn
    13.2k
    So the man who won the election is a rigid designator only in the actual world...Janus

    Yeah; but, quantification can occur across possible words, so meta-logically you could even have states of affairs as obtaining (not instantiating) for all possible worlds. This is where I think, the cart has been placed in front of the horse. We should treat possible states of affairs and descriptions as ontologically above particulars (clumps of things) and individuals.
  • Janus
    16.3k
    We should treat possible states of affairs and descriptions as ontologically above particulars (clumps of things) and individuals.Wallows

    Yes, but we can only imagine possible or counterfactual states of affairs as involving actual particulars and individuals. 'What if that house had burned down' is not the same as 'what if that house had never existed'. There must be some minimum of actuality in our counterfactual imaginings or it just becomes 'what if everything had been different' and then the whole notion of counterfactuality is without any reference to actuality, and hence becomes meaningless.
  • Janus
    16.3k


    How much does "much the same way" have to be before it becomes the same way, and hence and example of conflation, or subsumption?
  • Shawn
    13.2k
    Yes, but we can only imagine possible or counterfactual states of affairs as involving actual particulars and individuals.Janus

    This isn't necessarily so. Or is it, according to Kripke?

    'What if that house had burned down' is not the same as 'what if that house had never existed'.Janus

    Well, I tend to take quantification of particulars (like the house) as representative of assigning them a name in the structure of the world through adhering to treating circumstances and states of affairs in logical space.

    There must be some minimum of actuality in our counterfactual imaginings or it just becomes 'what if everything had been different' and then the whole notion of counterfactuality is without any reference to actuality, and hence becomes meaningless.Janus

    So, we're getting into metaphysics. I think, that we can treat any state of affairs, as tantamount to a 'name'. Just, that the de-re/de-dicto assertion crops up when speaking about existential quantification from a birds-eye perspective or from a particular individual.
  • Banno
    25k
    Can't see why that's a problem, considered extensionally. Which is what Kripke is doing.
  • Banno
    25k
    Seems to me you are missing this.
  • Janus
    16.3k


    Can you explain why you don't think it is a problem?
  • Snakes Alive
    743
    A description can be a rigid designator, if its descriptive material happens to pick out the same individual in every world. This can be done pending your view on the necessity of numbers, for example, using a description like "the successor of 2," which rigidly picks out the number 3, or by using a technical device like a modal actualizer, so that "the actual, current president of the US" picks out Trump in all worlds.

    For the most part, descriptions made use of in natural languages are not rigid designators. But this is a contingent, and so interesting, fact about language. In constructing an artificial language, there is no problem with constructing rigid descriptions.
  • Shawn
    13.2k
    A description can be a rigid designator, if its descriptive material happens to pick out the same individual in every world.Snakes Alive

    Yeah, so my point seems to be that descriptions or more aptly states of affairs are as important as individuals, as individuals cannot exist without descriptions of their states of affairs. I don't like the hard line being drawn between the two. You can have both co-existing, and drawing a hard line tends to make people confused about what's being talked about.

    using a technical device like a modal actualizer, so that "the actual, current president of the US" picks out Trump in all worlds.Snakes Alive

    Can you expand on this "modal actualizer" thing?

    For the most part, descriptions made use of in natural languages are not rigid designators. But this is a contingent, and so interesting, fact about language. In constructing an artificial language, there is no problem with constructing rigid descriptions.Snakes Alive

    Interesting. I have no idea what a language with contingent properties being rigid designators would even look like. Do you have an example in mind?
  • Banno
    25k
    Well, it seems to work. What's the problem?

    (Edit: Indeed, I'm not too sure what it is we are talking about here. But that's been the case for most of the discussion. The objections seem based on misreadings or misapprehensions.)
bold
italic
underline
strike
code
quote
ulist
image
url
mention
reveal
youtube
tweet
Add a Comment

Welcome to The Philosophy Forum!

Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.