to provide a suitable account of essences in ontological terms using modal language, — Banno
Fine moved essentialists over to epistemology and now seek to give an account of essences as how we know (understand, conceive, etc.) that something is what it is. — Banno
What we take as a simple depends on the task at hand - on what we are doing. I read PI as a rejection of the Augustinian essentialism expressed in §1, and might roughly be expressed as a rejection of real essences. — Banno
It is not obvious that such a view is at odds with Kit FIne's essentialism. — Banno
Perhaps contrary to most of the discussion so far, I also think this discussion is almost orthogonal to how reference works. The intersection might be somewhere in the region of Evans' critique of a causal theory of reference that sees no place for predication or contextual cues in referring behaviours. — fdrake
I think you can productively read it in the following manner - things have natures which constrain and partially determine how they behave. When you describe such a thing or process, that means setting out that nature in an act of understanding it. The understanding of the thing or process determines which properties we express as necessary to it, that which it could not be understood as it is without. — fdrake
It seems like a recognition of the subjective aspect of the act of understanding is what is being overlooked in some of the opposing viewpoints. — Leontiskos
Maybe. I don't see much by way of an argument in favour of essences, a reason that we need take them into account. I agree, of course, that our language games are constrained by the way things are, although that way of expressing it lacks a certain symmetry that I take as central – it's not just that we are constrained by the world, but also that we also constrain how things are by our speech acts. Here, I'm not thinking of Sapir-Whorf, so much as of money and boarders and social status, the paraphernalia of our social lives. So I usually prefer to talk of our language being embedded in the world, something akin to a form of life or confirmation holism.I think your cynical self is asserting fundamental presuppositions which the article is challenging, rather than engaging with them on their own terms. — fdrake
I think I can see what you mean there. Though I read it the other way - how Fine is using the vocabulary of essence makes meaning "thingly" or "concrete" - puts the locus of sinigication/expression closer to the described object or act. Like the essence of Socrates is constrained by who Socrates was. — fdrake
I don't see much by way of an argument in favour of essences, a reason that we need take them into account. — Banno
Anyway, given that the discussion has moved away from the Fine article I might leave this topic where it is. — Banno
Well, he did that, in that I had more or less taken Essence as a dead end, but what we have here gives it a bit of freshness. It harks back to some of the stuff I did on Individuation in my Honours year.I think he wants to blow open a hole and pour a different flavour of essence in. — fdrake
I would have said that our discussion of essences commenced here: ↪Leontiskos; — Banno
I don't think one can read Fine as rejecting modal accounts of essence, so much as refining them. Otherwise one would be rejecting the conception of essence as necessary and sufficient... — Banno
So it seems that he believes there's some subset of the necessary (possible worlds sense) truths which are necessary (essential) to an entity's being. — fdrake
typo — Leontiskos
Hmm. Any account of necessity that as incompatible with modal theory would need a pretty substantial defence. Fine's is certainly in line with modal theory, but at one stage you seem'd to reject Kripke, which would be very brave in this context.But modal logic does not have a copyright on the word "necessary." — Leontiskos
I have not understood how essences as definitions differs in salient ways from essences in terms of necessary properties. Isn't a definition a set of necessary and sufficient properties? — Banno
One way to cash this out is to say that risibility or the ability to learn grammar supervene on rationality, and it is rationality that belongs to the essence because it is explanatorily fundamental. Thus a human being is not defined as "A risible animal" or "An animal capable of learning grammar," but rather, "A rational animal." This contains and explains the others.
Aquinas claims that, in a similar way, delight supervenes on happiness, for happiness is essentially the possession of a fitting good and not the possession of delight, and yet delight always follows upon and attends happiness such that they appear indistinguishable.
I should point out yet again that it is one thing to disagree with some real definition and another to disagree with essentialism itself. The latter is much more contentious and difficult, and would seem to involve the claim that no properties are explanatorily prior or posterior. — Leontiskos
As I'm reading Fine a definition is necessary, because Fine accepts the argument that if something is not necessary then it is not essential, but necessity is not sufficient.
Or, if we're going by way of Aristotelian essence, then I'm not sure "sufficiency" is the conceptual mark we should be using at all (hence my divergence into Aristotelian causes for determining whether something named has an essence at all) — Moliere
A definition is a true description of an essence, which is a property which is explanatorily prior to other properties, including the necessary ones (like the Singleton Socrates). — Moliere
Leontiskos do you accept the argument that if some predicate is not necessary of a name that then that same predicate is not an essence of the name? (only asking because then we could add to this list to say that essences are necessary, though there are necessary predicates which are not essential) — Moliere
We think we understand something simpliciter (and not in the sophistical way, incidentally) when we think we know of the explanation because of which the object holds that it is its explanation, and also that it is not possible for it to be otherwise. It is plain, then, that to understand is something of this sort. And indeed, people who do not understand think they are in such a condition, and those who do understand actually are. Hence if there is understanding simpliciter of something, it is impossible for it to be otherwise. — Aristotle, Posterior Analytics, 71b9 (Chapter 2), tr. Barnes
Let us return to the honey bee example to make our point. With some study (and or a good Oxford dictionary) I could come to know in a fairly rigorous manner that a honey bee is defined as “a stinging, winged insect that collects nectar and pollen, produces wax and honey, and lives in large communities/colonies.” In this definition, the genus is insect meaning an arthropod with six legs and one or two pairs of wings. An arthropod is an invertebrate with segmented body, an exoskeleton, and jointed limbs. ‘Stinging, ‘winged,’ ‘collecting nectar and pollen,’ ‘producing wax and honey,’ and ‘living in large colonies,’ are differentia which distinguish the honey bee from other members of the same genus, and are taken from the categories of action, quality, and possession/habit.[74] Having these attributes (secondary beings) is the cause of some individuals (primary beings) in nature being honey bees. When I run into such primary buzzing beings, I know them with a very high degree of accuracy, through [this definition]. What is key is that, any time one has predicated a definition of a honey bee in the field, which is an expression (λόγος/logos) of his understanding it in itself and as distinct from other animals and species of its own genus. . . — Daniel Wagner, The Logical Terms of Sense Realism, p. 53
“Difference” is an essential attribute added to the genus and constituting the species (e.g., ‘with three equal sides’ differentiates the equilateral from the isosceles and the scalene). — Daniel Wagner, The Logical Terms of Sense Realism, p. 27
The meaning of a proper name is incomplete without some account of the way that proper names are used to reference real objects. — Leontiskos
Graham Harman is a contemporary philosopher associated with the philosophical movement known as speculative realism and object-oriented ontology (OOO). His ideas regarding objects are central to his philosophical framework. Harman's conception of objects departs from traditional philosophies that often emphasize human experience as the primary focus. Instead, he shifts the focus towards the objects themselves and their relationships.
Object-Centric Philosophy:
Harman proposes an object-centric philosophy, where objects are considered as the fundamental building blocks of reality. He argues that objects are autonomous entities that exist independently of our perception or knowledge of them. These objects have their own unique qualities, essences, and interactions with other objects.
Withdrawal and Vicarious Causation:
Harman introduces the idea of "withdrawal," suggesting that objects have an inherent depth that eludes complete human understanding. According to Harman, an object's true essence is never fully accessible to other objects. This withdrawal indicates that objects possess an inner reality that is not directly perceivable, and interactions between objects occur on a surface level.
He also proposes the concept of "vicarious causation," where objects influence each other indirectly through their appearances or interactions. Objects do not directly access the inner reality of other objects; instead, they interact through the surface qualities or manifestations of those objects.
Object Relations and Networks:
Harman emphasizes the relationships and interactions between objects. Objects, as autonomous entities, interact with one another, forming networks of relations. However, these relations are not exhaustive or fully determinative of an object's essence. An object retains its autonomy and uniqueness even within relationships.
Fourfold Structure:
Harman proposes a fourfold structure to describe the relationships between objects. This structure includes real objects (existing in the world), sensual objects (perceived by other objects), real qualities (inherent properties of objects), and sensual qualities (perceived qualities of objects). These elements contribute to the complex interplay and understanding of objects and their relationships.
Object-Oriented Ontology (OOO):
OOO, a philosophical movement that Harman is associated with, emphasizes that everything is an object, including not just physical entities but also abstract concepts and events. OOO advocates for treating all entities equally, acknowledging their autonomous existence and inherent uniqueness.
he attempt to limit oneself to the "discursive context" collapses on itself whenever an act of expression expresses an object. — Leontiskos
For example, a proper name is a 'rigid designator' which means that the object it identifies is ostensibly unique, and accounting for the manner in which one identifies such an object inevitably draws one outside the "discursive context." — Leontiskos
The meaning of a proper name is incomplete without some account of the way that proper names are used to reference real objects. — Leontiskos
That is to say, for example, in Harman, the "essence" of an object is always "withdrawn" or "hidden" such that it cannot be interacted with. — schopenhauer1
I guess that goes back to the sense/reference discussion you were having with Banno earlier. Specifically whether/how reference leverages concepts or practices that are (often) exclusively associated with sense. — fdrake
I agree with that, even though it's outside the scope of the thread. I believe that any speech act which refers does so on the basis of a history of use outside its immediate context, and how the referent is individuated+interpreted is informed by that history and the referent's nature. So I believe that the association of names (like "Socrates") with referents (Socrates) is done through an interpretation+individuation of the referent, and that the discursive contexts which refer to that referent must keep associating a "sufficiently like" (weasel words) interpretation+individuation of the referent to fix+continue that particular sense/referent/reference relation. — fdrake
Though there's a rub. Like if you and your friend are having a disagreement about whether the blegbleg really is a shmooblydoo or a bigglewiggle, another friend observing the disagreement can successfully refer to the blegbleg by aping their reference, even without their own understanding of the blegbleg's sense, conditions of individuation, or its real nature. — fdrake
How does that rub relate to the thread? Who knows, it just seems to. — fdrake
A basic question here is: What provides the surest starting point? Harman's objects? Aristotle's substances? Wittgenstein's linguistics? — Leontiskos
This video might help as a good jumping off point for a Harman's view of objects. Perhaps we can have a discussion on it? — schopenhauer1
That seems reasonable, but of course the devil’s in the details. — Leontiskos
On the other hand, your post was comparing Fine’s Aristotelian essentialism to Banno’s linguistic approach, which is also different than the topic of this thread. I suppose that is what I was responding to. — Leontiskos
I would have thought “...and the referent’s nature” was meant to circumvent such a rub. — Leontiskos
Great posts, by the way. Is there a thread where I can ask about your philosophical background? — Leontiskos
I have been pondering Michael Sugrue's claim that Anglo-American philosophy starts from the external world and can never manage to bridge the gap to the mind, whereas continental philosophy starts from the subject/mind and can never manage to bridge the gap to the external world. He makes it, for instance, in this video on Husserl at 44:59. It seems like this discussion is somewhat related. — Leontiskos
This is an incorrect formulation of the ontology-epistemology question, which I've seen quite often. With the "How is it that the world exists" you really mean to ask "how is it that we know that there's anything that exists. Very different questions.But anyways, to the broader point, much of philosophy revolves around how it is that the world exists without an observer, or sometimes formulated as a human observer. — schopenhauer1
This is an incorrect formulation of the ontology-epistemology question, which I've seen quite often. With the "How is it that the world exists" you really mean to ask "how is it that we know that there's anything that exists. Very different questions.
Your question, as you posted it here, is about the "why" does the world exist. Epistemology deals with our knowledge of existence. Which one are you asking? — L'éléphant
much of philosophy revolves around how it is that the world exists without an observer, or sometimes formulated as a human observer. — schopenhauer1
You are combining both the questions about whether the world exists (or whether there is existence) and how do we know that the world exists.In other words, where is the "incorrect formulation" stemming from, and why do you think it implies a "why"? — schopenhauer1
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.