So, without observers, nothing is related to anything whatever. That is the thrust of the OP — Wayfarer
As per above, this question can be asked not only of patterns, but of phenomena generally..........................There are patterns that appear in inorganic nature, in crystals, snowflakes, larva formations etc. — Wayfarer
The book’s argument begins with the British empiricists who raised our awareness of the fact that we have no direct contact with physical reality, but it is the mind that constructs the form and features of objects. It is shown that modern cognitive science brings this insight a step further by suggesting that shape and structure are not internal to objects, but arise in the observer.
↪Philosophim What a cromulent response! :smile:
This just pushes the question back a level -- why is it effective? — J
Wouldn't it make more sense for you (if I've understood your thinking here) to abandon any talk of accuracy or truth? — J
Suppose bleen is "green and "first observed" during or before 2004," or "blue and 'first observed' after 2004." Could you go walk around where you live and determine what was grue or bleen? — Count Timothy von Icarus
Suppose there is a famous green landmark in your town and it got flattened by a tornado in 2006. It was rebuilt with largely with materials salvaged from the original, but has a substantial amount of new material. Is it bleen or grue? — Count Timothy von Icarus
What if only small parts of it were replaced each year since 2004? — Count Timothy von Icarus
A theorem (as opposed to an equation that's given a real-world interpretation) isn't described as effective, it's described as true, or at least provable in L. — J
Do you want to abandon that way of talking? If a correspondence theory of truth demands that we do so, I'd argue that it represents a reductio ad absurdum and should be rejected on that ground. — J
If a correspondence theory of truth demands that we do so, I'd argue that it represents a reductio ad absurdum and should be rejected on that ground. — J
What would be the point of limiting ourselves in this way? — J
If you understood the essential properties and context of what grue and bleen is, then yes
the case of grue and blue, we're not asking what the definitions should be, we already know what they mean. Our decision is then, "should we use grue or blue"? And I mentioned earlier, as long as both are accurate to the point they are not contradicted by reality, its really a personal choice. It may be as simple as, "I like one word more than another" or as complicated as, "Those dirty grueians are a stupid people that I find inferior. Blue is obviously superior and the 'right' way to identify a color."
If you understood the essential properties and context of what grue and bleen is, then yes
You can tell when things were created down to the year just by looking at them? When you drive through a neighborhood you know the year each house was built just as readily as the the color it is painted? — Count Timothy von Icarus
This seems like "because difference is not a logical contradiction it is arbitrary." — Count Timothy von Icarus
Human languages distinguish between shape and color — Count Timothy von Icarus
If someone argued that chemistry should be split into chemistry done by people with blue eyes and chemistry done by people with other colored eyes, or argued that we should divide chemistry into pre and post 1990 chemistries, or a chemistry of federally recognized holidays, they would be rebuffed for non-arbitrary reasons. — Count Timothy von Icarus
This might be filtered through "personal preference," but personal preference doesn't spring from the aether uncaused and neither do our concepts and languages. — Count Timothy von Icarus
three kids who want to play with the same toys — Leontiskos
I go to the car dealership and I am offered whole cars. They don't let me buy a half car for half the money. — Leontiskos
I agree with the introduction to Pinter's book Mind and Cosmic Order
The book’s argument begins with the British empiricists who raised our awareness of the fact that we have no direct contact with physical reality, but it is the mind that constructs the form and features of objects. It is shown that modern cognitive science brings this insight a step further by suggesting that shape and structure are not internal to objects, but arise in the observer.
I read this as saying that patterns exist in the mind, not the world. — RussellA
The question raised is whether a distinctively mathematical explanation (DME) for physical facts truly exists – whether “the facts under question arise from a degree of mathematical necessity considered stronger than that of contingent causal laws.”
If you substitute “logical” for “mathematical,” you can see that the question is very much about whether our analytical (for lack of a better term) knowledge imposes itself on the physical world in a way that is genuinely explanatory. Jha et al. think not, and present a strong argument that all purported DMEs are actually rephrased or disguised versions of the causal explanations that ordinarily obtain. — J
So what I think needs to be questioned is why we think a hard and fast separation can be made between mind and world in the first place. — Wayfarer
I think the sentiment against this relationship goes back to the same basically nominalist and empiricist attitude that animates most analytical philosophy, which is unwilling to admit that ideas - mathematical ideas, logical principles - might possess any kind of intrinsic reality which can't be reduced to 'contingent causal laws'. — Wayfarer
Jha et al. argue that various presuppositions such as the principle of mass conservation and the physical integrity of individual objects (this has to be assumed in order to get “whole and unbroken”) — J
Q3: Why must the LNC hold (under the usual constraints) as a principle of thought?
Q4: Why can’t my cat be on my lap and in Paris at the same time? (constraint: I live in Maryland) — J
The fact your cat can't be simultaneously be in Maryland and Paris is because you have chosen to define "Maryland" and "Paris" in ways that are mutually exclusive and so one is not the other.
But there is no need to do this for any physical things, whether in the trivial senses we talk about all the time or in more fundamental ways; for instance, some quantum interpretations will ascribe an ontological realism to the idea that a thing can be in two places at once in the sense suggested by traditional conceptions of quantum superposition.
This is Jha et al’s argument, more or less. Math only appears to be causal when we state the problem in terms that remove, or demote to “background conditions,” the physical constraints that actually provide the explanation. — J
We haven't chosen this arbitrarily though. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Well, I suppose ones attitude towards reductionism and smallism will probably guide the extent to which one thinks quantum foundations is particularly relevant here. On the one hand, there seems to be increasing consensus around the idea that there is no hard dividing line between "quantum and classical worlds." On the other, there is strong consensus in physics that the same living cat cannot be simultaneously in College Park and strolling the the Champs-Élysées.
If we are unsure that being in Rome, New York differs from Rome, Italy, I think we have left empiricism and the natural sciences behind a long time ago.
40m — Count Timothy von Icarus
But for there to be a pair of apples, this presupposes a prior relation between the individual apples.
Jha et al are asking the very question about whether logical principles can be more than contingently causal. They’re not at all “unwilling “ to entertain the idea; it’s the topic of their paper. They do end up arguing against it, true. — J
He is the author of the blockbuster bestseller Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature (Oxford, 2009), which is soon to be a major motion picture. More recently, he has written the iridescently lyrical “Because Without Cause: Non-Causal Explanations in Science and Mathematics” (Oxford, 2016). Earlier he wrote the gripping page-turner An Introduction to the Philosophy of Physics: Locality, Fields, Energy, and Mass (Blackwell, 2002) and the steamy, heart-rending Natural Laws in Scientific Practice (Oxford, 2000).
There is a major debate as to whether there are non-causal mathematical explanations of physical facts that show how the facts under question arise from a degree of mathematical necessity considered stronger than that of contingent causal laws. We focus on Marc Lange’s account of distinctively mathematical explanations to argue that purported mathematical explanations are essentially causal explanations in disguise and are no different from ordinary applications of mathematics. This is because these explanations work not by appealing to what the world must be like as a matter of mathematical necessity but by appealing to various contingent causal facts. — Mathematical Explanations...
Newton's laws of motion are effective because they model the predicable behaviours of bodies in mathematical terms. Is that what a 'non-causal mathematical explanation' is referring to? — Wayfarer
Yes, that’s right. A non-causal mathematical explanation, like the one Marc Lange discusses, refers to an explanation that doesn’t involve direct physical causality (like a collision between two bodies) but instead shows how the behavior of a system arises due to deeper mathematical structures or constraints, like Newton’s laws. The laws describe what must happen, given certain conditions (modal necessity), without directly causing events in the same sense as physical interactions. The debate focuses on whether these are truly non-causal or still ultimately rely on contingent, causal facts. — ChatGPT
So they're disputing modal necessity? — Wayfarer
Yes, the authors of the article are disputing the idea of modal necessity as a basis for certain mathematical explanations. They argue that purportedly non-causal mathematical explanations, such as those Lange describes, are still grounded in contingent causal facts rather than being purely based on mathematical necessity. The debate centers on whether these explanations genuinely reflect a stronger necessity that transcends specific physical causes or whether they are simply causal explanations in disguise, relying on ordinary applications of mathematics to model physical interactions. — ChatGPT
What about thinking of them as generalised abstractions that enable accurate predictions of physical behaviour? — Wayfarer
Thinking of mathematical laws, like Newton’s laws of motion, as generalized abstractions makes sense. These laws provide abstract, generalized models that capture patterns of physical behavior across various contexts. While they don’t directly cause events (as physical collisions do), they enable highly accurate predictions by abstracting essential relationships (like force, mass, and acceleration). This framework helps us understand physical systems by focusing on the underlying structure and constraints that govern behavior, allowing for a broad application across many scenarios, even without invoking specific causal events. — ChatGPT
They argue that purportedly non-causal mathematical explanations, such as those Lange describes, are still grounded in contingent causal facts rather than being purely based on mathematical necessity.
It's the 'grounded in' which is the point of contention. They undermine the ontogical priority of logical necessity by making it appear derivative. — Wayfarer
Exactly—this is the heart of the dispute. The authors challenge the ontological priority of logical or mathematical necessity, arguing that these so-called "non-causal" explanations are actually derivative of causal facts. By framing mathematical necessity as contingent upon physical interactions, they seek to undermine the idea that such necessity has an independent or more fundamental status. Instead, they claim these mathematical abstractions are useful tools for modeling, but ultimately rest on causal realities rather than constituting a separate, superior explanatory framework. — ChatGPT
1) So, the neo-logos philosophies might say something like, "If nature has patterns, and our language has patterns, and we are derived from nature, it may be the case that our language is a necessary outcome of a more foundational logic". Thus, the logic would not be transcendental, but (for lack of a better term) "immanent" in nature, not some outside observing entity that is detached from it.
2) Kant never explains why our minds would compose such a world, but evolution does.
3) Wouldn't evolution put a connection between the efficacy of the mind and the world?
4) But what is the world outside of an observer?
5) Otherwise it's just "I have believe" without an explanation, which though is valid in terms of asserting an idea, is not necessarily valid as an fully informed reason for why you think that way. — schopenhauer1
That is, how can being be in one sense "one," i.e. everything interacts with everything else, there are no truly isolated systems — Count Timothy von Icarus
If a correspondence theory of truth demands that we do so, I'd argue that it represents a reductio ad absurdum and should be rejected on that ground.
— J
Very harsh. The word "true" has different meanings in different contexts — RussellA
So we shouldn't limit a robust correspondence theory to "facts about the world" — J
Therefore, we can use the Correspondence Theory and say that the proposition "there are infinitely many prime numbers" is true because there are infinitely many prime numbers. — RussellA
Kant argues in the CPR that we have transcendental knowledge of a world the other side of our senses, but never explains how this could work. — RussellA
how can we transcend our senses in order to know what has caused these experiences in our senses? — RussellA
For me, the problem about objects existing in a world independent of any observer, is, what mechanism is there in such a world independent of any observer that relates atom A to atom B but doesn't relate atom A to atom C?
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.