They claim that certain expressions of intolerance should be banned, which I consider equivalent to applying violence against their expression, as this is the only way a government can enforce law. I think maybe people are not understanding the definition of violence? To elaborate, I could expand it to "physical force likely to cause harm when non-compliant", examples of such force would be tasers, K-9's, tear gas, rubber bullets etc. which are used against those who resist arrest/imprisonment. It should be considered the same type of violence that enforces taxes and all other laws. — Ourora Aureis
intolerant philosophies ; as long as we can counter them by rational argument and keep them in check by public opinion, suppression would certainly be most unwise. — Ourora Aureis
Ideas dont kill people, people kill people. — Ourora Aureis
You are arguing for the use of physical violence by the state upon the individual for the expression of certain beliefs. — Ourora Aureis
I think this touches on a crucial question: Is free speech a value in itself, or a means to an end?
In the U.S., there's often this almost sacred reverence for free speech as an absolute principle. But I’d argue that speech is only valuable insofar as it sustains the conditions for open, inclusive, and rational discourse. Once it begins to actively undermine those conditions – by dehumanizing people, inciting hatred, or flooding the space with bad-faith noise – its “freedom” becomes self-defeating.
For example: should a philosophy forum tolerate someone saying “I hope women no longer exist in 10,000 years”? Or “Blacks are genetically inferior”? Or “The Holocaust didn’t happen”? These aren’t edgy thoughts. They’re acts of exclusion. They don’t provoke thought – they shut thought down.
Take a practical case: imagine a female newcomer logs into this forum, excited to engage with deep philosophical topics, and then stumbles across a thread where someone writes “Women are a waste of time", “They make terrible friends and even worse girlfriends." or one of the other. That’s not just distasteful – it’s a message loud and clear: "You’re not really human here. You’re a problem to be explained, not a person to be heard."
Free speech isn’t sacred. It’s instrumental. And if it’s used to destroy the conditions that make real discourse possible, then drawing lines isn’t just justified – it’s necessary. — DasGegenmittel
This is my entire point. All of these examples fail to rise to something accepted into a functional system that would be called "knowledge". All of them dissolve under a short temporal arc. A diagnostic error is not medical knowledge, AI bias is in the context of how the computer believes complicates at best. Post rationalization of a stock trade isn't thought of as persistent justified belief. — Cheshire
This is precisely what Aristotle would say re episteme. The example relies on a coincidence of accidents. Could it be reconstructed with per se predication? I don't think I've ever seen it done.
The difficulty of limiting knowledge to being is of course explaining discursive knowledge in the realm of becoming, which does seem to exist. This requires a robust metaphysics, a "metaphysics of knowledge," which is made difficult by the tendency of modern thought to put either epistemology (early modern) or philosophy of language (linguistic turn) before metaphysics.
I would guess we have pretty similar opinions here. We had a recent thread on this and my thoughts were:
[... alllll the Text]
When we get to the "metaphysics of knowledge" I don't even know if it is appropriate to call knowledge (or at least what is most fully knowledge) a "belief." When we are sure that there are cars in the oncoming traffic lane and that we mustn't drive into them, I think this is not simply a case of sense data + ratio (computational reason) = propositional belief. The reason we find it quite impossible to ignore such knowledge lies, IMHO, more in the co-identity of knower and known in such cases (a union). People find it impossible to believe otherwise because their intellect is "informed" by truth in the senses (sense knowledge), or what we might call the communication of actuality.
That's a fairly Aristotlian/Neoplatonic view, and less strictly Platonic of course. — Count Timothy von Icarus
It seems to me like you are getting at the role of understanding in knowledge, which has a phenomenological component. If truth just involved discursive justification and assigning the right truth values to linguistic utterances or symbolic strings, then LLMs would "know," right? — Count Timothy von Icarus
I have no clue what that's supposed to mean. — creativesoul
What is Smith's belief at the moment he forms it? — creativesoul
It does not follow from the fact that predictions are incapable of being true/false at the time they're made, that there can be no such thing as knowledge in cases involving temporality and change. Assuming they're justified and believed, predictions can become true despite being incapable of being so at the time they're articulated/made. They become JTB by virtue of turning out to be true. If they turn out to be false, then they cannot be knowledge, because knowledge cannot be false. — creativesoul
Since these are statements about future events, they do not constitute knowledge but rather speculation (credence), and the result is not knowledge either, as it does not necessarily and sufficiently follow from the premises. Luck is a temporal phenomenon; the outcome could have been different: good luck (JTB) & bad luck (JFB).If his cases are examples of justified false belief, then his challenge to those formulations fails to hit the target. <-------Can we agree on that much, for now? — creativesoul
At this point, deductive reasoning is conflated with inductive reasoning, as if temporality didn’t exist. However, there are two distinct moments in time: the scenario of the original assumption (t1), and the new information that Smith also (unknowingly) has ten coins in his pocket (t2; quasi-empirical). This thematic complex refers to what I call conceptual coincidence and further break down with reference to truth-makers. But there’s a lot more going on in this example: e.g., the non-parallel construction of definiendum and definiens & the Leibniz Law violation.As the key meaningful part of Smith's own belief articulation, "The man with ten coins in his pocket" picks out one and only one individual. Jones is the ONLY man that Smith believes will get the job, regardless of pocket content. Thus, Smith's belief, as Gettier articulated, is true if and only if, Jones gets the job and has ten coins in his pocket.
On the contrary, when P is examined as a proposition that is completely divorced from Smith's inference, "The man with ten coins in his pocket will get the job", is true if/when any man with ten coins in his pocket gets the job. This reasoning shows that there are very different sets of truth conditions regarding P, depending on whether P is considered in isolation from the believer(Smith) or examined with consideration of that.
Hence, the first case rests on judging Smith's belief using truth conditions of what is not(as does the second case). It is only as a result of not noticing and highlighting that conflation, that it seemed/seems okay to say that Smith's belief was/is true. When the inference of Smith is rightly taken into consideration "The man with ten coins in his pocket" means Jones and only Jones. Jones does not get the job. Hence, Smith's belief is justified and false. — creativesoul
Exactly. And what does that mean? There can be no such thing as knowledge in cases involving temporality and change, unless we adopt a different perspective. Gettier, and all those seeking a monastic definition of knowledge, are doomed to fail. It’s an attempt to achieve the impossible with outdated tools. We must think fundamentally differently.On my view, predictions of future events (belief about what will happen later) are capable of neither being true or false at the time they're made. — creativesoul
And in that sense, this must also be considered. There is no absolute certainty in the perception of the world. The person who sees the clock and draws an assertion from it doesn’t know at first that the clock is broken, but relies on their previously reliable everyday experience. Yet that, too, can be unreliable—comparable to the fake barn cases. Perception of reality is always only an approximation, never an absolute.This presupposes that the belief had epistemic validity to begin with. "It is three o'clock" does not follow from believing that a broken clock is working. "There is a barn" does not follow from mistaking a barn facade for a barn (believing that a fake barn is a real one). "There is a sheep in the field" does not follow from believing that a sheet is a sheep. — creativesoul
Sure, gladly—but I’m not criticizing JTB itself, but rather the use of JTB in modern contexts. My paper rehabilitates JTB for static scenarios and demonstrates why JTB must fail in dynamic ones.I may be inclined, if you like, to offer candidates of JTB that are not Gettier cases. We could then apply your concepts/reasoning to them and see what that looks like, and/or how well the criticism you levy fits a case of JTB. That could be interesting. I'm much less interested in applying criticism of JTB to cases that are not. — creativesoul
That’s very close to how I think about it. However, I also point out that the two types of knowledge are not independent from each other, but have points of integration and application: for example, rounding rules & epistemic standards and stakes.Now, I've read a good portion of the essay linked by DasGegenmittel in the op, and I think the intention is to divide knowledge into two distinct types, the eternal, unchanging type (static knowledge), and the evolving type (dynamic knowledge). I would not make a division in this way. I would say that all knowledge, just like all meaning is evolving, but there are differences of degree in the rate of change. Some might propose "ideals", which would be eternal unchanging objects of meaning, but these are imaginary, fictional, because we do not have any such unchanging ideas. So "ideals" are self-defeating, as fictions which are supposed to be eternal truths. And even ideas like that signified by "2", are changing, having come into existence at some time. And we see that there are a number of different numbering systems, like natural, rational, real, etc., and the sign has a different meaning depending on the conceptual structure of the system which provides the context of usage. — Metaphysician Undercover
The problem here is that JTB is normally conceived as static, but in this case, it is procedural. The expectation is not fulfilled, even though a JTB can initially be assumed, which then, due to its contingency, becomes a JFB, yet may still be labeled JTB due to conceptual coincidence within the framework of the truth-maker: Leibniz-law violation.But surely, if Smith's belief is a justified false belief, it is not going to count as knowledge. So what is fragile is not Smith's knowledge, but his belief. That's not a problem. — Ludwig V
Correct—JTB is already refuted by the mere existence of competing JTBs as counterexamples, which I illustrate more clearly using the Rashomon effect.I think it is important to say more about this. My view is a trifle unorthodox. It comes down to what description works for different characters in the story. Smith is thinking of the clock, as a (working) clock. Who wouldn't? But we readers who are in the know, are thinking of it as a broken clock. Of course we are - the author of the story has told us so and authors are never wrong about what is happening in their own stories. Smith obviously cannot possibly be describing (thinking of) the clock as broken and it makes nonsense of the story to attribute such a belief to them. In order to understand the story, we have to be capable of grasping the difference and its significance. There is, so far as I can see, no way around that.
It follows that the context of belief is not fully intentional. I've never seen such a concept elsewhere in philosophy, but the facts are clear. In some circumstances, we must respect the believer's description of their own belief. In others, we need to understand (and use) another description - the truth (as we see it, of course). — Ludwig V
My point was not about the truthful perception of a thing, but about differences in general. A thing can never be perceived absolutely; there are no 1:1 real-time representations.This is very doubtful, and that's the point of Kant's "a priori". Some form of abstractive power, or capacity, is necessary for, therefore prior to, sensory perception. And, since the difference between the thing-in-itself, and the perception of the thing (as a type of abstraction in the mind), is fundamental to the nature of knowledge, especially the fallibility of knowledge, we need to pay close attention to the nature of this difference in any epistemology. — Metaphysician Undercover
I suspect we think quite similarly here, though we start from different positions. I understand perception not only as a worldly, but also as a mental process—the recognition of a boundary between two things or numbers as a set (of numbers).Therefore the real meaning of mathematical symbols such as "2" may be entirely imaginary, creations of the mind which are not at all based in perceptual patterns. And I really think that this is the true nature of what is known as "pure mathematics". The mind creates categories which are not based in abstractions produced from sensory perception, but based in its own intentions. The "empty set" for example. — Metaphysician Undercover
Correct, but I would add that both sameness and difference are equally important to emphasize the definitional core of the matter. There is no delimitation without differentiation.This is Plato's point with justification. The senses deceive us, and cannot be the source for true justification. The idea that sense evidence is what justifies, is itself misleading, guiding us toward faulty justifications. We must establish principles of comparison derived from the creative, imaginative mind, which form the real basis for justification. These principles are derived from concepts of sameness rather than concepts of difference. This is why it is very important to have a very rigorous definition of "same", to start from, as that provided by the law of identity. — Metaphysician Undercover
He didn’t know it, but if we assume that, then he would be surprised—and according to the currently prevailing view of JTB, would have had knowledge by accident. And that’s exactly what you're describing.What if the individual under our consideration while pointing towards the broken clock said something like, "Hey guys! Yesterday, at exactly 2 o'clock, do you know that I believed that that broken clock was working. Yeah. Isn't that crazy? I just looked at it like I normally do and then went on about my business as usual. :lol: I even made it home on time!"
I don't see the nonsense in this, or my account of it. If it's there, could you set it out and show it to me? — creativesoul
That would indeed be strange. In the end, knowledge is—among other things and essentially—an attribution, meant to express certainty/trust so that one can act with little or no risk. JTB, in my view—as I’ve said—is rehabilitated for static scenarios within a dualistic conception of knowledge.I argue in favor of JTB. The account differs tremendously from historical convention though, in that I do not treat belief and propositions as equivalent. Nor do I treat belief and reports thereof as equivalent, self-reporting notwithstanding. Perhaps it may be a result of those differences that I can say that the characterization above fails. It's also odd for me to see another treat JTB as though it has agency. — creativesoul
Is Smith's belief accidentally true or is it false? It cannot be both. It is a problem for JTB, only if it's true.
If it is justified false belief, then it is not JTB and the problem dissolves completely. — creativesoul
The issue with this particular thread is that it grants too much to start with in granting that Gettier cases are examples of true belief. Issues with change/flux are irrelevant with respect to that. — creativesoul
What we have are competing explanations for the Gettier problem. One grants that Gettier has showed a problem with the justification aspect of JTB. That is the basis of the project. Another argues that both Gettier cases are examples of justified false belief, and thus pose no problem for JTB; case closed. You're arguing in the vein of the former, and I, the latter. — creativesoul
You clearly do not understand the charge being levied against your entire endeavor/project. — creativesoul
And even in cases where we do not, or even cannot, know the truth we have no reason to doubt there is a truth and that it is worth seeking. — Janus
Can this even be, given time passes? What could stay the same? — AmadeusD