'denotes', 'names', 'stands for', 'symbolizes'. All good. — TonesInDeepFreeze
For an n-place (n>0) relation symbol, the denotation is an n-place relation on the domain. — TonesInDeepFreeze
Tarski used "denote", but I don't think this term is strictly grammatically correct, — RussellA
I think snow is named "snow" would be better, rather than "snow" denotes snow. — RussellA
Denotes infers points to, and "snow" is doing more than pointing to snow. — RussellA
I think we could say that the extension of a predicate or function symbol is the relation or function the symbol maps to. (?) — TonesInDeepFreeze
That is semantical. — TonesInDeepFreeze
The extension of a property is the set of all things that have the property.
That is philosophical. — TonesInDeepFreeze
For an n-place (n>0) function symbol, the denotation is an n-place relation on the domain. — TonesInDeepFreeze
Whatever is meant by 'predicate' and 'property' there, you asked about model theory. — TonesInDeepFreeze
A second thread of Hochberg's article comes to something like this: a common predicate applies to several different things in virtue of a common property they possess. Now I doubt very much that Hochberg intends to deny that any two or more things have some property in common; thus for him as for the nominalist there are no two or more things such that application of a common predicate is precluded. Advocates of properties usually hold that sometimes more than one property may be common to exactly the same things; but Hochberg does not seem to be arging this point either. Rather, he seems to hold that a predicate applies initially to a property as its name, and then only derivatively to the things that have that property. The nominalist cancels out the property and treats the predicate as bearing a one-many relation directly to the several things it applies to or denotes. I cannot see that anything Hochberg says in any way discredits such a treatment or shows the need for positing properties as intervening entities.
The nominalist cancels out the property and treats the predicate as bearing a one-many relation directly to the several things it applies to or denotes. — Goodman, p49
'Snow is white' is true iff what 'snow' stands for has the property that 'white' stands for. — TonesInDeepFreeze
'Snow is white' is true iff what 'snow' stands for hasthe property that'white' standsfor [it, among other things]. — TonesInDeepFreeze
I am talking about how the spectrum — apokrisis
that allows your 50 shades of grey — apokrisis
This is confusing for sure. — apokrisis
But after the separation of the potential, you get the new thing of the possibility of a mixing. — apokrisis
So we start with a logical vagueness - an everythingness that is a nothingness. — apokrisis
We have a “greyness” in that sense. Something that is neither the one nor the other. Not bright, not dark. Not anymore blackish than it is whitish. You define what It “is” by the failure of the PNC to apply. You are in a state of radical uncertainty about what to call it, other than a vague and uncertain potential to be a contextless “anything”. It is not even a mid-tone grey as there are no other greys to allow that discriminating claim.
But then you discover a crack in this symmetry. You notice that maybe it fluctuates in some minimal way. It is at times a little brighter or darker, a little whiter or blacker. Now you can start to separate. — apokrisis
You can extrapolate this slight initial difference towards two contrasting extremes. You can drag the two sides apart towards their two limiting poles that would be the purest white - as the least degree of contaminating black - and vice versa. — apokrisis
Once reality is dichotomised in this fashion, then you can go back in and mix. You can create actual shades of grey by Goodman’s approach. — apokrisis
How do we recognise the discrete except to the degree it lacks continuity. — apokrisis
The final requirement for a notational system is semantic finite differentiation; that is, for every two characters K and K' such that their compliance-classes are not identical, and every object h that does not comply with both, determination either that h does not comply with K or that h does not comply with K' must be theoretically possible. — Goodman, Languages of Art
A kettle is not a word. — Michael
A kettle being black is not a sentence. — Michael
Which would be helpful if using were anywhere near as clear as mentioning. — Srap Tasmaner
and we have a more substantial account of truth. — Michael
Declarative sentences work by pointing a word or word-string at one or more objects. — bongo fury
Is there something mysterious about correspondence? — Michael
We have a sentence "the cat is on the mat", we have the cat on the mat, and we say that the former is about or describes the latter. Is that mysterious? — Michael
A propositional attitude is a mental state held by an agent toward a proposition. — Wikipedia
What do you mean? — Bartricks
I was confusing contextualized meaning and referent. — hypericin
Unlike redundancy theories, however, the prosentential theory does not take the truth predicate to be always eliminable without loss. What would be lost in (11′) is Mary’s acknowledgment that Bill had said something. — IEP
truth a property of sentences (which are linguistic entities in some language or other), — Pie
that S refers to a specific bit of water, not water in general. — hypericin
Simply, we English speakers all know what S means. It is basic English. But we don't know to what it refers.
Therefore, meaning and reference are distinct concepts, and must not be conflated. — hypericin
And yet, despite our clear understanding of S, we have no idea what the referent is. What water is cold? The relevant context is unknown. S has no clear referent and yet is perfectly understandable. This can only be the case if meaning and referent are different: only then can we make sense of understanding the one without knowing the other. — hypericin
We seem to agree that "snow is white" is a sentence — Banno
and that snow is white is a fact, — Banno
yet you seem to need to slip something else in between the bolded bit and the white snow. I don't. — Banno
So meaning is both purely imaginary and not in the head, an imaginary lightning bolt from symbol to object — hypericin
... which is also the object? — hypericin
Then how does he deal with sentences with no referent? "The cat in the hat" has meaning but no reference in the world. — hypericin
the very same thing can be marks on a screen, a string of letters, a sentence and a fact. — Banno
It's clear that the thing on the right is not the name of a fact. — Banno
the very same thing can be [generally, not just exceptionally] marks on a screen, a string of letters, a sentence and a fact [the one it also represents]. — Banno
"Snow is white" is not a fact; it is a sentence. That snow is white is how things are, and so, it is a fact.
Now the bit in the above sentence that I italicised is a string of letters, "snow is white", and it is not dissimilar to the bit I bolded. — Banno
"Snow is white" is not a fact; it is a sentence. [But only the string without quotes is a sentence. The string with quotes is a name, facilitating talk about the sentence.] That snow is white is how things are, and so, it is a fact. [But only the fact represented by the string is how things are. The string is a sentence, talking about the fact.] — Banno
Then where is it located? — hypericin
And it seems that others (@Michael) have tried to make the same point to you. — Banno
"Snow is white" is not a fact, because facts are things in the world, and so while "snow is white" represents a fact, it is not a fact. — Banno
The thing on the right is a fact. — Banno
The thing represented by the sentence on the right is a fact.
It's clear that the thing on the right is not the name of a fact. — Banno
Meaning is not something in the world either, — hypericin
it is something in the head — hypericin
(otherwise, how can we make sense of abstractions, lies, or fictions?). — hypericin
Sentence, meaning, worldly referent are all not identical, do you agree? — hypericin