So do the proofs you mention indeed first prove there exists a unique individual with such and such properties that is then named 'God'? — TonesInDeepFreeze
Especially, one can't just assert without proof that there does exist a unique individual having certain properties and then go on to demonstrate that that individual then has other properties for a QED. — TonesInDeepFreeze
But it would mean something like: Necessarily, there exists/is an x (God), such that a (the greatest conceivable being/ subject of all perfections) = x. — Amalac
How does a system of modal logic talk about its own semantics? I'm not saying it can't be done, but I'd like to know how it works. — TonesInDeepFreeze
That strikes me as being an additional premise. Of course we can't rule out that additional premises have consequences. — TonesInDeepFreeze
The actual world is one among the possible worlds (this again follows in some systems of modal logic). If one admits that god exists in all possible worlds, that would imply that god exists in the actual world.
And so, if one accepts that it is possible that it is necessary that god exists in all possible worlds (meaning: in some possible worlds, necessarily God exists in all possible worlds), then it follows that in all possible worlds, god exists in all possible worlds, and therefore “god exists in all possible worlds” is true in the actual world, which is one of the possible worlds in which that statement is true, and therefore god exists in the actual world.
All this follows if one accepts system B of modal logic, from the corollary of axiom B (if the modal ontological argument is valid):
◇□X → X (If it is possible that it is necessary that X, then X is the case).
Likewise in system S5, the corollary of axiom 5:
◇□X → □X — Amalac
Now, suppose an individual is a member of a certain universe, of course that individual is not a member of certain other universes. So, yes, there is no individual that is a member of every universe. — TonesInDeepFreeze
B applies to a theorem, not an individual. I don't think we have an answer yet. — Banno
Is ▢ ∃(x)(a=x) well-formed? Is it a theorem of S5? — Banno
Well, I was looking for a second opinion. And further I don't see where my actual question was addressed. — Banno
In predict calculus we might cheat and represent that an individual exists as ∃(x)(a=x); is there some way to pars this into modal logic, such that the individual (a) is in every possible world? — Banno
I suppose my exception would be Bertrand Russell. He has a bunch of stuff on ethics pertaining to all kinds of problems. One book would be The Conquest of Happiness. — Manuel
In S4 or S5, or a derivative therefrom, can an individual exist in every possible world without contradiction? — Banno
Put it this way: in possible world semantics it is possible to invoke a world that does not include a given individual. Hence there are no necessary individuals. (@Amalac - does that seem right to you? ) — Banno
...there is an evident absurdity in pretending to demonstrate a matter of fact, or to prove it by any arguments a priori. Nothing is demonstrable, unless the contrary implies a contradiction. Nothing, that is distinctly conceivable, implies a contradiction. Whatever we conceive as existent, we can also conceive as non-existent. There is no being, therefore, whose non-existence implies a contradiction. Consequently there is no being, whose existence is demonstrable.
However, we can look for an instantia crucis and ask if there is another example of judgment that combines these two properties — incompatible in terms of the conceptions of Kant and Hume—, that is, one that was analytic and existential in its content. A candidate for this impossible chimera is, I suspect, the judgment "something exists." The reason this judgment can be said to be analytic and therefore "necessary" is that its negation "nothing exists" is not only false, but also unintelligible and absurd: indeed, if there is something absurd, it is that. On that basis, one can argue that "something exists" is equal to "necessarily, something exists."
Thus, this argument (the ontological argument) could be expressed in another way by saying that if God is conceivable at all, he cannot not exist. This is how our contemporary defender of Saint Anselm, Charles Hartshorne, approaches the question; in his opinion, the ontological argument is perfectly reasonable if it is re-stated as a hypothetical judgment: "If God is possible, God is necessary." But is God conceivable under the assumption that to conceive him is to admit that his essence and his existence converge and, therefore, that he is a necessary being not only in the sense that he actually exists, eternally and immutably, but in the sense that it is inevitable that he exists, he is causa sui, so that his non-existence would be, as it were, an ontic contradiction?
"if god exists in every possible world, then god exists in every possible world" - not exactly enlightening. — Banno
What is "died" then? — TheMadFool
My intuition, for what its worth, recommends that I should consider "died" as equivalent with "dead" and definitely not "die". This intuition may need further investigation but that's a topic for another discussion. — TheMadFool
If he dies, he's already dead. A person can't literally die twice. — Manuel
If he was living he wasn't dead by definition. A living person can die, they can be murdered or killed. But once they die, they are no longer alive. — Manuel
1. If Socrates died then either Socrates died when Socrates was alive or Socrates died when Socrates was dead (premise) — TheMadFool
Speaking for myself, Sextus Empiricus has committed the fallacy of false dichotomy or false dilemma. There are actually 3 option, 1 more than those provided: alive or dead or die. — TheMadFool
Let's say Socrates died at point t in time. Then he was alive in all points (not in the one previous point and before, since points do not touch each other, and between any two points, no matter how close they are together, there is an infinite number of points) previous to t, and he was dead a point at t and in all points after t. — god must be atheist
Died twice implies he already died once and the ball is now in Sextus Empericus' court - how did Socrates die once if Sextus Empiricus' conclusion is that Socrates didn't die? — TheMadFool
3. If he died when he was dead, then he would have died twice, which is impossible given that we know Socrates did not come back to life and then died again. — Amalac
Oh, wait! Sextus Empiricus is dead! — TheMadFool
What I can immediately observe in his description --besides the totally irrational "died ... when he was dead"-- is the use of the word "living" instead the more realistic word "alive". Of course, because he could not have an argument then:) — Alkis Piskas
if you like: that time and space are discontinuous. Which they are definitely not. — Alkis Piskas
By appointing a value to time and esp. dividing time, you do what Zeno did: assume that time is discontinuous. It's not. Time is continuous. It has no start or end or middle point, or any points in it. The same holds with space. Try to locate a point in space! We use points in geometry only for representation and description purposes, to show axioms and solve problems. — Alkis Piskas
So he died once before! Problem solved! If Sextum Empiricus claims that he died once before, necessarily to have died twice, then Sextus Empircus has to admit that Socrates died! — TheMadFool
how has this discussion started and who has posted/started it? — Alkis Piskas
The space I am writing this message in is for comments. Where are the answer spaces, if any? — Alkis Piskas
The paradox seems like Zeno — Gregory
As regards motion and change, we get similarly curious results. People used to think that when a thing changes, it must be in a state of change, and that when a thing moves, it is in a state of motion. This is now known to be a mistake. When a body moves, all that can be said is that it is in one place at one time and in another at another. We must not say that it will be in a neighbouring place at the next instant, since there is no next instant. Philosophers often tell us that when a body is in motion, it changes its position within the instant. To this view Zeno long ago made the fatal retort that every body always is where it is; but a retort so simple and brief was not of the kind to which philosophers are accustomed to give weight, and they have continued down to our own day to repeat the same phrases which roused the Eleatic's destructive ardour.
I have a feeling that you might want to look into, analyze thoroughly, an expression that seems to be, luckily or not, a stock phrase employed by those who face major employment issues, that phrase being, "my career ended before it even started" — TheMadFool
How on earth can something end before it started? — TheMadFool
An infinite past has no start and yet, here we are, in the present, an end as it were. — TheMadFool
So, here’s some context: Matt Dillahunty sometimes talks about how Aristotle and his buddies sat down 2000 years ago and discovered all the valid syllogisms. That’s all of them and if your argument doesn’t take one of those forms, it’s invalid or something like that. Alex Malpass is trying to communicate to him that there are a lot of other formal logical systems that cover things that Aristotle’s logic doesn’t (I think he mentions modal logic as an example a bit before the start of the clip). In this clip specifically, Alex tells Matt that in classical logic for all x Px doesn’t imply exists x Px (which is correct) to which Matt pushes back. — Need Logic Help
(2) Over-estimation of the syllogism . The syllogism is only one kind of deductive argument. In mathematics, which is wholly deductive, syllogisms hardly ever occur. Of course it would be possible to re-write mathematical arguments in syllogistic form, but this would be very artificial and would not make them any more cogent. Take arithmetic, for example. If I buy goods worth $4.63, and tender a $5 bill in payment, how much change is due to me? To put this simple sum in
the form of a syllogism would be absurd, and would tend to conceal the real nature of the
argument. Again, within logic there are non-syllogistic inferences, such as: "A horse is an animal, therefore a horse's head is an animal's head." Valid syllogisms, in fact, are only some among valid deductions, and have no logical priority over others. The attempt to give pre-eminence to the syllogism in deduction misled philosophers as to the nature of mathematical reasoning. Kant, who perceived that mathematics is not syllogistic, inferred that it uses extra-logical principles, which, however, he supposed to be as certain as those of logic. He, like his predecessors, though in a different way, was misled by respect for Aristotle.
So, here’s some context: Matt Dillahunty sometimes talks about how Aristotle and his buddies sat down 2000 years ago and discovered all the valid syllogisms. That’s all of them and if your argument doesn’t take one of those forms, it’s invalid or something like that. — Need Logic Help
The issue seems to be that there are formal logical systems that Dillahunty was not paying adequate attention to, but how significant was this error of omission? — Need Logic Help
(...)a man whose opinions and theories are worth studying may be presumed to have
had some intelligence, but (...) no man is likely to have arrived at complete and final truth on any subject whatever.
What does one mean by past? Elapsed time ending in the present (now).
So, if the past is infinite, an infinite amount of time must've elapsed. — TheMadFool
The contradiction resides in your inclusion of the universe as an uncompleted series. If it was, then the elapsed time of the universe, your “infinitely many finite intervals of time” for the universe is impossible — Mww
The universe would never be “finished by means of successive synthesis”, from which follows necessarily that talk of “in a universe with an infinite past”, is meaningless. — Mww
While it may not be contradictory to speak of a universe with an infinite past, given the existence of it, it is still contradictory to speak of a universe with an infinite elapsed time, which makes no reference to any given time. — Mww
The set of negative integers is an uncompleted series, in which the last member is impossible to represent. — Mww
(...)take again the arguments (of Aquinas) professing to prove the existence of God. All of these, except the one from teleology in lifeless things, depend upon the supposed impossibility of a series having no first term. Every mathematician knows that there is no such impossibility; the series of negative integers ending with minus one is an instance to the contrary. — Bertrand Russell
No, I said what I meant to say. — Mww
Metaphysics.....the most fun to be had without paying for it. — Mww
Let's me take a stab at your argument, for my own benefit. As I understand what you're saying: even if time had no beginning it would not matter because we are finite, so we can place ourselves anywhere on the timeline and no be bothered about how we got here. — Manuel
Isn't the counterargument here that in order to get to now, we had to begin somewhere. — Manuel
But if time is infinite, how could we place ourselves here? An infinite amount of time has gone on before we got here. — Manuel
Either a part of infinity is finite or if not, it is also infinite. If a part of infinity is also infinite, regardless of not having starting conditions, we could not be here. — Manuel
But this raises more problems, if a part of infinity is finite, wouldn't we have to go through an infinite amount of time to reach a portion of infinity which is not. How's that possible? — Manuel
Man, this hypothetical’s got a farging mind of its own donnit? Seems “up to the present” makes an appearance in this current iteration, which changes the entire proposition. — Mww
(...)Now, in his first proof, Kant simply argues that the world must have a beginning in time, since otherwise an infinite number of years would have elapsed at the present moment, which is impossible. This concludes the first proof. — Karl Popper
Hmmm......and what of the idea of a succession of a series of times that never completes? Isn’t a succession in a series of times the same as an elapse of time? — Mww
A succession in a series makes no need of an amount for each time of the series. — Mww
Even so, isn’t an infinite series of successive finite intervals of minutes, still an infinite amount of time? — Mww
“....up to every given moment of time, an eternity must have elapsed, and therewith passed away an infinite series of successive conditions....” — Mww
the infinity of a series consists in that it can never be finished by means of successive syntheses. — Kant
Well, yes, by the very fact of how bias and norms create quasi-rules of how language is used in a society. I understand that terms become reified with time as these tendencies abate or are pressured due to how social norms progress. — Shawn
That is how I would define it, but I didn’t use “past” in my statement. You transcribed the term into it. — Mww
So is this where you’re coming from? And by association, is this the hypothetical proposition the truth of which you find doubtful? — Mww
You’re equating your “if the past were infinite” with his “an eternity must have elapsed” — Mww
Well that's what I meant, it seems I expressed myself poorly (english is not my mother tongue). — Amalac
I diverge from Kant here, and adjoin Schopenhauer, re: the world as “will and representation”, in that I consider the world to be the immediate unity of phenomena, that which directly appears to my representational faculties, a much narrower view of experience proper. All else, being possible experience doesn’t change the my idea of world, but rather, enlarges its content and thereby its limits. As such, the boundary of my world is the totality of my possible experience, and, because of that restriction, the CMB is irrelevant. — Mww
I think more the simultaneity of the initiation of phenomena, with the possibility of the representation of them, by an eventual intellect equipped with a cognitive system predicated on it. Within such a system, time is not an object so doesn’t depend on the ontology of objects, but it is used by the system in referencing objects to the system or to each other, so as soon as objects become possible, so too does the possibility of referencing them. Time is therefore irrelevant if there are no objects and if there is no system. — Mww
Again, he doesn’t maintain it, he supposes it in order to have something to debunk. — Mww
There may be an infinite time regressively from the beginning of the world, but not from an infinite time progressively to the beginning of the world. — Mww
If you read the antinomies, you should have found he did the same thing in the antithesis. In the thesis he supposed the world had no beginning then proved it did, in the antithesis he supposed the world had a beginning and proved it didn’t. They are called conflicts of transcendental ideas for just that reason; either can be proved in its own way. — Mww
Russell seems to assume an externalist, causal conception of empirical knowledge, and then projects that assumption onto Locke and then Hume, for whom this would be a stolen concept, given his stance on causation. But whether or not Russell is right about knowledge, the question here is whether Hume espoused the same view: only then would he be open to the charge in the OP. Hume actually seems to hold an internalist view, at least some of the time, i.e. his account of knowledge refers only to mental states. — SophistiCat
It seems also evident, that, when men follow this blind and powerful instinct of nature, they always suppose the very images, presented by the senses, to be the external objects, and never entertain any suspicion, that the one are nothing but representations of the other. This very table, which we see white, and which we feel hard, is believed to exist, independent of our perception, and to be something external to our mind, which perceives it. Our presence bestows not being on it: our absence does not annihilate it. It preserves its existence uniform and entire, independent of the situation of intelligent beings, who perceive or contemplate it.
But this universal and primary opinion of all men is soon destroyed by the slightest philosophy, which teaches us, that nothing can ever be present to the mind but an image or perception, and that the senses are only the inlets, through which these images are conveyed, without being able to produce any immediate intercourse between the mind and the object. The table, which we see, seems to diminish, as we remove farther from it: but the real table, which exists independent of us, suffers no alteration: it was, therefore, nothing but its image, which was present to the mind. These are the obvious dictates of reason; and no man, who reflects, ever doubted, that the existences, which we consider, when we say, this house and that tree, are nothing but perceptions in the mind, and fleeting copies or representations of other existences, which remain uniform and independent.
119. So far, then, are we necessitated by reasoning to contradict or depart from the primary instincts of nature, and to embrace a new system with regard to the evidence of our senses. But here philosophy finds herself extremely embarrassed, when she would justify this new system, and obviate the cavils and objections of the sceptics. She can no longer plead the infallible and irresistible instinct of nature: for that led us to a quite different system, which is acknowledged fallible and even erroneous. And to justify this pretended philosophical system, by a chain of clear and convincing argument, or even any appearance of argument, exceeds the power of all human capacity.
By what argument can it be proved, that the perceptions of the mind must be caused by external objects, entirely different from them, though resembling them (if that be possible) and could not arise either from the energy of the mind itself, or from the suggestion of some invisible and unknown spirit, or from some other cause still more unknown to us? It is acknowledged, that, in fact, many of these perceptions arise not from anything external, as in dreams, madness, and other diseases. And nothing can be more inexplicable than the manner, in which body should so operate upon mind as ever to convey an image of itself to a substance, supposed of so different, and even contrary a nature.
It is a question of fact, whether the perceptions of the senses be produced by external objects, resembling them: how shall this question be determined? By experience surely; as all other questions of a like nature. But here experience is, and must be entirely silent. The mind has never anything present to it but the perceptions, and cannot possibly reach any experience of their connexion with objects. The supposition of such a connexion is, therefore, without any foundation in reasoning. — Hume
Of course we'll continue to do those because of habit — Marchesk
Take the examples of a perpetual motion machine or accelerating up to the speed of light. Both are ruled out as impossible by physics. — Marchesk
So why hold people accountable? Why blame them for anything they do? — Marchesk