If not assertion or illocution or denotation, then what is force? There is still no clear account of what this thread is about.Yes, which is why I keep trying to find some better, more perspicuous ways to carve up "force." I was leaning toward believing that "force" itself should be strictly separated from both assertion and illocution... — J
So could you not understand what a sentence is about unless it is clear it was being used to make, say, an assertion rather than ask a question? Isn't it a bit more complex than that?I believe that in order for a sentence to be about something, it has to be used. — frank
Well, perhaps you haven't. Then we agree that there is a difference between what a sentence is about and what is done with it?I don't think anyone has made that claim. — frank
An utterance is just sounds or marks. Literally, nothing else. A sentence is a grammatically correct sequence of words, but a sentence has no specific meaning.
A proposition is expressed by an uttered sentence. A proposition is along the lines of content. — frank
Sure. But one can utter a sentence without expressing a proposition. And without making a judgement as to the sentence's truth.A proposition is expressed by an uttered sentence. — frank
It's just that so many of the reviews take this as central. It seems these folk would scrap modality. We do think things like "what if I hadn't answered your post?". So perhaps they are wrong and there is no mystery here. That would help explain why no one has been able to set out Kimhi's argument coherently.Parmenides' questions — J
I haven't been able to follow this. But at the beginning of this thread I had an intuition that there was some blurring of the notion of force in Frege that has been set out in subsequent work, which is why I went to the trouble of explicating the nature of illocutionary force. "Force" here is used to talk about intentionality, about what we are doing with the words at hand. So we speak of a difference in force between "Grass is green" used as an assertion, command or question. That's illocutionary force, operating at the level of sentences. There's also a difference in using "Berlin" for a city, a person or a rock band, and this might also be called a difference in "force". My understanding is that in choosing the judgement stroke to range over the whole expression Frege removed the illocutionary force. But the "force" that denotes remained. Hence we are able to use the same letter for the same item in the expression, giving us extensionality.Good. I’m only vaguely aware of how Frege’s concavity differs from our modern universal quantifier, but I think I can still ask these next questions. The Fregean universal quantifier ranges over objects as well as formulae/functions, right? So maybe my question about “Frege on the Beach” (sounds like a hit song) could be phrased as: "When you comprehend the term ‛Berlin’ (as I’m going to assume you do, Herr Frege), does your comprehension depend on the universal-quantification symbol? And then, should you choose to use the term to fulfill a function, does the existence commitment change to ∃x?” So the idea is that ∀ can range over names or terms that are not (yet) part of functions. Clearly, I’m trying to find a way to make a name (and its sense) a “thinkable thought” without violating Frege’s understanding of what logic can do. Does this sound at all sensible to you? — J
Good. Names are given meaning by being given an interpretation. For propositional logic that interpretation is just "⊤" or "⊥", something that is quite explicit in Frege. But of course there followed Russell's paradox, the controversy about Basic Law Five, the theory of Definite Descriptions, possible world semantics, rigid designation and so on. IT all became quite complicated, and very fruitful.Yes, that’s how I understand it too. — J
In a way, the OP is asking about the extent to which meaning is use. In what circumstances can we drop use and still have meaning? This is assertoric force: — frank
...assertion, which is expressed by means of the vertical stroke at the left end of the horizontal, relates to this whole. — Quoted in SEP 1879a: §2
Property is a legal convention, as pointed out. You don't inherit unless there are conventions of inheritance. Conquest is theft until ratified. Something is "mine" only if relevant others agree.Property is the result of the luck of inheritance or the gains of conquest. — Paine
I don't think so. It's about language. the contention is:That was Marx's argument — Paine
If this were so, then a thief, who gains control over what they steal, would correctly be said to own the the thing stolen.Basically ownership is about control. — Benj96
And every other attempt to define truth collapses too. For in a definition certain characteristics would have to be stated. And in application to any particular case the question would always arise whether it were true that the characteristics
were present. So one goes round in a circle. Consequently, it is probable that the content of the word " true " is unique and indefinable — The Thought: A Logical Enquiry
On this account, both "Berlin" and "2+2=4" are names. Indeed, if a proposition is considered to be a statement with a truth value, then any proposition is just the name of either the true or the false. Assuming bivalency, of course.“What would Frege say about comprehending a singular term?” — J
Hence he presumes two truth values without giving any account beyond reference. 2+2=4 names the true; 2+2=5 names the false.We do not need a specific sign to declare a truth-value to be the False, provided we have a sign by means of which every truth-value is transformed into its opposite, which in any case is indispensable. — SEP
Notice also that for Frege there is a structure literally hanging from the ⊢. So we have
The judgment stoke occurs once in the expression, at the beginning. It affirms the whole expression, not each individual line separately.read from bottom to top, for what we might now write as
∀A∀B(A→(B→A)).
In the modern version all the assertive paraphernalia on the left is removed. Along with it goes much of the implication of commitment. (again, stolen from SEP) — Banno
My bolding.The horizontal stroke, from which the symbol judgement is formed, binds the symbols that follow it into a whole, and assertion, which is expressed by means of the vertical stroke at the left end of the horizontal, relates to this whole. — Quoted in SEP 1879a: §2
How’s that?The overwhelmingly vast majority of true statements about the natural numbers cannot be expressed in language — Tarskian
Well, no. "General public" might do.That could still be either one. — schopenhauer1
Understanding an utterance in a language you know is not a voluntary action. You don't get the meaning through a conscious and laborious process something like decoding an encrypted message. If there's good reason to think you are doing something like this, you do it out of habit and a facility developed through countless hours of practice, quickly and without attention. You have to pay attention to the speaker, but not to the process of decoding. Or you're not doing anything like that. I would hope this is an empirical question. Either way, understanding is not something you usually should be described as "doing". It's more like something that happens to you.
There is something similar with speaking. Not just with respect to phonetics, not even just with all the mechanical bits of language production, but even in what you say. Think back over the last few days of verbal exchanges you had at work or in a social setting: in how many of those did you have to, or choose to, consciously and with effort decide what to say? Most of the time we effortlessly select the words to use, assemble them into a sentence and utter that sentence, but more than that, very often we don't even have to think about what to say; it just comes to us, which is to say, it just comes out.
Again, there are questions about how to describe what's going on here, but candid speech is, at least very often, habitual, requiring no more conscious effort than understanding the speech of others. — Srap Tasmaner
I think so. I baulk a bit at 'understanding is not something you usually should be described as "doing"', since we do say that he did or didn't understand... We treat it as something we do.Do we agree up to here? — Srap Tasmaner
The answer, by example: if P={a,b,c} then Pa is true; if P={b,c,d} then Pa is false.In virtue of what is the forceless combination Pa associated with the truth-making
relation that a falls under the extension of P, and thus with the claim Pa, rather than
with the truth-making relation that a does not fall under P (or falls under the extension
of ~P), and this with the opposite claim ~Pa?
This seems pretty much on the money. "⊢p" does not follow from "p". But that's kinda the point Frege makes, and solves with his nomenclature. In setting out Modus Ponens for example, Frege doesn't writeFrege’s system of logical notation, depending as it does on a distinction between the intensional force and extensional force of predicates, cannot account for the inference: “p”→ “A judges p”→ “A rightly judges p.” Within the context of “A judges,” “p” takes on a different intensional force (its sense) from when it stands alone, even though its extension (its reference) remains the same; it is intension, rather than extension, that permits inference. — Boynton