What are hallucinations if not an experience of a distal object without a distal object?also believe that distal objects are constituents of experience in the sense that you could not have an experience of a distal object without them. — Luke
What are hallucinations if not an experience of a distal object without a distal object? — flannel jesus
I also believe that distal objects are constituents of experience in the sense that you could not have an experience of a distal object without them. — Luke
Why wouldn't you use the same argument against naive realists? — Luke
I like the examples you (and Claude) have been giving, but I don't seem to draw the same conclusion.
I don't think indirect realism presupposes or requires that phenomenal experience is somehow a passive reflection of sensory inputs. Rather the opposite, a passive brain reflecting its environment seems to be a direct realist conception. These examples seem to emphasize the active role the brain plays in constructing the sensory panoply we experience, which is perfectly in line with indirect realism.
For instance, in the very striking cube illusion you presented, we only experience the square faces as brown and orange because the brain is constructing an experience that reflects its prediction about the physical state of the cube: that the faces must in fact have different surface properties, in spite of the same wavelengths hitting the retina at the two corresponding retinal regions. — hypericin
Rather, what we are immediately conscious of is the already "processed" phenomenological content. So an indirect realist account should identify this phenomenological content as the alleged "sense data" that mediates our access to the world, not the antecedent neural processing itself. — Pierre-Normand
The neural processing performed by the brain on raw sensory inputs like retinal images plays an important causal role in enabling human perception of invariant features in the objects we observe. However, our resulting phenomenology - how things appear to us - consists of more than just this unprocessed "sensory" data. The raw nerve signals, retinal images, and patterns of neural activation across sensory cortices are not directly accessible to our awareness.
Rather, what we are immediately conscious of is the already "processed" phenomenological content. So an indirect realist account should identify this phenomenological content as the alleged "sense data" that mediates our access to the world, not the antecedent neural processing itself. Luke also aptly pointed this out. Saying that we (directly) perceive the world as flat and then (indirectly) infer its 3D layout misrepresents the actual phenomenology of spatial perception. This was the first part of my argument against indirect realism.
The second part of my argument is that the sort of competence that we acquire to perceive those invariants aren't competences that our brains have (although our brains enable us to acquire them) but rather competences that are inextricably linked to our abilities to move around and manipulate objects in the world. Learning to perceive and learning to act are inseparable activities since they normally are realized jointly rather like a mathematician learns the meanings of mathematical theorems by learning how to prove them or make mathematical demonstrations on the basis of them.
In the act of reaching out for an apple, grasping it and bringing it closer to your face, the success of this action is the vindication of the truth of the perception. Worries about the resemblance between the seen/manipulated/eaten apple and the world as it is in itself arise on the backdrop of dualistic philosophies rather than being the implications of neuroscientific results.
The indirect realist's starting point of taking phenomenal experience itself as the problematic "veil" separating us from direct access to reality is misguided. The phenomenological content is already an achievement of our skilled engagement with the world as embodied agents, not a mere representation constructed by the brain. — Pierre-Normand
If someone claims that the direct object of perceptual knowledge is the already-processed phenomenological content, and that through this we have indirect knowledge of the external stimulus or distal cause, would you call them a direct realist or an indirect realist?
I'd call them an indirect realist. — Michael
On this view, phenomenology is concerned with describing and analyzing the appearances of those objects themselves, not the appearances of some internal "representations" of them (which would make them, strangely enough, appearances of appearances). — Pierre-Normand
I think the idea that one must start with "atomic" concepts isn't wholly inconsistent with the sort of holism Wittgenstein advocated — Pierre-Normand
How do you conceptualise a distal object in the second construal of indirect realism? — fdrake
What defines them as being indirect realists is in believing that we have direct knowledge only of a mental representation. Direct realists believe that we have direct knowledge of the distal object because nothing like a mental representation exists (the bottom drawing of direct realism). — Michael
In contrast, a direct realist posits no such intermediate representations at all. For the direct realist, the act of representing the world is a capacity that the human subject exercises in directly perceiving distal objects. On this view, phenomenology is concerned with describing and analyzing the appearances of those objects themselves, not the appearances of some internal "representations" of them (which would make them, strangely enough, appearances of appearances). — Pierre-Normand
What are hallucinations if not an experience of a distal object without a distal object? — flannel jesus
Then, your first part was an argument against a straw man, since an indirect realist can (and should, and does, imo) agree that phenomenological content is only accessible following all neural processing.This was the first part of my argument against indirect realism. — Pierre-Normand
As the MIT roboticist Rodney Brooks once argued, the terrain itself is its own best model - it doesn't need to be re-represented internally — Pierre-Normand
“The world is its own best model,” Brooks wrote. “It is always exactly up to date. It always contains every detail there is to be known. The trick is to sense it appropriately and often enough.”
“I’m watching these insects buzz around. And they’ve got tiny, tiny little brains, some as small 100,000 neurons, and I’m thinking, ‘They can’t do the mathematics I’m asking my robots to do for an even simpler thing. They’re hunting. They’re eating. They’re foraging. They’re mating. They’re getting out of my way when I’m trying to slap them. How are they doing all this stuff? They must be organized differently.’
Think of an amoeba, light hits a photo receptor, and by some logic the amoeba moves one way or the other.If you regard this as "perception", then this is direct perception — hypericin
All problems in computer science can be solved by another level of indirection
I would say that illusions and hallucinations are phenomenal experiences, instead of saying that they are the consequences of phenomenal experiences — Luke
The second part of my argument is that the sort of competence that we acquire to perceive those invariants aren't competences that our brains have (although our brains enable us to acquire them) — Pierre-Normand
Then, your first part was an argument against a straw man, since an indirect realist can (and should, and does, imo) agree that phenomenological content is only accessible following all neural processing. — hypericin
He may have refined his position since we began this discussion but he had long taken the stance that what I was focussing on as the content of perceptual experience wasn't how things really look but rather was inferred from raw appearances that, according to him, corresponded more closely to the stimulation of the sense organs. — Pierre-Normand
I am saying that appearances are mental phenomena, often caused by the stimulation of some sense organ (dreams and hallucinations are the notable exceptions), and that given causal determinism, the stimulation of a different kind of sense organ will cause a different kind of mental phenomenon/appearance. — Michael
The naïve view that projects these appearances onto some distal object (e.g. the naïve realist theory of colour), such that they have a "real look" is a confusion, much like any claim that distal objects have a "real feel" would be a confusion. There just is how things look to me and how things feel to you given our individual physiology.
It seems that many accept this at least in the case of smell and taste but treat sight as special, perhaps because visual phenomena are more complex than other mental phenomena and because depth is a quality in visual phenomena, creating the illusion of conscious experience extending beyond the body. But there's no reason to believe that photoreception is special, hence why I question the distinction between so-called "primary" qualities like visual geometry and so-called "secondary" qualities like smells and tastes (and colours).
Although even if I were to grant that some aspect of mental phenomena resembles some aspect of distal objects, it is nonetheless the case that it is only mental phenomena of which we have direct knowledge in perception, with any knowledge of distal objects being inferential, i.e. indirect, entailing the epistemological problem of perception and the viability of scepticism. — Michael
...a non hallucinatory experience of a distal object by definition requires the existence of a distal object. — flannel jesus
...distal objects are not constituents of experience. — Michael
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.