It's not just Kripke, and it's about substitution.What exactly is Kripke's value in calling them identity statements? — Richard B
Philosophy is limited to discourse, and so must be the subjects of its questions. Yet a third version would insist on a distinction between "answer" and "subject": thus, we can answer a philosophical question within the realm of philosophical discourse, but that doesn't mean that the subject of such discourse is also necessarily linguistic. — J
If philosophy becomes merely a matter of keeping our language games internally consistent, then it risks becoming a kind of syntax-policing—about saying what can or can't be said, not about what is or must be. That’s a long way from asking what is real and how it might be known.
I would have thought that the existence of necessary truth, and questions as to what that implies, or why they are necessary, are fundamental philosophical questions, about more than simply 'what we can say'.
The most direct way of responding would be that truth can be distinguished from delusion or falsehood.
And if we discover that water is H₂O, then ☐(water=H₂O). And so on through the many different examples. Notice how each of these is a hypothetical – an "if... then...", in which the antecedent is found a posteriori - by looking around. But all that is being done here is ensuring that we keep our language consistent. Once we fix reference by accepting the antecedent, we are obligated to respect the modal consequences of that act of naming as expressed by the consequent. — Banno
We establish "natural kinds" because we as humans can agree on definition and judgment as it is applied to our natural surroundings, not because we identified some essence that exists in all possible worlds.
Indeed, if Homer and Charles Dickens (and so Charles Darwin as well) could be speaking of essentially different forms of "water" and "horse" and "tiger," this would cast doubt on any grasp of human history, which in turn should cast doubt on any faith in scientific institutions. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Forgive my ignorance. That suggests that you have an independent definition of "extensional context". But I thought that intersubstitutability was the definition of an extensional context. ?In an extensional context, a=b iff for any string, substituting a for b does not change the value of that string. — Banno
Are you possibly confusing "All the propositions that we think we know about tigers are false" with "Each of the propositions that we think we know about tigers may be false"? Consider the discovery of black swans. How did they know that those black birds were swans? Similarly, a big cat with no stripes might not be a tiger.If we did find out that everything we knew about tigers were mistaken or in error, that would nevertheless be a discovery about tigers. It follows that "tiger" does not refer to tigers in virtue of some description that sets out their characteristics. — Banno
So now I'm wondering how reference is achieved.Notice that reference remains intact despite the failure of each description. Hence reference is not achieved by using descriptions, nor by essences. — Banno
So how is it achieved?
Concerns of this sort are hardly new. W.V.O. Quine (1960), for instance, famously claims that reference is ‘inscrutable’, or that there is simply no matter of fact what a given referential term refers to. His arguments, however, depend on certain methodological constraints that many would now be inclined to reject. Not so with the related ‘problem of the many’, popularized at roughly the same time by Peter Unger (1980) and Geach (1980). To see the issue, consider someone using an utterance of ‘that’ to refer to a cloud in the sky. What exactly is this cloud? The obvious answer would seem to be: a set of water droplets suspended in the air in such-and-such region. But what about some droplet right on the edge of that region? Should it be counted or not? In fact, there will be innumerable such droplets, and we seem to have no systematic way of answering this question: if we say ‘yes’, we face a continuous march outwards; if we say ‘no’, we face a continuous retreat. Neither option seems even remotely satisfactory, and yet if we cannot provide an answer to the question of what exactly the cloud is then it might well seem that we have equally well failed to answer the question of what the relevant use of ‘that’ refers to.[19]
Forgive my ignorance. That suggests that you have an independent definition of "extensional context". But I thought that intersubstitutability was the definition of an extensional context. ? — Ludwig V
I don't believe so. The idea is that we learn what some thing is, name it, and then discover that everything we knew about it was false.Are you possibly confusing "All the propositions that we think we know about tigers are false" with "Each of the propositions that we think we know about tigers may be false"? — Ludwig V
Consider the historical figure Thales of Miletus. Tradition holds that he was the first philosopher, perhaps the first to suggest that water is the fundamental substance of all things. Yet, on closer inspection, our supposed knowledge of Thales collapses into uncertainty. Were these views really his? Were the anecdotes true? Or are they accretions of later doxography and myth-making?
As historical scrutiny deepens, it becomes clear that we know almost nothing about Thales with certainty. Yet this very realization—that we know nothing about him—is itself a fact about Thales. It is not a fact about someone else or a mythological construct; it concerns the very individual to whom the name "Thales" refers.
Therefore, paradoxically, our ignorance becomes a form of reference. The name "Thales" successfully picks out an individual in history, even though our beliefs about him may be largely mistaken or minimal. This supports the view that the name refers rigidly and directly, independent of any particular descriptive content we might associate with it. The denotation succeeds not despite our ignorance but is revealed in it. — ChatGPT
Good question. To my eye, it's clear that we sometimes do work out a reference from a description associated with it; it's just that we can show that this is not what happens in every case. Indeed, it should hardly be a surprise to learn that there is more than one way for a reference to succeed.So now I'm wondering how reference is achieved. — Ludwig V
Are you suggesting that you think it is not a tough question? If so, I would love to know more.A bajillion theories of reference (or supposition) have developed over the years; apparently it's a tough question. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Well, the cloud issue is just a sorites paradox. You're right, it makes very specific assumptions, which, IMO, are, let us say, unhelpful.The "problem of the many" strikes me as only particularly problematic for a certain sort of supervenience metaphysics for instance. — Count Timothy von Icarus
It is indeed. But explaining what that means is less clear.It seems obvious that people have things in mind that they intend to refer to in most cases. — Count Timothy von Icarus
OK. It's just that I'm not sure that it does work. But perhaps that's beyond our scope here.It's an extensional context if substitution works. — Banno
There's something very odd about saying that we learn what some thing is, and then discover that what we have learnt about it is false. What is the "it" here?I don't believe so. The idea is that we learn what some thing is, name it, and then discover that everything we knew about it was false. — Banno
Yes. But that means that we do know how to pick out Thales.What this shows is that we don't manage to pick out Thales in virtue of what we know about Thales, a somewhat counterintuitive result. — Banno
I agree with that. One alternative way is by means of an ostensive definition - which, of course, isn't a definition at all by the usual standards. Nonetheless, it works.Good question. To my eye, it's clear that we sometimes do work out a reference from a description associated with it; it's just that we can show that this is not what happens in every case. Indeed, it should hardly be a surprise to learn that there is more than one way for a reference to succeed. — Banno
I agree with that. I'm still a bit puzzled about why I think that "how it managed to denote it's target" is not a answerable question, but "how do you know that Thales is not Homer" is.What this doesn't rule out is the sort of view that might be seen in a Wittgensteinian account, in which reference is an aspect of the more general language games in which we participate, or even a sub-game within those games. On such a view a reference may be counted as successful if we get on with what we are doing, regardless of how it managed to denote it's target. — Banno
Sure, usefulness is dependent on what is real or true. For something to be useful means that there is some sense of truth attached to it.Although "99.9%" probably undersells things. Do ants, or trees, or ducks, or men every give birth to tigers? Has anything but a tiger ever given birth to a tiger?
Even in hybrids, the hybrid's traits are an admixture. Horses and donkeys give birth to mules, not cats and frogs, etc.
Note that this also defines what humans find "useful." If one tries to breed one's male pigs to one's female sheep, the family will starve. — Count Timothy von Icarus
There is no reference if the scribbles refer to something that is not the case. One can only confirm there is a reference by making some observation about what the scribbles refer to. If there is no reference then they are just scribbles and not words. It's just that we often trust people are not lying when having a conversation with them so we don't feel a need to confirm everything that is said.Yep. Notice that reference remains intact despite the failure of each description. Hence reference is not achieved by using descriptions, nor by essences. — Banno
For me, things are real if they possess causal power. Rocks and ideas are real because they possess causal power. You can use your ideas to change things in the world and rocks can make you feel pain when you drop one on your foot. Essences would be akin to how different things interact with each other. For instance light is either reflected or passes right through objects depending on what the atomic structure of those objects, and which wavelengths of light are reflected or absorbed is dependent upon the same atomic structure.Then there's Kripke's suggestion, that if we must think of essences we can think of them as the properties had by something in every possible world in which that thing exists. This has the benefit of being formalisable and reasonably clear while keeping to a minimum any metaphysical consequences.
Then you may be suggesting that we can be rid of essences by doing some sort of Bayesian analysis that allows us to conclude that tigers are real. Maybe.
But you and I might agree that essences have little to do with what is and isn't real. — Banno
I'm thinking mutual agreement.Scribbles are just scribbles unless they refer to something. What makes a scribble a word and not just a scribble?
You can draw any scribbles on this page but what makes some scribble meaningful? You might say it depends on how it is used. And I will ask, "used for what? - to accomplish what?" To use anything means you have a goal in mind. What is your goal in using some scribbles? — Harry Hindu
I'm thinking mutual agreement. — Patterner
Wikipedia says: An alphabet is a standard set of letters written to represent particular sounds in a spoken language.The scribbles do not refer to the sounds of a spoken language. — Harry Hindu
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.