In short, when a truth occurs, it occurs ontically—and that which ontically is is not subject to the possibility of being wrong, i.e. fallibility. But we can only appraise what ontically is epistemologically, which will always be to some extent fallible. — javra
When differentiating the ontological from the epistemological, ontically occurring truths (which are absolutely certain and not possible to be wrong) do occur all the time. But our epistemic appraisals of what are and are not ontic truths (the latter, again, do occur) will be fallible to some measure. — javra
* The monkey wrench is logical and other putatively analytical truths. [...] There's something odd about asking whether "If A, then not (~A)" is a belief, or how we might justify it. But I'll leave that for others. — J
Is there a contradiction? — Leontiskos
Consider this proposition as if it were itself a truth:
<Ontological truths (which are absolutely certain and not possible to be wrong) do occur all the time.>
Is this "truth" an "ontological truth" or an "epistemological truth"? Because if it is an "epistemological truth," then it is not certain, and if it is an "ontological truth," then your appraisal is not fallible. This is why I'm not sure the way you are dividing up this territory is ultimately coherent. — Leontiskos
The truth of the proposition here quoted would of course of itself be an epistemic truth. One which I so far find thoroughly justifiable: To keep things short, I so far find that there can be no epistemic truth in the absence of an ontically occuring truth it aspires to express. Can you, or anyone else, cogently justify the occurence of an epistemic truth that does not claim to be or else intend to conform to an ontic truth?
If not, then it remains cogently justifiable that ontically occuring truths do occur. Conversely, it then becomes unjustifiable that ontically occurring truths do not occur. — javra
If there is no pole of knowledge then I don't see how one [inference to the best explanation] can be better than another (because no [inference to the best explanation] can better approach that pole). — Leontiskos
So, if we know p could be false, then we don't know that it's true, but we may well believe that it's true. — Janus
You seem to be saying that "epistemic truths" presuppose the existence of "ontological truths"; we all believe ourselves to be uttering "epistemic truths"; therefore we are all presupposing the existence of "ontological truths"; and because of this the belief in "ontological truths" is justified.
I think that's a good account on the "game of pool" approach, but I would prefer an account that provides for knowledge of at least some "ontological truths," rather than mere justified belief. — Leontiskos
Then on the premise that we know that every p (epistemological truth) could be false, we cannot know any p. — Leontiskos
On all of these conceptions certain knowledge is impossible, and knowledge is traditionally understood to be certain. — Leontiskos
↪Relativist
has forwarded a theory where all (or almost all - this is contentious) beliefs are inferences to the best explanation, and are thus probabilistic. — Leontiskos
Here is a different approach to the same conclusion:
Can it be in any way validly justified that no ontologically occurring truths occur? If one believes that this is the case, what does one intend to express by the proposition of “no ontically occurring truths occur” if this proposition is not meant to conform/correspond to the actual states of affairs of the world and, thereby, of itself be an ontic truth? Thereby contradicting the very proposition made. Therefore, there is no justifiable alternative to the proposition that ontic truths occur. — javra
As to providing knowledge of some "ontological truths", this, again, is what our ability to honestly and cogently justify offers us the possibility of. It just that our JTB knowledge will not, by a fallibilist account, be infallible. (Fallibiilty does not equate to being wrong.) — javra
Remember that the JTB model of knowledge was presented by an Ancient Skeptic. If one presumes knowledge to be infallible, then this quote holds. If one presumes knowledge to be fallible, then it does not. — javra
By everything I've so far stated, there then can occur ontically true beliefs which we can justify at will. These then will be instances of ontic knowledge, which is certain. Because we can only hold epistemic appraisals of what is ontically true, though, everything we uphold as knowledge will be epistemic knowledge, rather than ontic knowledge - which, as with epistemic truth, is less than "completely assured, fixed, and invariable." — javra
I'll be back tomorrow. — javra
Regarding "probablistic" - do not mistake this with orthodox Bayesian epistemology, which depends on the absurd assumption that we can attach a consistent set of epistemic probabilities to every statement we claim to believe. Rather, I embrace Mark Kaplan's* "modest Bayesianism", which makes the modest claim that we can attach a relative confidence level to SOME pairs (or small sets) of statements of belief. If there's a reasonable basis for the ranking. — Relativist
If there is no pole of knowledge then I don't see how one IBE can be better than another (because no IBE can better approach that pole).
Similarly, if we know what ice is then we have a pole and a limit for the coldness of water. If we don't know what ice is, then the coldness of water is purely relative, and there is nothing to measure against. I would argue that knowledge is prior to IBE, and that IBE is parasitic upon knowledge. Thus if you make IBEs the only option, then there is nothing on which an IBE can be parasitic upon or subordinate to, and this undermines IBEs themselves. — Leontiskos
Does your "tentpole" comment refer to the mere fact that knowledge exists, are you suggesting IBEs that aren't based on knowledge are all equivalent, or something else entirely? — Relativist
That's also an intelligible argument, but I think it's weaker than the other one. This is because it seems to commit the error of applying the LEM to justification, so to speak. — Leontiskos
The words "infallible" and "fallible" are often used by "fallibilists" but never by "infallibilists," which makes me think they involve contentious presuppositions. — Leontiskos
But if "fallibility" means that we cannot be certain, then the same problem arises. — Leontiskos
Well you're walking a tightrope with these sentences. — Leontiskos
First of all, I have never claimed knowledge is impossible. I said it is rare. Is this sufficient for uncertain "knowledge"* to make sense, on your terms?The general idea here—which will apply to a large number of the epistemological theories on offer—is that if we abandon the possibility or notion of certain knowledge, then the replacement form of uncertain knowledge will cease to make sense. — Leontiskos
I'm good with all that. Just wanted to make the case that almost anything we claim to be true requires some (potential) justification. — J
the truth of things which are true by definition and logical self-evidence is simply obvious, and just needs to be pointed out to be established in conscious understanding.
— Janus
It is obvious to us. But we have learnt how to do reasoning as part of learning language and interacting with people. — Ludwig V
So, if we know p could be false, then we don't know that it's true, but we may well believe that it's true.
— Janus
Then on the premise that we know that every p (epistemological truth) could be false, we cannot know any p. — Leontiskos
I think we are still talking past each other. I take your point that there is an entailment involved and that this must involve two propositions. I also take your point that "Jones is the man who will get the job" and "Jones is Jones" are not equivalent, even though A=A.If there were only one proposition, then how could there be an entailment? Gettier's argument depends on the entailment, and entailments involve at least two propositions. "The man who will get the job" does not refer to either Smith or Jones. It is a descriptor. What this means is that, contrary to your view, Smith is not uttering a tautology when he says, "Jones is the man who will get the job." Such an utterance is not the same as, "Jones is Jones," even for Smith. — Leontiskos
I think we agree that (d) and (e) are two distinct propositions, and (d) implies (e)... suppose that Smith has strong evidence for the fol1owing conjunctive proposition:
(d) Jones is the man who will get the job, and Jones has ten coins in his pocket. .....
Proposition (d) entails: (e) The man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket.
Let us suppose that Smith sees the entailment from (d) to (e), and accepts (e) on the grounds of (d), for which he has strong evidence. In this case, Smith is clearly justified in believing that (e) is true. — Analysis. vol. 23 (1966)
That's right, because (e) also follows from (s) "Smith is the man who will get the job, and Smith has ten coins in his pocket." Now we know that if Jones gets the job, (e) will be true, and if Smith gets the job, (e) will be true. So it also follows that (e) is true, because whoever gets the job will have ten coins in his pocket.But imagine, further, that unknown to Smith, he himself, not Jones, will get the job. And, also, unknown to Smith, he himself has ten coins in his pocket. Proposition (e) is then true, though proposition (d), from which Smith inferred (e), is false. — Analysis. vol. 23 (1966)
No, I would not say exactly that. I do say that, given what S believes, when he asserts that the man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket, he is asserting something that he does not know to be true. But when the hiring agent says the same sentence, that needs to be interpreted in the light of their knowledge and beliefs, and the hiring agent does know that the man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket. Are we to say that Smith's belief is false? It depends whose point of view you regard as the appropriate context.Your theory amounts to the idea that when Smith says, "The man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket," he is saying something false. But when someone else says the exact same sentence, such as the hiring agent who knows that Smith has ten coins in his pocket, he is saying something true. — Leontiskos
Could you please explain to me the difference between a material conclusion and a formal conclusions? I'm not familiar with it. I may have forgotten what it is.So I think a material conclusion can differ from a formal conclusion, for example when both say the same thing and yet the "therefore" of the first is merely valid whereas the "therefore" of the second is sound. — Leontiskos
I would accept that. But I do have a reservation about the data. Unless I can make my own observations (or experiments), I have to trust the report of them. In order to pass on knowledge, we have to be able to assume a common context to at least some extent.I would go farther and say that you can see that their argument is correct. It's not so much a matter of trusting them. — Leontiskos
It depends what you mean by "necessarily". I suspect that you have in mind logical necessity, and that is not possible, because "there is a vase on the table" is contingent. In one way, I'll accept that we can imagine that the vase on my table is an alien or a hologram. But there is not a shred of evidence for either possibility, so there is no rational basis for an actual doubt. It is and empty possibility. In fact, when I try to imagine it, I cannot imagine how that possibility might have come about, except by a further fantasy which has little or no connection with reality. Contrast the possibility that the vase on the table is actually a listening device with a camera, planted by an evil agency to entrap me. But then, I can rule that out, so it is in a different class.As one banal example, why must something which by all accounts appears to all everywhere to be a vase on a table in fact necessarily be a vase on a table—such that it being a vase is true—rather than, say, being an extraterrestrial alien which is camouflaged as a vase, or else an advanced hologram — javra
Quite right too. (I sometimes wonder what distinguishes Descartes' evil demon from a paranoid fantasy.)But I also think that is too strong and that we do know some things with certainty, because I don't think skepticism based on the bare logic possibility of error should be taken seriously. — Janus
I agree that when it comes to claims of knowledge, justification is required. On the other hand I know many things with certainty that require no justification simply because they are directly known―in these cases justification just doesn't enter the picture. — Janus
The problem I think you see is of your own creation. Or so it seems to me. — Banno
I agree that when it comes to claims of knowledge, justification is required. On the other hand I know many things with certainty that require no justification simply because they are directly known―in these cases justification just doesn't enter the picture.
— Janus
And this resembles the "A or ~A" case, where it's difficult to see it in terms of justifications. Still, I think the conclusion we ought to draw from this is that we're not quite sure what a justification is. What sorts of reasons may play a part in justification? (We noted earlier that a "good justification" is very unclear, in many cases.) If you ask me for my justification in believing "I am having thought X right now" and I reply, "I am directly observing this occurrence as we speak," have I offered a justification? Perhaps so; that's one way of understanding what reasons count as justification, though I'd probably also need to say something about the previous reliability of my direct observations. Or we might conclude that "directly observing" and "having" are two ways of saying the same thing, so no actual reason has been offered. Then, if "I am having thought X" needs a justification, we'd have to look elsewhere. — J
But Wittgenstein disagrees with Moore’s depiction of this form of certainty as a kind of empirical knowledge. — Joshs
In one way, I'll accept that we can imagine that the vase on my table is an alien or a hologram. But there is not a shred of evidence for either possibility, so there is no rational basis for an actual doubt. — Ludwig V
I agree that when it comes to claims of knowledge, justification is required. On the other hand I know many things with certainty that require no justification simply because they are directly known―in these cases justification just doesn't enter the picture. — Janus
And this resembles the "A or ~A" case, where it's difficult to see it in terms of justifications. Still, I think the conclusion we ought to draw from this is that we're not quite sure what a justification is. What sorts of reasons may play a part in justification? (We noted earlier that a "good justification" is very unclear, in many cases.) If you ask me for my justification in believing "I am having thought X right now" and I reply, "I am directly observing this occurrence as we speak," have I offered a justification? — J
We shall say that we have acquaintance with anything of which we are directly aware, without the intermediary of any process of inference or any knowledge of truths. (Russell 1912: 78)
I say that I am acquainted with an object when I have a direct cognitive relation to that object, i.e., when I am directly aware of the object itself. When I speak of a cognitive relation here, I do not mean the sort of relation which constitutes judgment, but the sort which constitutes presentation. In fact, I think the relation of subject and object which I call acquaintance is simply the converse of the relation of object and subject which constitutes presentation. That is, to say that S has acquaintance with O is essentially the same thing as to say that O is presented to S. (Russell 1910/11: 108) — https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-acquaindescrip/#Dis
I'm afraid I didn't realize that. Fair enough.Yes, and, again, that was the entire point of the example given. — javra
Does that mean that you are thinking of seeing the pink elephant as introspection and so immune from mistake? I can't help feeling that applying the description "pink elephant" to whatever I am seeing is not immune from mistake.The person’s knowing that they are seeing a pink elephant is knowledge by acquaintance; it is non-inferential and so not contingent on justifications; — javra
I don't quite understand this. Our community ascribes false beliefs to people all the time and that's why they are called "intentional"In which case the intentionality associated with the believer's mental state is irrelevant with respect to the belief that the community ascribes to the believer — sime
I don't understand this either - apart from the first part. If beliefs did refer to the actual physical causes of the believer's mental state, we could never ascribe them to each other, since we mostly have no idea what they are.Beliefs refer to the actual physical causes of the believer's mental-state - in which case the believer's intentionality is relevant - so much so, that it is epistemically impossible for the believer to have false beliefs. — sime
The person’s knowing that they are seeing a pink elephant is knowledge by acquaintance; it is non-inferential and so not contingent on justifications; — javra
Does that mean that you are thinking of seeing the pink elephant as introspection and so immune from mistake? I can't help feeling that applying the description "pink elephant" to whatever I am seeing is not immune from mistake. — Ludwig V
hallucinations and mirages are not introspections (aka, self-examinations of one’s own being, thoughts, etc.) … but imaginings (such as can occur in daydreams) seen with the mind’s eye — javra
I can't help feeling that applying the description "pink elephant" to whatever I am seeing is not immune from mistake. — Ludwig V
That sounds right -- but it also means that we can't say the drunk saw a pink elephant. Seeing with the mind's eye is a metaphorical extension of what it means to see something. — J
I'd suggest that here truth is foundational, and knowledge derivative.An attempt to analyse truth in terms of knowledge using a definition of knowledge in terms of truth will of course be circular. — Banno
A. a belief merely refers to the coexistence of a believer's mental state and an external truth-maker, — sime
Or we might conclude that "directly observing" and "having" are two ways of saying the same thing, so no actual reason has been offered. Then, if "I am having thought X" needs a justification, we'd have to look elsewhere. — J
He asserts instead that it is a matter of our enmeshment in a “form of life”, a hinge on the basis of which to organize facts rather than the ascertainment of those empirical facts by themselves. — Joshs
This is spot on. But I don't think it is just pedantry.But in any case, this is about choice of terminology. We could say to the drunk, "No, you didn't," and mean either "You saw nothing" or "What you saw wasn't a pink elephant." Neither one is obviously correct, apart from pedantry. — J
I don't think there is any mistake at all. You are presenting a tediously familiar philosophical "problem" but in a way that makes us to look at the problem in a different way. The conceptual resources in your presentation do not allow a satisfying description of the situation. As you say, two contradictory answers seem both to be true. If you say the drunk saw nothing, you are not taking into account what they say and what they do - they do in fact behave as if they saw a pink elephant. If you say, what the drunk saw was not a pink elephant, you invite the question what they did see, and there is no answer, apart from nothing.I'd say the mistake is in the use of "see". — J
I take it that the three of us are 1) someone who says the drunk saw nothing, and 2) someone who says what the drunk saw was not an elephant and 3) the drunk who says that they saw a pink elephant? ln which case, you are quite right. But your description is excluding the "straightforward" answer that the drunk is hallucinating a pink elephant.But we're all three dividing up the conceptual territory the same way. — J
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.