• Michael
    15.4k
    Everything is what it is.
  • Michael
    15.4k
    And none of us can forget:

    Everything is a goat — Bill Capra
  • rachMiel
    52
    The Wittgenstein bubble should have been blank.
  • Christoffer
    2k


    Hehehe, yup, science have made metaphysics kinda irrelevant. We can use it for things that's still hard to prove, with proper logical arguments, but I find most metaphysical ideas today to exist among religious, spiritual people who can only form ideas around their beliefs rather than facts or people who think their personal opinions are facts, but I've rarely seen any proper metaphysical philosophy that don't use scientific premisses and facts.
  • Marchesk
    4.6k


    Except, Democritus was on to something, we're still debating some of those things, like the mind/body problem (consciousness in particular). Witty didn't end the speculation. He just added to the speculation that it might largely be the result of a misunderstanding of how language works.
  • Marchesk
    4.6k
    Hehehe, yup, science have made metaphysics kinda irrelevant.Christoffer

    Not really. Science has been able to answer some questions that used to be metaphysical. But there are plenty of questions that we don't know how to investigate empirically. Questions about consciousness, the interpretation of QM, laws of nature, causality, the nature of time, mereology, supervenience, the nature of perception, and various debates over realism vs anti-realism.
  • Marchesk
    4.6k
    Everything is what it is.Michael

    Which isn't saying anything. Water is water.

    Okay, but what makes water be like water and not like glass? Well, turns out ordinary matter has a chemical composition which determines that. And how does chemical composition determine the properties of water? Physics. And what determines physics? And now you're on to cosmology, which is one step removed from asking metaphysical questions.
  • Janus
    16.2k


    I think Collingwood makes a pretty good case that the only possible science of metaphysics would consist in a history of absolute presuppositions. Science, whether modern, medieval or ancient always involves indemonstrable metaphysical presuppositions; so Wittgenstein was dead wrong in saying (if he did say) that metaphysics is always merely an abuse of language. Of course this is not to say that there have not been examples of metaphysical thought which do consist in abuse of language.
  • Pierre-Normand
    2.4k
    Everything is what it is.Michael

    Wittgenstein was reportedly fond of Bishop Butler's aphorism: "Everything is what it is and not another thing".

    Arguably, this isn't so much an anti-metaphysical attitude as it is a repudiation of reductive analysis. Arguably, also, Wittgenstein's own philosophical quietism can be construed as being consistent with the practices of connective analysis, and of descriptive metaphysics, in the sense Peter Strawson used those phrases.
  • Banno
    24.8k
    I think Collingwood makes a pretty good case that the only possible science of metaphysics would consist in a history of absolute presuppositions. ...so Wittgenstein was dead wrong in saying (if he did say) that metaphysics is always merely an abuse of language.Janus
    What is a "absolute presupposition"?

    They appear not at all dissimilar to "hinge propositions".
  • Janus
    16.2k
    As I understand it. according to Collingwood absolute presuppositions are the fundamental principles upon which the fields of human inquiry depend. They are understood to be different than propositions in that it is inappropriate to speak about them in terms of truth and falsity.
  • Metaphysician Undercover
    13.1k
    They are understood to be different than propositions in that it is inappropriate to speak about them in terms of truth and falsity.Janus

    OK, if we can't speak of them in terms of whether they are true or false, why not identify them for what they are then? They're uncertain thoughts.

    As I understand it. according to Collingwood absolute presuppositions are the fundamental principles upon which the fields of human inquiry depend.Janus

    Collingwood seems to have a negative view of epistemology. He thinks that the fields of human inquiry are based on uncertain thoughts.
  • tim wood
    9.2k
    In any area of endeavor where thinking is involved, you get to ask if your process - whatever it is - is valid (true, provable, whatever qualifying word you want). Pretty quickly you get to, in some areas, axioms. Within the process or activity, the axioms are - well, we all know what axioms are, yes? Outside the process, a person may question axioms, but while the answers may be interesting, they are not relevant to the process itself - unless they destroy the process.

    For example, there are the axioms of plane geometry. Questions about one of them led to non-Euclidean geometry. That is, the parallel line axiom doesn't hold in some non-planar geometries (maybe all - I don't know). But it still holds in plane geometry. It's still an axiom; in plane geometry the same axiom it always was.

    Absolute presuppositions (different from ordinary and relative presuppositions) are both like and different from axioms. Different in that axioms are often questioned and scrutinized while absolute presuppositions are not. Similar in that they constitute the ground or foundation on which the activity stands.

    It's reasonable to question axioms, because how the results of the questioning break influences, rebounds back to, the endeavor. But it's hard to understand that questions as to the truth of absolute presuppositions are irrelevant. I know, all sorts of people get immediately exercised at the notion that something can be efficacious independent of its truth, but the idea is that it is an absolute presupposition, and the idea of an absolute presupposition is that you have to start somewhere. This isn't to say that the starting point is weighed and tested and argued on; usually it isn't. Absolute presuppositions evolve. And they change, usually as the result of a significant rupture in understanding and culture, whether large or small.

    One such is the idea of cause. The idea that each effect E is the result of a cause C is an absolute presupposition. Don't think so? Prove it! In other words, make it a relative presupposition resting on, depending on some more fundamental absolute presupposition, or prove it without making any presuppositions at all.

    Collingwood, whom I think discovered absolute presuppositions as absolute presuppositions, argued that Metaphysics is the discovery of what absolute presuppositions were/are made by what groups of people at what times. He makes this argument in a very readable book, An Essay on Metaphysics, at Amazon for about USD $20.

    His arguments, such as they are, and however poorly I may reference them, are significant and substantial. To be dismissive of them or to mock them without actually knowing something of what they are or understanding them, is simply to make a display of personal ignorance, aka stupidity. Far better to make the investment in understanding. Then argument may have merit and be worthy of respect, whether right or wrong.

    Here's a not very good example of an absolute presupposition. Suppose you need a sterile bandage. You find some at home, and you (relatively) presuppose that they're sterile. But they've been in your cabinet for five years, so it's reasonable to ask if these supposedly sterile bandages are really sterile. You decide you need to be sure, so you go to the pharmacy to buy some new sterile bandages. The presupposition that the pharmacy bandages are sterile is an absolute presupposition in the sense that they're what you're going to use, and the question as to their sterility does not arise (it is absolutely presupposed).
  • Banno
    24.8k
    They are understood to be different than propositions in that it is inappropriate to speak about them in terms of truth and falsity.Janus

    Where Wittgenstein differs from this may be in saying they are true but unjustifiable.
  • mcdoodle
    1.1k
    As I understand it. according to Collingwood absolute presuppositions are the fundamental principles upon which the fields of human inquiry depend. They are understood to be different than propositions in that it is inappropriate to speak about them in terms of truth and falsity.Janus

    My reading of Collingwood is that it's about questioning and absolute presuppositions. When you study a philosopher you come up with questions met with answers which lead to further questions which lead...eventually, to the point where the views of that philosopher offer no answer. Here are the absolute presuppositions which, I agree with Banno, bear a remarkable resemblance to hinge propositions.

    As someone on the old forum said to me, one very odd thing about Collingwood is that he held these seriously anti-ontological views (I don't think they are anti-epistemological) but he also went to church every Sunday and engaged in acts of worship.
  • aporiap
    223

    This comic makes Descarte the only dualist in the entire history of philosophy
  • tim wood
    9.2k
    I had to do quick review to see what a hinge proposition is, and it does seem like an absolute proposition. But I infer that Wittgenstein is still interested in the truth or falsity of hinge propositions, even as he regards them as indispensable to the matter at hand:

    "That is to say, the questions that we raise and our doubts depend on the fact that some propositions
    are exempt from doubt, are as it were like hinges on which those turn." (http://www.philosophie.uni-mainz.de/stei/downloads/SteiWittgenstein-Handout.pdf.)

    Collingwood, on the other hand, was clear about the irrelevance of the truth or falsity. For him, the important feature was that the absolute presupposition was absolutely presupposed by this or that group at such-and-such a time and place. He was not about reproducing whatever it was they were doing to see if their presuppositions were true by his modern standards; he was only interested in what in fact they presupposed, and presupposed absolutely. He called this activity of identifying them metaphysics and categorized metaphysics as an historical science - and made a compelling case for it all.
  • Janus
    16.2k


    Yes, I think what you say is kind of true, though not only of philosophy, but of science, economics, anthropology; in short of all domains of inquiry. As absolute presuppositions are also operative in the kinds of everyday commonsense beliefs that we could never foresee being overturned, they may be said to resemble hinge propositions. The difference is that in the domains of inquiry the absolute presuppositions are things we can be said to necessarily suppose, rather than believe, in order to carry out any investigation at all.

    So, for example that the cosmos is mind could be the absolute presupposition of an idealist philosopher, which is required for the further elaboration of his idealist philosophy. From within that philosophy the truth of its founding assumption can never be questioned; the question simply cannot arise. Similarly from within the methodological naturalism of the physical sciences the absolute presupposition that the cosmos is material cannot be questioned.

    There is also some commonality with Peirce's idea of 'regulative assumptions'. This paper:https://slideheaven.com/regulative-assumptions-hinge-propositions-and-the-peircean-conception-of-truth.html explores the commonality between Peirce's regulative assumptions and Wittgenstein's "hinge propositions". Here is the abstract:

    Abstract
    This paper defends a key aspect of the Peircean conception of truth—the
    idea that truth is in some sense epistemically-constrained. It does so by exploring
    parallels between Peirce’s epistemology of inquiry and that of Wittgenstein in On
    Certainty. The central argument defends a Peircean claim about truth by appeal to a
    view shared by Peirce and Wittgenstein about the structure of reasons. This view
    relies on the idea that certain claims have a special epistemic status, or function as
    what are popularly called ‘hinge propositions’


    This passage from Cheryl Misak's The American Pragmatists deals with Peirce's notion of 'regulative assumptions':

    His answer is that it is a regulative assumption of inquiry that, for any matter into which we are inquiring, we would find an answer to the question that is pressing in on us. Otherwise, it would be pointless to inquire into the issue: “the only assumption upon which [we] can act rationally is the hope of success” (W 2: 272; 1869). Thus the principle of bivalence—for any p, p is either true or false—rather than being a law of logic, is a regulative assumption of inquiry. It is something that we have to assume if we are to inquire into a matter. Peirce is clear and explicit on this point. To say that bivalence is a regulative assumption of inquiry is not a claim about special logical status (that it is a logical truth); nor is it a claim that it is true in some plainer sense; nor is it a claim about the nature of the world (that the world is such that the principle of bivalence holds). The principle of bivalence, he says, is taken by logicians to be a law of logic by a “saltus”—by an unjustified leap (NE 4: xiii). He distinguishes his approach from that of the transcendentalist:
    when we discuss a vexed question, we hope that there is some ascertainable truth about it, and that the discussion is not to go on forever and to no purpose. A transcendentalist would claim that it is an indispensible “presupposition” that there is an ascertainable true answer to every intelligible question. I used to talk like that, myself; for when I was a babe in philosophy my bottle was filled from the udders of Kant. But by this time I have come to want something more substantial.
    *

    Misak, Cheryl. The American Pragmatists (The Oxford History of Philosophy) (pp. 50-51). OUP Oxford. Kindle Edition.

    * the bolded text is Peirce's own words

    As someone on the old forum said to me, one very odd thing about Collingwood is that he held these seriously anti-ontological views (I don't think they are anti-epistemological) but he also went to church every Sunday and engaged in acts of worship.mcdoodle

    I don't know much about it, but apparently Collingwood accepted the truth of his own version of the Ontological argument, which might indeed seem odd considering his notion of the historical relativity of absolute presuppositions.
  • Janus
    16.2k
    OK, if we can't speak of them in terms of whether they are true or false, why not identify them for what they are then? They're uncertain thoughts.Metaphysician Undercover
    Collingwood seems to have a negative view of epistemology. He thinks that the fields of human inquiry are based on uncertain thoughts.Metaphysician Undercover

    An "uncertain thought" is a thought about which we are undecided as to whether it is true or not. Absolute presuppositions are understood to be things we necessarily suppose in order to investigate anything at all, and about which it is inappropriate to think in terms of their being propositions which could be demonstrated to be true or false; so...no.
  • Janus
    16.2k


    I'm not sure Wittgenstein could be considered to be consistent if he were to say that "hinge propositions" are true, even though they are not justifiable.
  • Metaphysician Undercover
    13.1k
    In any area of endeavor where thinking is involved, you get to ask if your process - whatever it is - is valid (true, provable, whatever qualifying word you want). Pretty quickly you get to, in some areas, axioms. Within the process or activity, the axioms are - well, we all know what axioms are, yes? Outside the process, a person may question axioms, but while the answers may be interesting, they are not relevant to the process itself - unless they destroy the process.tim wood

    What do you mean, "we all know what axioms are"? An axiom in mathematics exists by a completely different standard from an axiom in philosophy. And I am sure there are many in between.

    It's reasonable to question axioms, because how the results of the questioning break influences, rebounds back to, the endeavor.tim wood

    In philosophy an axiom is a self-evident truth. It is based in experience, description, and definition. It's really not reasonable to question an axiom unless you have reason to believe that the description or definition is inaccurate. In this case one might question it, because the so-called "truth" is not self-evident to that person who sees a fault in the description or definition.

    I know, all sorts of people get immediately exercised at the notion that something can be efficacious independent of its truth, but the idea is that it is an absolute presupposition, and the idea of an absolute presupposition is that you have to start somewhere. This isn't to say that the starting point is weighed and tested and argued on; usually it isn't. Absolute presuppositions evolve. And they change, usually as the result of a significant rupture in understanding and culture, whether large or small.tim wood

    Why not start with description rather than "absolute presupposition"?

    Here's a not very good example of an absolute presupposition. Suppose you need a sterile bandage. You find some at home, and you (relatively) presuppose that they're sterile. But they've been in your cabinet for five years, so it's reasonable to ask if these supposedly sterile bandages are really sterile. You decide you need to be sure, so you go to the pharmacy to buy some new sterile bandages. The presupposition that the pharmacy bandages are sterile is an absolute presupposition in the sense that they're what you're going to use, and the question as to their sterility does not arise (it is absolutely presupposed).tim wood

    What does this have to do with metaphysics?

    An "uncertain thought" is a thought about which we are undecided as to whether it is true or not. Absolute presuppositions are understood to be things we necessarily suppose in order to investigate anything at all, and about which it is inappropriate to think in terms of their being propositions which could be demonstrated to be true or false; so...no.Janus

    If we suppose them, we believe them to be true. I wouldn't suppose something I didn't believe to be true, except for the purpose of a counterfactual. So it's not true to say that we cannot speak of them in terms of truth or falsity, we are supposing them not for the purpose of counterfactual, we are supposing them as truth, therefore we speak of them as true.

    Even if we suppose them as counterfactuals, they are uncertain thoughts. So either way, if we suppose them as true when we have no reason to believe them as true, or if we suppose them as counterfactual, they are uncertain thoughts.
  • Janus
    16.2k
    If we suppose them, we believe them to be true.Metaphysician Undercover

    No, assuming something for the sake of investigation does not entail that I must believe what I am assuming to be true. Look at the example of bivalent logic in the passage quoted above from Misak's book on the American pragmatists.
  • Metaphysician Undercover
    13.1k

    OK, but it's still nothing more than an uncertain thought under your definition

    An "uncertain thought" is a thought about which we are undecided as to whether it is true or not.Janus
  • Janus
    16.2k


    No, it's not an uncertain thought under that definition, because its truth or falsity is not in question; we are not undecided about its truth or falsity; it is simply irrelevant.

    It is not an uncertain thought in any other sense, either, because it may be as clearly conceived as you like.
  • Metaphysician Undercover
    13.1k
    No, it's not an uncertain thought under that definition, because its truth or falsity is not in question; we are not undecided about its truth or falsity; it is simply irrelevant.Janus

    Yes the truth or falsity clearly is in question, according to that quoted passage. Did you read it? We hope to someday resolve it as to truth or falsity, though it is not resolvable at the time of making the presupposition.. From that quoted passage:

    “the only assumption upon which [we] can act rationally is the hope of success” (W 2: 272; 1869).Janus

    when we discuss a vexed question, we hope that there is some ascertainable truth about it, and that the discussion is not to go on forever and to no purpose.Janus

    The fact that we hope it will some day be resolved as true or false indicates that it is something which we are undecided about. It is an uncertain thought.

    It is not an uncertain thought in any other sense, either, because it may be as clearly conceived as you like.Janus

    That a thought is clearly conceived doesn't make it a certainty.
  • Janus
    16.2k
    “the only assumption upon which [we] can act rationally is the hope of success” (W 2: 272; 1869). — Janus


    when we discuss a vexed question, we hope that there is some ascertainable truth about it, and that the discussion is not to go on forever and to no purpose. — Janus


    The fact that we hope it will some day be resolved as true or false indicates that it is something which we are undecided about. It is an uncertain thought.
    Metaphysician Undercover

    You're misunderstanding what is written there. "We hope that there is some ascertainable truth about it" means that we proceed as if there were, otherwise we would not enquire; it does not mean that we are in a state of uncertainty about whether there is "some ascertainable truth". I'ts a subtle, but salient, difference you are missing.

    Think of it another way in terms of another example. Science (leaving aside QM) proceeds on the assumption that every event must have a cause. Science is not concerned with proving that every event must have a cause, because that would seem to be impossible, since we cannot possibly examine every event or even show definitively that the events we can examine had causes. Rather, an absolute presupposition of science is that every event has a cause; if we didn't think in terms of causation, science would be impossible.

    So we can say that whether or not every event has a cause is undecidable, but that does not mean that we are undecided about the truth or falsity of "every event must have a cause"; in fact we are not undecided about that at all, because we have decided that it is undecidable, and we have decided to adopt it nonetheless, because we have decided that it is indispensable to our inquiries.

    That a thought is clearly conceived doesn't make it a certainty.Metaphysician Undercover

    If the idea is clearly conceived and we are certain that it is indispensable to our inquiries, then it cannot be counted as an "uncertain thought".
  • creativesoul
    11.9k
    Attitudes towards statements of thought are where certainty and uncertainty reside. Attitudes.

    Thoughts aren't the sort of thing that can be certain or uncertain. Thoughts do not doubt their own truth. Rather, they presuppose it somewhere along the line. Uncertainty arises from doubt. It is a product thereof. If a thing cannot doubt, it is not the sort of thing that can be uncertain. Thoughts aren't the sort of thing that can doubt.

    Language use matters.

    The irony... :lol:

    I overstated the importance of language...

    :joke:

    Edited to add the following exception...

    To be clear... creatures without statements can be uncertain about the immediate future as well. My cat can be uncertain about the noise it heard, or about the stability of what she's about to step onto. Her thoughts about the noise and the structure aren't uncertain. Rather, she is as a result of having those thoughts.
  • tim wood
    9.2k
    If we suppose them, we believe them to be true.Metaphysician Undercover

    It's annoying, MU your deliberate misreading and disingenuous dismissal of what you have not troubled to understand. And your bending what you do read to your own interpretation without regard for what you do read. Absolute presuppositions are not supposed. They are absolutely presupposed. Now be quiet until you go find out what that means, because until you do, you don't know what you're talking about. Sorry to be blunt.

    The significance of them has nothing to do with their being either true of false. Their significance is that they were/are absolutely presupposed. This isn't open for debate; it is a fact. I can add to this, but until you do some reading, it's a complete waste of my time.
  • creativesoul
    11.9k
    It's annoying, MU your deliberate misreading...tim wood

    I do not believe that it is deliberate. It's very annoying none-the-less.
  • creativesoul
    11.9k
    Absolute presuppositions are understood to be things we necessarily suppose in order to investigate anything at all...Janus

    This reminds me of what Kant called a priori. That which is necessarily presupposed by experience itself.
bold
italic
underline
strike
code
quote
ulist
image
url
mention
reveal
youtube
tweet
Add a Comment

Welcome to The Philosophy Forum!

Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.