↪VagabondSpectre
For me, Noam is a puny ant, he hasn't even come under my radar, that's how (un)important he is — Agustino
In modern academic and popular culture circles, and I swim in none of those.but he certainly has a mighty high reputation in many circles — VagabondSpectre
In what sense are space and time ideal if they are not a priori? It seems to me that it is necessary to a priorize them à la Kant to prove them to be ideal...ideality of space and time — The Great Whatever
But space isn't perceptual - you don't perceive space, you perceive objects in space.Ideal, meaning not independent of their perception. What is perceptual doesn't need to be a priori. — The Great Whatever
:-} Yes obviously. Nowhere did I claim that. For something perceived to be ideal doesn't require it to be a priori - and space isn't perceived - things are perceived in space. So it could very well be that the objects and perceptions given in space are ideal, but not space itself. So I'd say that for something non-perceptual to be ideal does require it in some sense to be a priori - hence why space and time are called transcendentally ideal.The point was just that something being ideal, even in the sense Kant uses the term, is not for it to be a priori. — The Great Whatever
The point was just that something being ideal, even in the sense Kant uses the term, is not for it to be a priori. — The Great Whatever
Yes obviously. Nowhere did I claim that. For something perceived to be ideal doesn't require it to be a priori — Agustino
In what sense are space and time ideal if they are not a priori? It seems to me that it is necessary to a priorize them à la Kant to prove them to be ideal... — Agustino
So I'd say that for something non-perceptual to be ideal does require it in some sense to be a priori - hence why space and time are called transcendentally ideal. — Agustino
Conditions of perception are not themselves perceived - the eye does not see itself. Therefore, you can say that objects of perception are ideal - which is what Berkeley does - but to make the claim that space, time etc. are ideal requires making them a priori.It's misleading to call space and time 'non-perceptual' in Kant's sense, because although they aren't objects of perception, they are conditions of perception, and so in this sense are not independent of perception (are not transcendentally real), which is precisely what Kant's point is. — The Great Whatever
Who held them before Kant?But Kant didn't invent the aprioricity of time, space and causality. These are old rationalist notions. — The Great Whatever
Well of course most of a thinker's ideas aren't original, even if he is a great thinker, like Kant or Schopenhauer - however, some of them are original insights. It would be strange to say that there are no original insights, and everything has already been thought before.My point is we tend to be ahistorical in discussing individual thinkers, because as single people we just don't read very much, so we don't understand that individual thinkers are not as original as they seem to be when read in isolation. — The Great Whatever
Sure he was reacting against Hume's skepticism of causality, I'm already well aware of that.In fact, to understand Kant, you must understand that it was the attempt to empiricize especially causality that he was reacting against. Again, situate it in history. — The Great Whatever
Conditions of perception are not themselves perceived - the eye does not see itself. Therefore, you can say that objects of perception are ideal - which is what Berkeley does - but to make the claim that space, time etc. are ideal requires making them a priori. — Agustino
Who held them before Kant? — Agustino
Well of course most of a thinker's ideas aren't original, even if he is a great thinker, like Kant or Schopenhauer - however, some of them are original insights. It would be strange to say that there are no original insights, and everything has already been thought before. — Agustino
Sure he was reacting against Hume's skepticism of causality, I'm already well aware of that. — Agustino
Objects of perception are given in space. Space is a precondition of perception, and therefore cannot itself be perceived. You cannot hold space, touch space, etc.Though there seems to be no good reason to me to believe space isn't an object of perception. — The Great Whatever
Yeah maybe if you're looking in a mirror.And of course, the eye does see itself. — The Great Whatever
I am unaware that they held them, if you have evidence of this please cite it.Pretty much every rationalist philosopher prior to Malebranche and Leibniz and so on. — The Great Whatever
Insight has to do with how one solves a problem provided by his context. It can be impressive if the way the problem is solved is spectacular, as in Kant's case with regards to causality.It's not that I think everything has been thought before, it's just that in its milieu no purportedly original insights look very impressive. Their impressiveness is a function of ignorance of the surrounding historical context. — The Great Whatever
No they didn't think everything was empirical, quite obviously. But neither did they think that causality was a precondition of any experience at all... that's Kant's original insight. And in fact, Hume's criticisms would have been irrelevant if philosophers had already thought of causality as a precondition to any and all experience - so Hume was certainly not acting against that position.But consider: how could Hume have been making a stride for Kant to react against, if prior to Kant, everyone had already thought causation was empirical (Hume's position)? — The Great Whatever
Yes that's true. So what? The way he salvaged it is genius - that is original.Kant was trying to salvage an older position that Hume was attacking. — The Great Whatever
Objects of perception are given in space. Space is a precondition of perception, and therefore cannot itself be perceived. You cannot hold space, touch space, etc. — Agustino
Yeah maybe if you're looking in a mirror. — Agustino
I am unaware that they held them, if you have evidence of this please cite it. — Agustino
Insight has to do with how one solves a problem provided by his context. It can be impressive if the way the problem is solved is spectacular, as in Kant's case with regards to causality. — Agustino
No they didn't think everything was empirical, quite obviously. But neither did they think that causality was a precondition of any experience at all... that's Kant's original insight. — Agustino
Ok so on this view, causality is associated with the intelligibility of the world, not with its possibility - the world could possibly not be intelligible, and indeed that is a different statement from that mentioned before, and requiring separate proof. Under Kant, the world simply cannot but be intelligible, since all experience is so structured.But you can start with the Stoics – I'm no expert on this, but they believed that the necessity of causation was a necessary precondition for the rational intelligibility of the world (and therefore for its existence, since reality is inherently intelligible) — The Great Whatever
Yes >:) just like opium causes sleep because it has sleep inducing properties"By means of a faculty?" — The Great Whatever
No... the rationalist position has been that causality is required to make the world intelligible - no rationalist held it that causality was required to be able to make the world possible - it was only with regards to the world's intelligibility that this was under discussion. So if they were wrong about the world's intelligibility, then obviously they could be wrong about causality. Causality wasn't certain in other words, which is exactly what Hume attacked. But Kant showed that they can't be wrong about causality, and showed why the world is necessarily intelligible - because it is structured, a priori to experience, by space, time and causality. This is a significant achievement, because it makes the question "is the world intelligible" redundant.I think maybe this is debatable, but the rationalist position has always been that causality is a prior necessary to hold the world together, as its precondition — The Great Whatever
Can you please provide me with a citation for this? Has René shown that there is an unexperienced synthesis of self and world that occurs prior to experience and indeed makes experience itself possible?Descartes – synthetic unity of apperception — The Great Whatever
the world could possibly not be intelligible — Agustino
But Kant showed that they can't be wrong about causality, and showed why the world is necessarily intelligible - because it is structured, a priori to experience, by space, time and causality. This is a significant achievement, because it makes the question "is the world intelligible" redundant. — Agustino
Yes he would obviously deny it, but he would have to provide additional argument for it. That's what it means when something isn't certain. Kant created a framework in which this was certain.I think a classical rationalist would deny this. — The Great Whatever
I think his analysis of experience shows that experience - as we find ourselves experiencing - necessarily will follow those necessities - we cannot even imagine it being otherwise. But of course, it could be possible.In fact Kant didn't show that – he postulated it, but there's nothing to show that the way our faculties happen to be are necessary – it's only that given that we have faculties that enforce necessities within them, such necessities obtain – well, within them. — The Great Whatever
I tend to agree with this. The contingency was well noted afterwards with the advent of modern physics. Our synthetic judgements, while a priori, aren't necessary. This may sound shocking but it basically means that we're in all cases, a priori, having a form of say space, imposed on our experience, but how we conceive of this space (Euclidean, non-Euclidean, etc.) can be different, and indeed can change. What cannot change is that we must have some sort of conception - ie space is an a priori form of experience. It's the necessity of a particular conception which vanishes.So there is a deeper contingency to Kant's system, even if you take his positing of such faculties as justified. — The Great Whatever
I don't know who it was addressed to, but I do remember reading about Descartes not taking the cogito as a syllogism but rather as an intuition. Fine. So how does this show that "any thought that was had must be 'my' thought (which is the unity of apperception)"? How is 'any thought that was had being "my" thought' equivalent to:I had in mind his response to Hobbes (I think it was) when he claimed that the cogito wasn't a syllogism as such, but a sort of bootstrapping intuition on which allowed one to conclude that any thought that was had must be 'my' thought (which is the unity of apperception). — The Great Whatever
:san unexperienced synthesis of self and world that occurs prior to experience and indeed makes experience itself possible — Agustino
I think his analysis of experience shows that experience - as we find ourselves experiencing - necessarily will follow those necessities - we cannot even imagine it being otherwise. But of course, it could be possible. — Agustino
an unexperienced synthesis of self and world that occurs prior to experience and indeed makes experience itself possible — Agustino
Descartes was an idiot — Agustino
Kant renounces Berkeley explicitly but ends up adopting his position almost exactly. — The Great Whatever
Because unlike them, he deeply analysed the processes of reason, knowedge, and thinking itself. — Wayfarer
What are the conditions by which I know the world, or what is good, or what is beautiful? — Wayfarer
He differentiated his view from Berkeley in a lengthy argument in the second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason, the 'Refutation of Idealism'. — Wayfarer
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.