Comments

  • The Old Testament Evil
    Nothing in God's late condemnation of Saul suggests the misrepresentation thesis.Count Timothy von Icarus

    I haven't read much on this point, but it seems to me that the condemnation remains intelligible as long as we don't take the Samuel thesis to an extreme. Saul's actions seem indefensible in general.

    So I think this line could be fruitful even if we don't go the route of the "deceiving" thesis:

    I remember the writing in bSamuel as brilliant and capturing what can happen even when legitimate prophecy is granted to the crooked timber of humanity.

    ...

    In Torah, you'll hear, e.g., "And God said to Abraham...." In the book of Samuel, this doesn't happen, and instead, it's Samuel telling Saul to put Amalek under the ban. The key here is Samuel. He could be correctly and perfectly conveying God's will, or he could be mistaken, or he could be deceiving. The clarity of Torah, where we see God's words openly dictated, is no longer present in Samuel.
    BitconnectCarlos

    Meier's Themes and Transformations in Old Testament Prophecy would generally support this thesis, as he argues that the potency, competency, and clarity of prophets gradually diminishes as the Bible draws on.
  • The Christian narrative


    So true. :fire:

    ---

    I continue to be impressed by the amount of gymnasticsjorndoe

    I continue to be impressed by the anti-Trinitarian "mysticism". "It's totally contradictory. I don't have a coherent argument for that conclusion, but just take my word for it!~" Usually one comes to the conclusion that something is contradictory after making a serious argument to that effect. Not on TPF, though. :wink:
  • Referential opacity
    Dude,Banno

    On your reasoning, we can disprove the thesis simply by noting that Superman wears a cape whereas Kent does not. Therefore they are not equal or identical.Leontiskos

    You're just kicking the can and avoiding the concrete question. What you mean by "=" is something like, "equivalent with respect to the properties that we take to be relevant," and you haven't the slightest idea of what should count as a relevant or irrelevant property. Else, on your "all properties" account, there are no two things that are equal. Therefore, as I said, your "=" is just a matter of different names for the same thing. Again:

    Consider two biconditionals:

    SC: The two terms can be substituted salva veritate within this context ↔ The two terms are equivalent within this context
    SA: The two terms can be substituted salva veritate in every context ↔ The two terms are equivalent in every context (i.e. the two terms are absolutely identical)

    Both of these biconditionals are true, but this is the argumentation that leverages SA:

    i. [Claim that two terms can be substituted in every context]
    ii. [Identify a context in which the two terms cannot be substituted]
    iii. Draw a reductio of some kind

    For example:

    1. "Superman" = "Clark Kent."
    2. Lois believes that Superman can fly.
    3. ∴ Lois believes that Clark Kent can fly.

    As I pointed out above, (1) is false, but it is false in a very deep sense. This is because SA is a linguistic impossibility, and therefore to stipulate that some pair of terms satisfies SA is to stipulate a linguistic impossibility. It’s therefore no surprise that one can always find a context in which the two terms cannot be substituted once one moves out into the real world.
    Leontiskos

    SA is a linguistic impossibility. Leibniz' whole point was that if you have two things with all the same properties, then you don't have two things. You were mistaken and there is only one thing after all. Thus the "=" on your definition is by definition not a two-place relation. Instead it is a reflexive relation where the object is identical to itself, and where we have mistaken a single object for two different objects. It is epistemology trying to disguise itself and pass for a static proposition. It is a conflation of reference and referent.

    "Superman = Clark Kent" is logically presupposing both that there are two things being related, and that there are not two things but only one thing. It's that inherent contradiction that is the problem, and which is so bound up in your own thought.
  • The Old Testament Evil
    I apologize: I was not understanding you before. I thought you were referring to demonic possession. Indeed, I agree that it is much more questionable if demonic hybrids would have rights.Bob Ross

    That's alright - it's an understandable assumption. At this point we are knee-deep in obscura. :smile:
    For example, according to the secondary literature the demons that Jesus casts out were originally spawned by groups like the Amalekites, and roamed the Earth looking for hosts after being killed by the Israelites.

    Could God wipe them out justly? I don’t know, but it would definitely violate the rationale I gave above for rights.Bob Ross

    That's a fair argument you give. What's interesting is that when Jesus encounters these demons that—according to the secondary literature—originally came from groups like the Amalekites, they say things like this:

    And behold, they cried out, “What have you to do with us, O Son of God? Have you come here to torment us before the time?”Matthew 8:29 (RSV)

    The backstory here is that in his mercy and providence, God has allowed such beings to continue to exist on Earth until "the time," namely the end times. So oddly enough, there is a respect even for demons built into the narratives. Jesus even accedes to their request in v. 32.

    Yes, but no one that objects with those to me (so far) has ever coherently defined what ‘murder’ is. Like I said, that view may be internally coherent in some theory; but it isn’t coherent with the idea of rights I expounded above. Do you have a different definition of murder that you prefer such that God and the Angel of Death are not committing murder?

    My definition, to recap, is that murder is the direct intentional killing of a person.
    Bob Ross

    Yes, and it's fair enough that you would press your point. Let's try to understand the logic a bit. First, your argument, which of course presupposes that murder is impermissible:

    1. Murder is the direct intentional killing of an [innocent] person
    2. The Angel of Death intentionally kills the innocent Amalekite infant
    3. Therefore, the Angel of Death is a murderer

    And then the reductio I mentioned (although I will not here present it as a reductio):

    4. It is the Angel of Death's job to take life
    5. It is not impermissible to do one's job
    6. Therefore, the Angel of Death is not a murderer

    This is the case where there is a logical standoff between two contradictory conclusions, and yet there is no attempt to formally invalidate the opposing argument. Formal reductios also function in precisely this way. If we have only these two arguments, then one must simply weigh them and decide which is stronger.

    Digging deeper, (4) and (5) have to do with the idea that death is inevitable, and that for a person to die is not inherently unjust. This opens up the can of worms of the metaphysics and ethics of death, and the adjacent can of worms is the question of God's sovereignty within which question is the matter of whether God is responsible for death (or whether God "directly intends" the fact of natural death).

    So this all gets complicated quickly, and therefore it is hard to try to capture the various complexities with a syllogism or two. For example, if everything that occurs is allowed by God to occur, and if this allowance counts as an intentional bringing-about, then it follows that everyone who dies is murdered. The reductio in this case lies in the idea that murder and death are two different things. Note too that we are wrestling with precisely the same issue that the Hebrews wrestled with in trying to understand God's sovereignty and providence (in, for example, hardening or not-hardening Pharaoh's heart).

    Interesting. It seems like Fr. Stephen is taking a more spiritual approach to the theology and the Bible (going back to the beginning of our conversation).Bob Ross

    I wouldn't say that he takes a more spiritual or metaphorical approach to theology and the Bible, but I can see how this video in particular might produce that idea.

    His critique is fair insofar that systematizing is can go too far and systematize for the sole sake of doing so (e.g., Kant); but I wonder how valid this critique really is: he seems to just have given up on striving towards perfect knowledge. It seems like systematic knowledge is just the attempt at, or aspiration towards, complete knowledge. Should we really give that up? What do we have left after doing so?Bob Ross

    This is a really interesting and complicated topic, but I will try to say a few things.

    In general we recognize that one must collect the data before they form their theory or propose their thesis. We also recognize that if a theory is invalidated by data, we have to accept that rather than stubbornly cling to the theory while ignoring the data. I think De Young is saying that a lot of people have over-simple theories that run into problems when deeper and broader datasets are encountered. For example, I am told that there is a fun documentary on the Super Smash Bros video game, which follows different groups of people who thought they were the best and had mastered the game, only to find that others were much better (and that South Koreans are often elite in such matters).

    It's something like that: you thought you understood it until you understand that you don't. That is Socrates' virtue: an understanding of his own limitations and ignorance. De Young is saying that when it comes to God this phenomenon gets taken to a whole new level (cf. Isaiah 55:8-9).

    At the same time there is the danger of falling into the other extreme, which is what I think you are speaking to. There is the danger of skepticism or despair of knowledge altogether. There is the danger of theological voluntarism where God becomes wholly inscrutable. Yet what happens when one settles into a deep tradition such as Christianity, is that they settle into the habit of finding they were mistaken and thus being prepared to see how they are currently mistaken. This creates an openness to a reality beyond them (and this same phenomenon occurs when someone takes on a teacher, acknowledging that they have much to learn). I want to say that this humble stance towards reality and God is incredibly important, even if one rejects Christianity. We can of course reject things, but (please God) we should never find ourselves in a place where a self-confidence has closed us off to reality or to that which transcends our own capacities.
  • The Christian narrative
    That must mean there is something objective and particular about the concept of the TrinityFire Ologist

    I think this is right. The "sensus fidelium" could not exist if what is agreed upon were truly incoherent.
  • The Christian narrative


    That was a very good bringing-together of various different strands of the thread. :up:
    I was revisiting Damascene's exposition of the faith to see how much more accessible it is than Aquinas. It is certainly more accessible, but perhaps still not accessible enough for what this thread would require.

    Wholly instrumental analytic reason is in a sense diabolical (in both its original and current sense).Count Timothy von Icarus

    Agreed. And we can hold that such an approach is diabolical while also maintaining that it need not be explicitly atheistic (for example). The issue has to do with a closed-off-ness to both analogical reasoning and transcendence.

    -

    Let's just leave it at this: on it's face, the Catholic Trinity appears to be contradictory.frank

    If there is a contradiction, then present the argument for that conclusion. As I noted earlier, internecine differences over the Trinity do not turn on the question of contradiction. They turn on the question of consistency with Scripture, the Fathers, or other such sources.
  • ChatGPT 4 Answers Philosophical Questions


    Thank you, that is very helpful! Let me ask a few follow-up questions.

    As a result, the base-model has the latent ability to express any of the wide range of intelligible opinions that an author of some piece of the training data might have produced, and has no proclivity to adjudicate between them.Pierre-Normand

    Isn't it true that the opinions of the author of some piece of training data will converge in some ways and diverge in others? For example, the opinions might converge on the idea that slavery is wrong but diverge on the question of who will be the Governor of Nevada in 2032. If that is right, then how does the LLM handle each case, and how does one know when the opinions are converging and when they are diverging? Similarly, [what] criteria does the LLM use to decide when to present its answer as a mere opinion, and when to present its answer with more certitude?

    During post-training, the model's weights are reconfigured through reinforcement learning in order to fit the schema USER: <query>, ASSISTANT: <response>, USER: <follow up question>, etc. and the models responses that are deemed best in accordance with predetermined criteria (usefulness, harmlessness, accuracy, etc.) are reinforced by human evaluators of by a reward model trained by human evaluators. Some political biases may arise from this process rather than from the consensual or majority opinions present in the training data. But it is also a process by means of which the opinions expressed by the model come to be pegged rather closely to the inferred opinions of the user just because such responses tend to be deemed by evaluators to be more useful or accurate. (Some degree of reward-hacking sometimes is going on at this stage).Pierre-Normand

    Great.

    So suppose the LLM's response is an output, and there are various inputs that inform that output. I am wondering which inputs are stable and which inputs are variable. For example, the "post-training" that you describe is a variable input which varies with user decisions. The "predetermined criteria" that you describe is a stable input that does not change apart from things like software updates or "backend" tinkering. The dataset that the LLM is trained on is a variable input insofar as one is allowed to do the training themselves.

    I am ultimately wondering about the telos of the LLM. For example, if the LLM is designed to be agreeable, informative, and adaptive, we might say that its telos is to mimic an agreeable and intelligent person who is familiar with all of the data that the LLM has been trained on. We might say that post-training modifies the "personality" of the LLM to accord with those users it has interacted with, thus giving special weight to the interests and goals of such users. Obviously different LLMs will have a different telos, but are there some overarching generalities to be had? The other caveat here is that my question may be incoherent if the base model and the post-trained model have starkly different teloi, with no significant continuity.

    It's more akin to a rational reconstruction of the opinions that the model has learned to produce under the constraints that this response would likely be deemed by the user to be useful, cogent and accurate. Actual cogency and accuracy are achieved with some reliability when, as often is the case, the most plausible sounding answer (as the specific user would evaluate it) is the most plausible answer.Pierre-Normand

    Okay, interesting. :up:

    (I also read through some of your GPT links. :up:)
  • The Christian narrative
    Googling "God: Multiple persons sharing one being" returns the Trinity.Banno

    Is that really a surprise?

    Banno is a case in point for the future in which LLM-based arguments become synonymous with a kind of self-fulfilling prophecy bias. What Narcissus would have given for an LLM to reflect back to him his own prejudices!
  • The Christian narrative
    ↪frank But I think what I've said in the above posts acknowledges all of that. I said:

    So two men both 'participate' in the form 'man' even though they are numerically different men.
    Wayfarer

    One (rather limited) way of approaching the Trinity is as a mean between the extreme of a strong emphasis on the persons (which moves in the direction of polytheism) and the extreme of a strong emphasis on the unification of the divine nature (which moves in the direction of emphasizing the divine nature at the expense of the personal distinctions).

    So on this scheme we're sailing down a river where the north shore is polytheism, the south shore is ousia-overemphasis, and we want to stay in the middle of the river and avoid crashing into either shore. As with all areas of subtle philosophy, overcorrection is a constant danger.

    Banno presented " an unlikely strawman that very little attention is [historically] paid to the idea at all." You responded by pointing to the idea that "is God" is indicating the predication of a nature, and that is definitely the right response to Banno's odd transitivity argument. You gave an example of two men who participate in the form of 'man' (human), which is also a helpful illustration. The quibble against your example is that the persons of the Trinity are not separated from each other in the way that human persons are separated from each other, and that if for some reason we take your example to be identical to the Trinity, then it fails: it veers too close to the north shore. This objection is intelligible, but I don't see any reason to assume that you were offering the example as something more than an analogy.

    (Another way of viewing that objection is as a utilization of Euthyphro-like reasoning against the reification of the ousia.)

    The danger for the Catholic is polytheism.Banno

    No, Catholicism (and Western Christianity in general) has always veered closer to the south shore. Polytheism is the danger for Eastern Christianity.

    When Catholics say the Father is God, they are not predicating. They aren't saying God is a category the Father belongs to. It's an identity statement. The Father is not a section of God. The Father is fully God. Whatever God is, the Father is equal to that.frank

    No, this is not right. I would go back to my posts where I quoted the Catechism of the Catholic Church. We can say that the Father is God (in the Triune sense), but by that we include the Son and the Spirit with the Father, for they are never apart (except notionally, in the single notional case where an exclusive relation of origin is being considered). More commonly, we would say that the Father is divine (and this is a matter of ousia).

    Regarding my post to you about John 1:1, there is an ancient sense in which "God" ("the god") is used hypostatically to refer to the Father, but the semantics of the hypostatic use and the Triune use are distinct.

    Christianity is the most ideologically dynamic of all the global religions because it's a fusion of several different sets of cultural outlooks and values.frank

    Perhaps this is most true of Christianity given its geographic sprawl, but it is also true of many other religions to a lesser extent.

    Kastrup uses this as a metaphor for the relationship between individual minds and what he calls “mind at large.” Just as each dissociated identity experiences itself as a separate person, we experience ourselves as separate individuals—when, in his view, we are all expressions of the same underlying mind manifesting in different ways.Wayfarer

    In a more individual way Trinitarian thought is often applied analogously to psychological health. When the various aspects of one's personality become dissociated, one becomes mad, corrupt, divided, schizophrenic, etc. When the various aspects of one's personality enter into a symbiotic and fruitful union, one achieves psychological health. Monomania would be the case where only one aspect of one's personality is allowed to continue existing.
  • Referential opacity


    And I'll note that you've failed to answer the simple question, "What does <Superman = Clark Kent> mean?," three times now.

    More of the same from Banno.
  • Referential opacity


    Why not just admit what I've said from the start: that you don't know what you mean when you say things like, "Superman = Clark Kent"?

    On your reasoning, we can disprove the thesis simply by noting that Superman wears a cape whereas Kent does not. Therefore they are not equal or identical.
  • Referential opacity
    This is not a complete account, but it'll do.Banno

    So again, what does <Superman = Clark Kent> mean? And is the "binary predicate" true or false in this case?

    (I of course responded to your confusions yesterday.)
  • Referential opacity
    "=" is very well defined in both maths and logicBanno

    Then give your account of what <Superman = Clark Kent> means.

    I only grant that it is well-defined in mathematics.

    Analytics like Banno seldom have any idea what they are doing when they say, "x = y," as they assume that anything can be placed into that form. They don't recognize the mathematical context and the single genus of the relata that their formulation takes for granted.Leontiskos
  • Referential opacity
    That conclusion (not premise) could only be made by someone who knew both the differences and sameness between what is a “Clark” and what is a “Superman”.Fire Ologist

    Right. In order for (1) to avoid tautology there must be rational movement, and this requires some difference between the two relata.

    And of course I don't mean that we can't use (1) as a premise, but rather that we must be prepared to give an argument for such premises. Such premises are not self-evident.

    P1: X = Y
    P2: Z is ready enough to say "X can fly."
    P3: Therefore, Z is ready enough to say "Y can fly."

    I don’t think this apparent controversy is about an apparent flaw in the notion “X = Y”, but from the insertion of the “Z is ready to say that…”. Z’s belief creates a new context in which we must redefine X and Y. So we can’t substitute the use of either X or Y from P1, in any sentence following P2; P2 has redefined X and Y according to Z’s belief.
    Fire Ologist

    Yeah, I think you're right about this. P3 requires a premise about whether X = Y for Z.

    But drumming my point, we could also scrutinize P1. What does P1 mean? In the Superman case it is supposed to mean that one and the same thing goes by two different names. Is that what it means in a mathematical context? I'd say the fact that we don't really know what we are saying with (1) is significant. Given that there are so many multivalent meanings to P1, it is itself a kind of analogical claim. Presumably disambiguating P1 would shed light on P3.
  • The Christian narrative
    How did I end up analogizing the Trinity to a single human person, and it jibes with Aquinas, but I didn’t go to Aquinas? Incoherence in the notion of a ‘Trinity’ would make this an utter accident.Fire Ologist

    Yes, and what's interesting here is that the development of the concept of personhood had a great deal to do with Trinitarian theology. The precision that we now have around the word "person" did not exist in the 4th century. Theater and Trinitarian thought were two of the principle ways that the concept was developed.

    There is a similar way in which someone might think that a cardinal (bird) looks like a Roman Catholic Cardinal, or that cappuccino looks like a Capuchin's habit. In fact the bird and the coffee were named after Cardinals and Capuchins, and so the causality is reversed.

    This all helps give the lie to the idea that religious thinking is somehow private or irrelevant. Religious thinking forms the basis for much of our current thought and language.
  • The Christian narrative
    'Essence' is 'what is essential to the being', from the Latin 'esse' 'to be'. So two men both 'participate' in the form 'man' even though they are numerically different men.Wayfarer

    Right. So if we stumbled upon an organism, we might wonder whether it is human. We might come to decide, "This thing is of the same nature as John Doe (and is therefore human)."

    The genesis of Trinitarian theology is the same. Folks were wondering what Jesus is. The Council of Nicea came to decide, "The Son is consubstantial with the Father (and is therefore divine)."
  • Referential opacity
    @bongo fury

    I can’t say I understand Analytic Philosophy’s interest in this sort of substitutability and “referential opacity.” It seems endlessly confused.

    For example, suppose “Superman” = “Clark Kent.” This looks like an absurd supposition from the start. The only reason Clark Kent exists at all is because “Superman” != “Clark Kent.” If Superman and Clark Kent were equivalent and therefore substitutable, then this would only mean that Kal-El’s disguise or pseudo-identity had failed.

    More generally, if we have two names for the exact same thing (identical both notionally and mind-independently), then one of the names is superfluous and pointless. This hangup with referential opacity seems to be a matter where one posits that superfluous and pointless case and then supposes that it is a centrally important case. How the heck is this case deemed so important?

    Probably what is happening is that the “objective” identity is focused on so strongly that one forgets that what is (supposedly) “objectively” identical need not be notionally identical. It seems controversial to claim that the “objective” referent of “Superman” and the “objective” referent of “Clark Kent” are identical, but I would say that it is clearly false to claim that the two signs have notional equivalence. Even to the narrator, “Superman” means something like, “Kal-El in his superhero identity,” whereas, “Clark Kent,” means something like, “Kal-El in his secondary identity, disguised as a human.” That they are not simply equivalent means that they cannot be substituted in every context.

    More simply, “Superman” and “Clark Kent” are not different names for the same thing. The whole point of a disguise is to create a “name” that does not reference the true referent. Thus it is much truer to say that “Clark Kent” means “Not-Superman” than to say that “Clark Kent” and “Superman” name the same thing.

    What’s weird is that the person interested in this sort of thing might respond, “Okay, so Superman isn’t the best example of this.” But what is the best example? Wouldn’t the best example be something that is completely absurd rather than only partially absurd (like Superman)? It seems like the best example would be two words which refer to the exact same thing, such that there is no notional difference, no difference of semantic range, no connotative difference, etc. The best example looks to be a sheer linguistic impossibility.

    Am I missing something important here?

    ---

    Let me sketch out my guess at what is occurring.

    Consider two biconditionals:

    • SC: The two terms can be substituted salva veritate within this context ↔ The two terms are equivalent within this context
    • SA: The two terms can be substituted salva veritate in every context ↔ The two terms are equivalent in every context (i.e. the two terms are absolutely identical)

    Both of these biconditionals are true, but this is the argumentation that leverages SA:

    i. [Claim that two terms can be substituted in every context]
    ii. [Identify a context in which the two terms cannot be substituted]
    iii. Draw a reductio of some kind

    For example:

    1. "Superman" = "Clark Kent."
    2. Lois believes that Superman can fly.
    3. ∴ Lois believes that Clark Kent can fly.

    As I pointed out above, (1) is false, but it is false in a very deep sense. This is because SA is a linguistic impossibility, and therefore to stipulate that some pair of terms satisfies SA is to stipulate a linguistic impossibility. It’s therefore no surprise that one can always find a context in which the two terms cannot be substituted once one moves out into the real world.

    I think the issue has to do with epistemic direction, and this error plagues much of Analytic Philosophy. SC and SA are only epistemically coherent (and generally useful) when one moves from the first half to the second half. “These two terms are substitutable, therefore they are equivalent—either in this context or in every context.” That is how one reasons. A judgment of equivalence is inherently a conclusion rather than a premise. Equivalence is never intuited or stipulated.

    Now we did get a kind of argument for equivalence in this thread. In this thread (1) was supported by the argument, “Term1 and term2 both rigidly designate the same thing.” Yet note that this does not fulfill SA, namely because it does not address the “context” where such a thing is not believed by Lois. Validity would require, “Term1 and term2 both rigidly designate the same thing, and every rational agent knows this.”

    Note that this sort of thing happens all the time among TPF Analytics. For example, in the thread from which this thread was spawned, was just assuming by fiat that the Christian theological terms “Jesus” and “God” are unconditionally substitutable. It is the same sort of move from, “Superman is Clark Kent,” to, “Superman = Clark Kent” (in the sense of SA), albeit with a different context-valence.
  • The Christian narrative
    In this case, “is” doesn’t mean numerical identity (as in "Clark Kent is Superman") but rather participation in a common essence.Wayfarer

    Spot on. Apparently this has been explained quite a few times throughout the thread. :up:
  • Value as a Subject-Object Relation
    The abstract of your article contains such outrageous grammatical errors that I am inclined to suspect either that it was written by rather poor AI, or that you are only semi-literate.alan1000

    You are mistaken. There are no grammatical errors in the abstract.

    It looks like an interesting article.

    The second problem is that to read the article, I have to sign on to a website, with the obvious security compromise which that entails.alan1000

    Academia.edu is a highly regarded website, and your idea that having to sign in is prohibitive doesn't make much sense. You also have to sign in on TPF, after all.
  • ChatGPT 4 Answers Philosophical Questions
    Owing to the way they've been post-trained, all LLMs are largely unable to offer political opinions of their own.Pierre-Normand

    Can you expand on that?

    My assumption was that—supposing an LLM will not offer contextless political opinions—it is because a polemical topic is one where there is wide disagreement, lack of consensus, and therefore no clear answer for an LLM.

    I'm also curious what the difference is between, "Do you think Trump is a good president?," versus, "Does [some demographic] think Trump is a good president?," especially in the case where the demographic in question is unlimited (i.e. everyone). It seems like the two questions would converge on the same question for the LLM, given that the "opinion" of the LLM should be identical with the various opinions (or rather, linguistic patterns) which it collates.
  • Referential opacity


    That's a good post, frank. :up:

    In Aristotelian-speak we would say that a material phoneme is not a formal word, and that the presence of a rigid designator requires certain intentions and beliefs on the part of the speaker.

    T1 has to show up in the b sentence, and it's not there. There's nothing to substitute.frank

    ...And so the question asks what t1 really is, given that the material markings which attend t1 are not sufficient for the presence of t1. So if we let t1 = "Superman," we haven't yet achieved what is needed for "objective" substitution-claims, given that "Superman" means different things to different people (i.e. the term is equivocal). Approaching these issues without something like 's Setoid is a dead end.

    Substitutability depends on equivalence, and given that no rational or logical law/relation sidesteps the filter of belief, therefore it is false to claim that substitutability depends on equivalence irrespective of belief. If John does not believe that two terms are equivalent, then John cannot substitute them, and it is sheer confusion to think that there is some case where a substitution occurs but a "John" does not exist.
  • Referential opacity
    It is reasonable to think that the relationship between L and some other category W that represents an alternative analytic conception of the world, can be described in terms of a functor F : L --> W.sime

    Right, and I think a lot of this could be tied back to the "God's-eye view" question. If no category (L, W, etc.) is inherently privileged over any other, then it looks like the referential opacity "problem" cannot even arise.

    Put differently, if we omit the presupposition that there is a "narrator" perspective which provides indisputable facts, then there is merely a disagreement between Lois ( L) and the observer (W) over whether Superman is Clark Kent. In that case each accuses the other of holding a mistaken belief which in turn influences their belief about what is permissibly substitutable.

    (The reason I find this example so strange is because, depending on the time index, Lois may or may not believe that Superman is Clark Kent.)
  • The Christian narrative
    They believed God is everything.frank

    In the sense that God is everything - God is the “in” and “with” of all things.
    But in the sense that each separate thing is separate from each other (like this rock and that drink), each separate thing is not God and God is not that thing.
    Fire Ologist

    Right. So to take a group like the Stoics, the Logos is seen to order all things without remainder, but what is at stake is not an ontological thesis. Logos-providence does not entail pantheism.

    So now here’s the analytic side of it. Leontiskos does the above make sense to you? It’s not expressly dogma, or from someone else - just my attempt to speak about the Trinity and how is see it. Where is there blatant error and where is it correct?

    I think you, @Leontiskos can check my math and see coherence with the basic doctrines in some of the above, see the logic of it.
    Fire Ologist

    I think the general thrust is correct. The traditional Christian metaphysics of the God-world relation tends to be participatory rather than a matter of identification. God does things like create, sustain, and guide creation, but he is not himself creation. An ontological creator-creation distinction is maintained in traditional Christianity.

    (And you made a distinction between God as a category of being and God as the living being we know as God. And you talked of “the God” versus “God”. These are all necessary distinctions, but I think it can confuse this further. Meaning, I follow you, but I could see someone misconstruing that you are saying there is more than one God.).Fire Ologist

    To simplify the whole question, because the ancient Greek texts did not have the uppercase-lowercase distinction, and they did not have indefinite articles, therefore they were unable to linguistically represent 'God' in the way that we commonly do today. But there are pros and cons. One of the cons of our own idiom is that although everyone uses the term 'God', it is not at all clear when the term is being used with any clear sense.

    What is a person?Fire Ologist

    :up:

    Aquinas sees this as the preliminary question to the whole discussion.
  • The Christian narrative
    Fine. The use of Logos tells that it's related to Plato, the Stoics, and Philo. The basic idea was that God is everything. That's what Plotinus believed. I'm happy to give you the victory over sorting out what Catholics believe.frank

    Okay, well thanks for that. Logos was a philosophical term of art, but it was also a common linguistic term. Both are probably at play in John's prologue.

    The basic idea was that God is everything.frank

    Not for any of the figures you mention (i.e. pantheism).

    I'm glad you concede that Catholics do not fall into the transitive problem. More generally, I would say that in an anthropological sense it is mistaken to attribute extremely simplistic mistakes to millennia-old traditions. Millennia-old traditions do not make extremely simplistic mistakes, such as failing to recognize the law of identity or transitivity, and this includes all sorts of religions and traditions. This is because 1) just because someone lived before the 21st century does not make them dumb; 2) adherents of a tradition will tend to scrutinize their tradition more thoroughly than outsiders given that they think about the issues more seriously; and 3) when you have the input of billions of people over thousands of years, extremely simplistic mistakes do not survive. It is this remarkable underestimation of millennia-old traditions that I find especially problematic.
  • The Christian narrative
    Fine. You're saying John 1:1 is saying that the Word was with the Father, and the Word was divine.frank

    Yep, and it's the same with predications of the Son. His nature/ousia is God/divine. But he is not "the god," where "the god" means something like the Father or else a generic god-person. The Nicene Creed says, "Consubstantial with the Father," which is the much more traditional phrase.

    262 The Incarnation of God's Son reveals that God is the eternal Father and that the Son is consubstantial with the Father, which means that, in the Father and with the Father the Son is one and the same God.Catechism of the Catholic Church, #262
  • The Christian narrative
    I cannot come to know any person by reason alone. Not you, not Banno, not my children. I cannot come to know many things by reason alone.Fire Ologist

    That does an injustice to the Trinity. The mystery of knowing the Trinity is not akin to the mystery of truly knowing the nuances of me, Banno, or a fine wine.

    We don't have official declarations that we can't know each other. The Trinity is not just a routine complicated thing.
    Hanover

    Nah, @Fire Ologist is right on the money. Here is the Catechism:

    236 The Fathers of the Church distinguish between theology (theologia) and economy (oikonomia). "Theology" refers to the mystery of God's inmost life within the Blessed Trinity and "economy" to all the works by which God reveals himself and communicates his life. Through the oikonomia the theologia is revealed to us; but conversely, the theologia illuminates the whole oikonomia. God's works reveal who he is in himself; the mystery of his inmost being enlightens our understanding of all his works. So it is, analogously, among human persons. A person discloses himself in his actions, and the better we know a person, the better we understand his actions.

    237 The Trinity is a mystery of faith in the strict sense, one of the "mysteries that are hidden in God, which can never be known unless they are revealed by God".58 To be sure, God has left traces of his Trinitarian being in his work of creation and in his Revelation throughout the Old Testament. But his inmost Being as Holy Trinity is a mystery that is inaccessible to reason alone or even to Israel's faith before the Incarnation of God's Son and the sending of the Holy Spirit.
    Catechism of the Catholic Church

    The inner life of others is also opaque to us unless they "let us in," and once they do that their outer works are made transparent. Granted, the Trinity is moreso, but the similarity is significant.
  • The Christian narrative
    98% of Christian denominations accept the Trinity from a doctrinal point of view, yet only 16% of Christians actually accept it. https://www.arizonachristian.edu/wp-content/uploads/2025/03/AWVI-2025_03_Most-Americans-Reject-the-Trinity_FINAL_03_26_2025.pdf?utm_source=chatgpt.com

    What this means is that there is a distinction between self avowing as a Christian and being a part of the institution of Christianity. Such is common among religions, particularly large ones.
    Hanover

    I think it only means that not everyone studies Trinitarian theology.

    I have always thought Christians were polytheistic, not as a criticism, but just a fact, not having any reason to particularly care to save them from it. I found Mormon belief clearer and just more forthright, but, again, there were no consequences for my view. I might as well have been studying the Greek gods.Hanover

    The Mormon view is clearer. But it isn't representative of Christianity.

    My point here is that I can fully understand preposterous views, like a snake talking to Eve, but you're arguing from incoheremce. While you may say it all makes sense if you think about it long enough, it really doesn't.Hanover

    Well you presented an argument and I pointed out why your argument fails. Calling it "preposterous" but being unable to present a valid argument against it is not helpful.

    This is the official view of the Catholic Church:

    "The mystery of the Most Holy Trinity is the central mystery of Christian faith and life. It is the mystery of God in himself. It is therefore the source of all the other mysteries of faith…” (CCC §234)

    “The Trinity is a mystery of faith in the strict sense… We cannot come to know the Trinity by reason alone.” (CCC §237)

    This is a direct nod to mysticism. While you might use reason to get at it somewhat, ultimately it's "a mystery."
    Hanover

    We've covered this ad nauseum in the thread. "Mystery" does not mean "preposterous" or "contradictory."

    I do note in the Creed that it refers to "we," which could simply mean human reason cannot be used as a basis to understand the Trinity, and it would follow also that it can't be used to reject the Trinity. We can neither come up with reasons to prove it exists or that it doesn't, but we accept on faith that it does.Hanover

    No, that is incorrect. The Catholic view is that the Trinity is not contradictory, and that is why Catholics such as Augustine answer charges of contradiction, and they do it substantively. They do not say, "Oh it's a mystery so you can't argue against it by definition." That's not what Catholicism means by "mystery."

    Look, our religious difference seems to have everything to do with the truth-aptness of religious claims. You always go back to the idea, "None of this is provable or disprovable or rational or irrational, and none of it really matters anyway (for there are no differences that arise on account of these beliefs), so let's all just stop arguing about it." I think that is deeply mistaken. If one has that view then a lackadaisical approach to religion is warranted, such as failing to distinguish Mormons from traditional Christians. But if one does not have that view then the lackadaisical approach is not warranted. In that case we would have to take the objections seriously and admit that religion is susceptible to rational objections. It seems like I think religion is susceptible to rational objections and you don't, and therefore we approach all of this from significantly different vantage points.

    If Christian, confirmation bias is dogmaticaly imposed and it eliminates the possibility of disproof and it entails belief regardless. You can understand then the feeling that there is no value in the debate. Your mind can't be changed by operation of law, so to speak.Hanover

    I've explained why this claim fails quite a few times. Check out my posts towards the end of <this thread>.

    You're therefore not in a battle with the analytics or the users of reason. You're in a battle specifically with non-Christians who reject your demand of acceptance of Church dogma and refuse to humbly accept their human rationality cannot comprehend divine rationality.Hanover

    This is an incorrect framing, and it evinces the same lackadaisical attitude that led you to interpret me to be saying the exact opposite of what I had said. You aren't reading or interpreting posts carefully, likely because you hold to an a priori position which says that none of this matters anyway.

    This therefore has nothing to do with secularism versus theism or analytics versus whatever. This is just whether one is willing to be Christian or not. If true Christians tied to doctrinal belief (98%) constitute the authentic Christians, then this is just about being Christian or not, and not about being an Analytic, a rationalist, a theist, or whatever.Hanover

    Believe it or not, people don't just decide whether to be a Christian or not for no reason whatsoever. It has to do with other holdings, including things like rationalism, theism, atheism, etc.

    My belief holds, for example, that death is mourned because the opportunity to perform God's law has ended. Heaven, in all its glory, is not sought after, but is brought to earth by good acts. We seek to bring God here, not to go to the heavens for God. It's a this worldly religion based upon what you do. It's not a religion centered around eternal rewards.

    My point is that you probably find that profoundly wrong, and you may find issues within it unresolvable, but why should I pretend to care. I don't hold my views because they are logically consistent, empirically provable, or factually credible. I hold them for meaning, purpose, comfort, morality, sense of community, sense of beauty, utilitarian benefit, belonging, etc etc.
    Hanover

    I don't think religious positions are inadjudicable. I think your belief in the inadjudicability of religious positions is mistaken.

    I guess I'm asking, why the grappling in the muck with the non-believers when you've got enough reason to believe even if some of their academic objections can't be readily overcome?Hanover

    Because a fallacious argument against Christianity impedes others from life in God.

    Look, if you believe something is good and shareable, and someone gives a fallacious argument against it, then (ceteris paribus) you should point out the problems in the argument. If you don't do that then you don't care about others sharing in the good.

    Obviously Judaism is not an evangelistic religion, and that's a big difference. But the idea that one should protect what is good and true is not a strange idea.
  • The Christian narrative


    This is actually a really excellent question and objection, given that my claim is that "The Son is God" is never used in early Christianity.

    In the Greek of Jn 1:1 the first instance of 'God' includes the definite article whereas the second does not.

    So if we use your NIV translation but include the articles and omit the capitalization, we get this:

    "In the beginning was the word, and the word was with the god, and the word was god."

    The reading that you and Banno see is, "...and the word was the god," which is on par with, "Jesus is the god."

    In the Biblical mindset god (theos) is not a binary notion. For example, angels and demons would also be described with theos or similar terms (which have to do with generalized divinity). Nevertheless, the Hebrew authors still differentiate the one god or the creator god from lesser divinities. In the New Testament Greek this is usually done with the definite article ("the god"). This is why, for example, Jn 1:1 was not a knockdown argument against Arius, for Arius saw the Word as a divine being unequal with the one god.

    So in that Jewish and Early Christian idiom, "the god" is the Father, whereas Jesus is the Son of God. This same idiom is present in the Nicene Creed as well as in current Catholic and Orthodox liturgy. "God" used hypostatically refers to the Father.

    So the opening Collect of a Roman Catholic liturgy is conditional in the following way:

    – If the prayer is directed to the Father: "Through our Lord Jesus Christ, your Son, who lives and reigns with you in the unity of the Holy Spirit, one God, for ever and ever";
    – If it is directed to the Father, but the Son is mentioned at the end: "Who lives and reigns with you in the unity of the Holy Spirit, one God, for ever and ever";
    – If it is directed to the Son: "Who live and reign with God the Father in the unity of the Holy Spirit, one God, for ever and ever."
    — Roman Missal, Third Edition

    Now I bolded each instance of 'God'. You can see that instances 1, 2, and 4 are a Triune use of 'God', whereas 3 is the ancient hypostatic use of 'God' (the Father).

    Another example is the opening Collect from the first Sunday of Advent (chosen at random):

    Grant your faithful, we pray, almighty God,
    the resolve to run forth to meet your Christ
    with righteous deeds at his coming,
    so that, gathered at his right hand,
    they may be worthy to possess the heavenly Kingdom.
    Through our lord Jesus Christ, your son,
    who lives and reigns with you in the unity of the holy spirit,
    one God, for ever and ever.
    — Roman Missal, Third Edition

    Again, instance 1 is hypostatic whereas instance 2 is Triune (despite the fact that the Father is never without the Son and Spirit).
  • The Christian narrative
    Well, I know what I mean... Ands the thread is pretty much about trying to make sense of what you mean.Banno

    Tell me what you mean by 'is' and what you mean by 'God' and I will tell you whether the proposition "Jesus is God" is true.

    Curiously, when I typed "Shield of the Trinity" into Google, the AI gave an overview. Part of the overview was that the diagram can be misleading insofar as some might see four entities (Father, Son, Spirit, God), and that they might therefore mistake "is" for a copula of identity. Ding ding!

    -

    Edit: Else, to avoid repeating myself:

    Again, basing the entire discussion on a heuristic diagram which is famous for its oversimplification is not a good approach. Here is a clause from the Catechism of the Catholic Church that most closely approximates the same idea:

    262 The Incarnation of God's Son reveals that God is the eternal Father and that the Son is consubstantial with the Father, which means that, in the Father and with the Father the Son is one and the same God.
    — Catechism of the Catholic Church, #262

    We could disambiguate the modern phrase, "The Son is God":

    A. "The Son—in the Father and Spirit and with the Father and Spirit—is God"
    B. "The Son—apart from the Father and the Spirit—is God"

    (A) is theologically true whereas (B) is theologically false. The Son is never apart from the Father and the Spirit. What is happening in this thread is that (B) is being claimed as Catholic teaching, and this is false given that (B) is not Catholic teaching. (B) is a hostile translation of a highly compacted and oversimplified diagram.* In the contemporary colloquial idiom when Catholics speak of "God" as a sort of proper name they are talking about the Triune communion of persons: Father, Son, and Holy Spirit. For Catholics the inner life of God is tri-personal, and this creates friction with the standard account of 'God' as mono-personal. The hostile translation (B) is presupposing 'God' as a mono-personal hypostasis, which would place the relata into the same genus and accord with a transitive property of identity. But anyone with knowledge of historic Christianity will know that this is a misrepresentation, that for Christians the generic "God" is triune rather than a single hypostasis, and that "Son" and "God" therefore belong to different genera. ↪Bob Ross was correct in saying that what is at stake is a predication rather than an identity relation. That is a remarkably accurate interpretation of Nicene Christianity.
    Leontiskos
  • The Christian narrative
    That's the reasoning behind the substitution argument given earlier. If in "Jesus is God" and "The Holy Spirit is God" the "is" is that of identity, then we ought be able to substitute and get "Jesus is the Holy Spirit". But Scripture won't let us.Banno

    The underlying idea that, "'Son' and 'God' are formally substitutable terms," requires an insane ignorance of Christian Trinitarianism.Leontiskos

    -

    Are you now denying that Jesus is God?Banno

    You literally don't know what you mean when you say, "Jesus is God." You literally have no idea what you mean by "is," and now you are trying to leverage your ambiguous, bumper-sticker phrase to try to somehow shame me. :lol:
  • The Christian narrative
    In syllogistic logic, all relations are reduced to single-places predications. “Socrates is taller than Plato” have to be paraphrased into one-place predicates like “Socrates is-a-thing-taller-than-Plato” before entering a syllogism. Something like "Tully is Cicero" has to be treated not as a relation, but as a single-placed predicate. It has to be treated the same way as, say, "Tully is a writer". Tully is a member of the group of writers, and Tully is a member of the group of things which are Cicero.Banno

    This is just more ignorance of history, in this case syllogistic logic. Syllogistic logic is predicative. For example, "Socrates is human," is not the single-place predicate H(S). Pretending it is is a kind of myopic projection of predicate logic beyond its bounds. That's what your strange analysis of "is" is: an awkward shoehorning of natural language into the straightjacket of specialized logical devices.

    But all of this is based on your insistence that we must stick with your bumper sticker formulation, "Jesus is God," despite the fact that the theological sources simply do not rely on such bumper sticker formulations. Were we to abandon the bumper sticker, your strawman would fall apart. So we can't do that! :grimace:
  • The Christian narrative
    - Yes, the analogy limps insofar as it utilizes the idea of separable parts. Yet my point is that an age which accepts (2) will surely reject the Trinity.
  • The Christian narrative
    One of the great weaknesses of Analytic Philosophy is that it doesn't recognize that logic follows upon being, and that every approach to logic presupposes a metaphysics. Older logicians were better logicians than the Analytics because they understood this.

    Thinking now of these metaphysical premises, presumably it is no coincidence that a numerical objection to the Trinity has become popular in an individualistic age. The core argument is something like this:

    1. The Trinity is a unified multi-hypostasis reality
    2. But there are no unified multi-hypostasis realities
    3. Therefore, the Trinity cannot exist

    For example, in our day it is commonly believed that a social reality constituted of persons is reducible to persons. So someone in our day might say that a "family" is a fiction, and all that really exists in a family are the individuals.

    On that assumption the Trinity is "illogical" (precisely because it contradicts the metaphysical doctrine of (2)). But a negation of (2) is not implausible. Families are arguably multi-hypostasis realities, and not mere fictions. The "superorganism" of a beehive is another example, where the hive is more than the sum of its parts. The Trinity will be seen as possible so long as we see unities which are more than the sum of their parts as possible. The Trinity is a bit like a beehive where the hypostases are in such elegant concert that it is hard to tell where one begins and another ends, and where the bees are nonplussed about this fact. This extreme unification is precisely why Christianity holds that Trinitarian activity ad extra is not differentiable from standard monotheism.
  • The Christian narrative
    - Oh, dear. :sweat:
  • The Christian narrative
    The source was openly an LDS source, That's why frank provided the picture of the Mormons on bikes. @Banno then cited another article describing other views on the Trinity. The point then was just to point out there wasn't Christian consensus on the Trinity.Hanover

    Okay...

    I've pointed out the problems with appealing to Mormonism on Christian questions. Banno is quoting from SEP and is mistakenly transferring its philosophical authority into a religious authority. SEP is really not a reliable theological source. In that article it is adopting one particular way of ordering very recent logical approaches to the Trinity.

    None of that has much to do with consensus. There is a Christian consensus on the Trinity, and it is based in the Councils of Nicea and Constantinople (325 and 381).

    Thus approximately 98.5%[59] of the world's Christians are Nicene Christians, adhering to the Nicene Creed's Trinitarian and Christological doctrines. The remaining 1.5% include non-Trinitarian groups such as the LDS Church, Jehovah's Witnesses, Swedenborgians, etc.Nicene Creed | Wikipedia

    If the LDS are to be counted as Christians, then they account for 0.61%, and SEP's logical taxonomy has nothing to do with representation or consensus. So I would say that the OP's focus on Catholicism is representative of Christianity generally, especially if we favor the general Nicene tradition.
  • The Christian narrative
    The trinity is three entirely seperate personages, not a single entity. They have a common purpose, and they're referred to as the godhead. Such is true Christian theology. https://www.churchofjesuschrist.org/comeuntochrist/article/do-latter-day-saints-believe-in-the-trinity

    When you say "the Christian narrative" and then start going on about the Nicene Creed which was arrived at 325 years after Jesus' death, you're just taking about your peculiar brand of modified Christianity.
    Hanover

    I was looking through your posts to try to understand where you are coming from. Maybe part of the problem here is that you are depending on Mormon sources. At least the second sentence of your article is candid:

    Like many Christians, we believe in God the Father, His Son Jesus Christ, and the Holy Spirit. However, we don’t believe in the traditional concept of the Trinity. — Mormon Source
  • The Christian narrative
    I think it struggles if it's subjected to basic logical demands (e.g., law of identity, law of non-contradiction, etc.).Hanover

    Well we can look at your argument too, which I would say comes down to this:

    I don't know where [Hanover's] either/or is coming from.Leontiskos

    -

    1. Yahweh is God. Jesus is God. The holy spirit is God.

    2. . Hanover is a person, Bob is a person, Frank is a person.

    3. Hanover is Banno. Bob is Banno. Frank is Banno.

    Is 1 like 2 or is 1 like 3? Clear this up for me.

    If 1 is like 2, then you have three things that fit into a single category.

    If I is like 3, then you either have 1 person with 3 names or a 3 headed monster.
    Hanover

    You are giving a dilemma:

    4. Either "is God" means something like "is a person" or else "is God" means something like "is Banno"
    5. Either way we arrive at an anti-Trinitarian outcome
    6. Therefore, the doctrine of the Trinity is inconsistent

    As I alluded to, the either/or of (4) is ad hoc and false, and therefore your argument is unsound. Christians say what "is God" means, and it means, "is divine," or, "Homoousios with the Father."

    Again, basing the entire discussion on a heuristic diagram which is famous for its oversimplification is not a good approach. Here is a clause from the Catechism of the Catholic Church that most closely approximates the same idea:

    262 The Incarnation of God's Son reveals that God is the eternal Father and that the Son is consubstantial with the Father, which means that, in the Father and with the Father the Son is one and the same God.Catechism of the Catholic Church, #262

    We could disambiguate the modern phrase, "The Son is God":

    • A. "The Son—in the Father and Spirit and with the Father and Spirit—is God"
    • B. "The Son—apart from the Father and the Spirit—is God"

    (A) is theologically true whereas (B) is theologically false. The Son is never apart from the Father and the Spirit. What is happening in this thread is that (B) is being claimed as Catholic teaching, and this is false given that (B) is not Catholic teaching. (B) is a hostile translation of a highly compacted and oversimplified diagram.* In the contemporary colloquial idiom when Catholics speak of "God" as a sort of proper name they are talking about the Triune communion of persons: Father, Son, and Holy Spirit. For Catholics the inner life of God is tri-personal, and this creates friction with the standard account of 'God' as mono-personal. The hostile translation (B) is presupposing 'God' as a mono-personal hypostasis, which would place the relata into the same genus and accord with a transitive property of identity. But anyone with knowledge of historic Christianity will know that this is a misrepresentation, that for Christians the generic "God" is triune rather than a single hypostasis, and that "Son" and "God" therefore belong to different genera. was correct in saying that what is at stake is a predication rather than an identity relation. That is a remarkably accurate interpretation of Nicene Christianity.

    ()


    * The misrepresentation is also being used by @frank as a support for the strawman of the OP.
  • The Christian narrative
    I think there is an explanation of the many instances of “is” in the Triune God. I can provide some of them. Count and Leon have provided some.Fire Ologist

    Again, @Banno's argument is invalid, and obviously so:

    1. Son = God(head)
    2. Spirit = God(head)
    3. Therefore, Son = Spirit {transitive property of identity}

    Again, the transitive property of identity requires relata of the same genus:

    The presupposition when using the transitive property of identity is that each of the relata are the same kind of thing (i.e. belong to the same genus). So if A, B, and C are all numbers, then we can apply the transitive property of identity to them. But if A is a number, B is an animal, and C is a solar system, then we cannot.Leontiskos

    4. 2+2 = 4
    5. 3+1 = 4
    6. Therefore, 2+2 = 3+1 (transitive property of identity)

    7. 3 = giraffe
    8. giraffe = Copernican System
    9. Therefore, 3 = Copernican System (transitive property of identity)

    (6) is valid whereas (3) and (9) are not.

    Count has already pointed this up:

    It's "one nature, three persons." Consider the analogous case of human nature:

    Mark is human. (A is B)
    Christ is human. (C is B)
    Therefore Mark is Christ. (A is C)
    Count Timothy von Icarus

    A nature (ousia) and a person (hypostasis) are not of the same genus, and this is why Banno's argument is invalid.

    Analytics like Banno seldom have any idea what they are doing when they say, "x = y," as they assume that anything can be placed into that form. They don't recognize the mathematical context and the single genus of the relata that their formulation takes for granted. This is one example of why Banno's philosophy is so unreflective. In a philosophical sense, "x = y" pertains to epistemic moves, where a single object goes by two different names. There are just too many reasons why this sort of approach is utterly inappropriate when talking about the Trinity. The underlying idea that, "'Son' and 'God' are formally substitutable terms," requires an insane ignorance of Christian Trinitarianism. It is such an unlikely strawman that very little attention is paid to the idea at all.
  • The Christian narrative
    I fed the last page into Claude and received the following review:Banno

    @Hanover, @Baden - isn't this literally against the rules of TPF? An entire post of AI? Further, Banno is constantly telling us that "I win because AI said so," all the while failing to provide even the prompts he is providing to the AI. Is this really what the forum has come to? Is this rule still being enforced?

    AI

    AI LLMs are not to be used to write posts either in full or in part (unless there is some obvious reason to do so, e.g. an LLM discussion thread where use is explicitly declared). Those suspected of breaking this rule will receive a warning and potentially a ban.

    AI LLMs may be used to proofread pre-written posts, but if this results in you being suspected of using them to write posts, that is a risk you run. We recommend that you do not use them at all
    Baden

    Making AI say whatever you want it to say is pretty easy. Hanover knows this:

    ↪Banno Then continue your conversation with ChatGPT and ask it for Jewish interpretations that it stands for repudiation of human sacrifice and then have it compare that to your other post. Then argue with it and have it change its mind.

    It has such poor resolve I find
    Hanover
  • The Christian narrative
    Leontiskos's suggestion that analytic philosophy is overly restrictive when evaluating the Trinity because it demands logic is difficult to accept,Hanover

    This is a very strange interpretation given that I said just the opposite:

    The Analytic, with his tiny set of norms, must ultimately admit that pretty much everything passes muster, at least on Analytic grounds.Leontiskos

    To the extent we're referencing the analytic tradition as elaborated by Wittgenstein and Davidson, particularly with their dispensing with the idea that meaning is based on an internal referent, I see Leon's point. If the soul is an entity and the love one has for God is a true thing in one's heart, it's entirely inadequate to suggest these words refer to just their use and not some mystical entity.

    And we've got to keep in mind that the linchpin of Wittgenstein's enterprise is in denying private language, which is a metaphysical impossibility to the theist because his internal state is publicly shared by God. That is,a theist might see Wittgenstein's theory as a brilliant reductio that proves without God you are limited to an absurdly restricted system of language. Of course, the secular analytic embraces this conclusion and runs with it.
    Hanover

    I don't see theology as private, even if we are prescinding from the idea that God is part of the group. Theology has always been a public, social enterprise.

    But then I disagree with Leon in his hesitation to accept that logical thought (which here I mean logical reasoning, which includes analogizing and the use of precedent as authority) by itself is not a religious act.Hanover

    I said that logical thought can but need not be worship. I would say that the fact of logical reasoning is not itself worship even if the material object is construed as "religious." So for example, if an atheist is logically analyzing Rabbinic literature, he is not engaged in worship.