What I have consistently said is that reductio is not valid in the same way that a direct proof is. — Leontiskos
To me, RAA depends on modus tollens. — Lionino
But my fuller position is that any inference utilizing strange senses of would-be familiar logical concepts must be used with care. I am not opposed to the Mines of Moria, but I don't think people are taking enough care in traversing them. — Leontiskos
If ¬(B∧¬B) is true, as it must be, then this is not a valid use of modus tollens.A→(B∧¬B)
¬(B∧¬B)
∴ ¬A — Leontiskos
Rubbish.you said you preferred the reductio to the modus tollens. — Leontiskos
So I ask again: How is it that something and its negation can both [function as the second premise of a modus tollens]? — Leontiskos
I think Leontiskos is talking about choosing between the conjuncts, while Banno is correctly stating that reduction ad absurdum is formally valid. — Lionino
Ok, Presenting a statement that someone has not made is not presenting an interpretation. :roll:I literally said it was an interpretation, not a translation. — Leontiskos
Quite so. So what? It remains that RAA is a valid inference in classical propositional logic.This does not contradict what I have been saying. — Leontiskos
Neither do I. This distinction between false and FALSE is not my doing. It seems to be another case of Leontiskos confabulating arguments on the part of those who disagree with him.Banno may speak for himself, but I don't know what difference in reference you mean by spelling 'false' without caps and with all caps. — TonesInDeepFreeze
Presenting a statement that someone has not made is not presenting a translation.That was my interpretation of Banno, not Banno himself. — Leontiskos
I agree with Tones that you habitually misrepresent positions that are counter to your own, here and elsewhere.I think your charges of "misrepresentation" are all bosh — Leontiskos
I'll agree with that. It is incomplete. As Tones pointed out RAA is an inference rule, not a sequent within classical propositional logic. The inference allows one to infer ~ρ given a proof of (μ ^ ~μ) with ρ as assumption, a form displayed in the truth table.Has everyone agreed by this point that ↪Banno's truth table does not fully capture what a reductio is? — Leontiskos
This is rubbish. Given a proof of B and ~B from A as assumption, we may derive ~A as conclusion. This is the form of reductio inferences and is quite valid.The easiest way to see this is to note that a reductio ad absurdum is not formally valid — Leontiskos
All of your premises are wrong except for number 1. — Lionino
It depends upon the values given to the variables. — creativesoul
Why not? I'm not seeing the issue here...we end up with ¬(a→(b∧¬b)), and this can't be read as "It is not the case that a implies a contradiction" — Lionino
So, since ¬◇(a→(b∧¬b)) would be read by many as "It is not possible that A implies a contradiction", is that the same thing as "It is necessary that not-A implies a contradiction"? — Lionino
Again, no.(It would seem that you are wrong in claiming that classical logic treats contradictions as false. — Leontiskos
A reductio is not truth-functional. — Leontiskos
Given a proof of B and ~B from A as assumption, we may derive ~A as conclusion — Lemmon
Maybe not as much as you think.I have already responded to these charges. — Leontiskos
I'm not seeing a salient point here. Pretty demonstrably, you have made a series of claims that have been shown to be in error.At this point you either have an argument for "∴¬A" or you don't. Do you have one? If not, why are you still saying that ¬A is implied? — Leontiskos
...but they have no way of knowing when their logic machine is working and when it is not. — Leontiskos
and soEach of these systems sets out different ways of dealing with truth values. How the truth value of a contradiction is treated depends on which of these systems is in play. — Banno
Asking, as you do, how to treat the truth value of a contradiction apart from the system that sets out how a truth value is to be dealt with makes little sense. — Banno
A reductio is as much a proof in classical propositional logic as is modus tollens. — Banno
A reductio is as much a proof in classical propositional logic as is modus tollens.a reductio is an indirect proof which is not valid in the same way that direct proofs are. — Leontiskos
Simply because I matched your example, which hasIn your conclusion you reject (2) instead of (1). Why do you do that? — Leontiskos
and not ~A⊢A→(B∧¬B).A→(B∧¬B)
∴ ¬A — Leontiskos
Ah, so it's an esoteric mystery. :wink:This answer proves that you do not understand the questions that are being asked. If one wants to understand what is being discussed here they will be required to set aside their ready-made answers. — Leontiskos
The consequent is (B∧¬B)Nowhere in that post do you affirm (B∧¬B).
— Banno
I never said I did. Read again what you responded to. " — Leontiskos
Your loss.I've been ignoring Tones... — Leontiskos
Then the thread is in erorr. (p ^ ~p) is false in classical propositional logic.I think the thread shows that this is not true. — Leontiskos
Not at all. A contradiction in first order predicate logic is an expression of the form (φ ^ ~φ). It is not an expression of the form ~φ. The lack of specificity here is your attempt to make use of a notion of contradiction that is not found in classical propositional logic.The problem here is that your answer lacks specificity — Leontiskos
How is it that something and its negation can both be false? — Leontiskos
Nowhere in that post do you affirm (B∧¬B).Whether or not we affirm the negation of the consequent... — Leontiskos
I'm puzzling over what this might be.the notion of contradiction in its entirety — Leontiskos
As has been explained at length, in classical propositional logic contradictions are false.pray tell how a contradiction is to be dealt with in classical propositional logic? — Leontiskos
Another example of your practice of misattributing stuff to your interlocutors - as you did with . What I said is that the disagreement here is as to which system is in play. Hence there is no absolute answer as to which view is "right"....you seem to be implying that, according to the logic, one person is right and one person is wrong when they disagree about whether a given instance of (b∧¬b) should be treated as a proposition/variable or as a simple truth value. — Leontiskos
This seems to be the source of your difficulties.A contradiction is a contradiction. It is neither true nor false. It is the basis for both truth and falsity. — Leontiskos
Yep. Worth noting that parsing this correctly shows that the original was incomplete - implied nothing."The car is green" and "The car is red" is not a contradiction. But if we add the premise: "If the car is red then the car is not green," then the three statements together are inconsistent. That's for classical logic and for symbolic rendering for classical logic too. — TonesInDeepFreeze
Taking "implies" as material implication, they are not contradictory but show that A implies a contradiction.Do (A implies B) and (A implies notB) contradict each other? — flannel jesus
I had the same thought when I read that. It's wellformed. It is also invalid: A∧¬AI'd like to see what formation rules you come up with. — TonesInDeepFreeze
...but are refusing to make sense of them... — Michael
So the proper comparison would be:
1. You were given an order
2. Do this
I have no problem with (1). Is this all "you ought do this" means? — Michael
1. You ought do this
2. Do this
The first appears to be a truth-apt proposition, whereas the second isn’t. But beyond this appearance I cannot make sense of a meaningful difference between them. The use of the term “ought” seems to do nothing more than make a command seem like a truth-apt proposition. — Michael
The first appears to be a truth-apt proposition, whereas the second isn’t. Beyond this appearance is there a meaningful difference between them? Will you say that the use of the term "asked" seems to do nothing more then make a question seem like a truth-apt proposition?1. You were asked to give an answer to what we get when we add six and five.
2. What is six and five?
1. She greeted you
2. "Hello"
There follows a passionate defence of the justice. Your girlfriend did you an injustice when she reneged on the promise she made. It was an injustice because she undertook an obligation to you, which she did not fulfil. One ought fulfil one's obligations, since that is what an obligation is.I will end by describing the advantages of using the word "ought" in a non-emphatic fashion, and not in a special "moral" sense; of discarding the term "wrong" in a "moral" sense, and using such notions as 'unjust'. — MMP, p.13
I will maintain that questions, greetings and obligations are examples of things that exist "beyond the act", along with property, currency, marriage, incorporation, institutionalisation, legality... and a few other things.There is nothing that exists beyond the act. — AmadeusD