At conception and birth we are blank slates
— Cartesian trigger-puppets
We are not. Anyone who has children knows this. It has been a long time since I read the literature, but the last I looked the idea of a tabula rasa had been rejected by developmental psychologists. — Fooloso4
All human knowledge begins with opinion.
— Fooloso4
Im referring to humans on the individual level. At conception and birth we are blank slates except for some genetic precursors that predispose us to behave instinctively (innate knowledge). — Cartesian trigger-puppets
All human knowledge begins with opinion. — Fooloso4
of a proposition is to admit uncertainty and thus take an agnostic position.. . .know of the improbability. . . — TheMadFool
(ax. 1) If theism is cognitive, then its claims (e.g. "the Abrahamic Deity exists") are demonstrably true or not true.
(ax. 2) If theism is noncognitive, then its claims (e.g. "the Abrahamic Deity exists") are mere poetry (i.e. figures of speech). [from ax. 1] — (excerpts) QED & Other Stigmata
Agnosticism means uncertainty as you say, however, since atheism requires a lack of belief, these two are compatible. — Judaka
I'm not even sure if you're providing a stance on agnosticism vs gnosticism — Judaka
Which implies that upon learning more, we could switch from the default position to a position of gnosticism, as we learned more. — Judaka
Could you clarify, if a human values intellectual honesty, what exactly are you asking them to do? — Judaka
I wasn't just arguing that I don't know whether or not particular moral claims are true; I was arguing that I don't know what it means for moral claims to be true. I think that the sentences "thou shalt not kill" and "don't kill" mean the same thing, and I don't know what it means for "don't kill" to be true. — Michael
I understand what physical facts are, I understand what mathematical facts are, I understand what logical facts are, but I don't understand what moral facts are supposed to be. — Michael
This just goes to show that taboos are still essential to thinking about morality. — baker
Reread my preamble for context. Ethics, as I understand it, is fallibilistic (i.e. pragmatic(ist)) and performative, not justificationist and propositional. — 180 Proof
I don't know what it means for "I ought not kill" to be true or false, so I can't answer that question. — Michael
Moral facts are, in effect, truth-makers / warrants for moral claims. — 180 Proof
I'm asking for an example of an objective moral fact. This would be a moral statement (e.g., genocide is wrong) that is true independent of us.
— Cartesian trigger-puppets
You are conflating statements with facts. Why? — 180 Proof
I don't think "moral statements" – normativity – when I say 'moral claim'. What am I missing by deviating from the specious ontic premises of (e.g.) "error theory"? — 180 Proof
Do you have such an example?
A barefoot little girl cries alone at night on an empty street. Her distress, loneliness & defenselessness constitute a moral claim for help. That those abject conditions can increase and/or be prolonged by neglecting to help her is a moral fact recognized by SEEING (I. Murdoch, E. Levinas, P. Foot) oneself, or anyone else one cares about, in that little girl's "shoes". — 180 Proof
I think the passage in the middle about the meaning of nouns and names is rather different in spirit from the quoted passages. — Wayfarer
I can't see anything that supports that in the SEP article. Are there real things in Plato's philosophy? I would have thought that 'things' were only real insofar as they were instantiations of ideas. (See entry on Aquinas below). — Wayfarer
SOCRATES: But if neither is right, if it isn’t the case that everything always has every attribute simultaneously or that each thing has a being or essence privately for each person, then it is clear that things have some fixed being or essence of their own. They are not in relation to us and are not made to fluctuate by how they appear to us. They are by themselves, in relation to their own being or essence, which is theirs by nature.
HERMOGENES: I agree, Socrates.
SOCRATES: And if things are of such a nature, doesn’t the same hold of actions performed in relation to them? Or aren’t actions included in some one class of the things that are?
HERMOGENES: Of course they are.
SOCRATES: So an action’s performance accords with the action’s own nature, and not with what we believe. Suppose, for example, that we undertake to cut something. If we make the cut in whatever way we choose and with whatever tool we choose, we will not succeed in cutting. But if in each case we choose to cut in accord with the nature of cutting and being cut and with the natural tool for cutting, we’ll succeed and cut correctly. If we try to cut contrary to nature, however, we’ll be in error and accomplish nothing.
HERMOGENES: That’s my view, at least.
SOCRATES: So, again, if we undertake to burn something, our burning mustn’t accord with every belief but with the correct one—that is to say, with the one that tells us how that thing burns and is burned naturally,
and what the natural tool for burning it is?
HERMOGENES: That’s right.
SOCRATES: And the same holds of all other actions?
HERMOGENES: Certainly.
SOCRATES: Now isn’t speaking or saying one sort of action?
HERMOGENES: Yes.
SOCRATES: Then will someone speak correctly if he speaks in whatever way he believes he should speak? Or isn’t it rather the case that he will accomplish something and succeed in speaking if he says things in the natural way to say them, in the natural way for them to be said, and with the natural tool for saying them? But if he speaks in any other way he will be in error and accomplish nothing?
HERMOGENES: I believe so.
SOCRATES: Tell me this. Is there something you call speaking the truth and something you call speaking a falsehood?
HERMOGENES: Indeed, there is.
SOCRATES: Then some statements are true, while others are false?
HERMOGENES: Certainly.
SOCRATES: And those that say of the things that are that they are, are true, while those that say of the things that are that they are not, are false?
HERMOGENES: Yes — Plato
Why Ctesippus, said Euthydemus, do you think it possible to tell lies?
Good heavens yes, he said, I should be raving if I didn’t.
When one speaks the thing one is talking about, or when one does not speak it?
When one speaks it, he said.
So that if he speaks this thing, he speaks no other one of things that are except the very one he speaks?
Of course, said Ctesippus.
And the thing he speaks is one of those that are, distinct from the rest?
Certainly.
Then the person speaking that thing speaks what is, he said.
Yes.
But surely the person who speaks what is and things that are speaks the truth – so that Dionysodorus, if he speaks things that are, speaks the truth and tells no
lies about you.
Yes, said Ctesippus, but a person who speaks these things, Euthydemus, does not speak things that are.
And Euthydemus said, But the things that are not surely [are not], no?
No, they [are not].
Then there is nowhere that the things that are not are?
Nowhere.
Then there is no possibility that any person whatsoever could do anything to the things that are not so as to make them be when they are nowhere?
It seems unlikely to me, Ctesippus said.
Well then, when the orators speak to the people, do they do nothing?
No, they do something, he said.
Then if they do something, they also make something?
Yes.
Speaking, then, is doing and making?
He agreed.
Then nobody speaks things that are not, since he would then be making something, and you have admitted that no one is capable of making something that is not. So according to your own statement, nobody tells lies. — Plato
“Theaetetus sits” (a) The true statement says things that are, as they are about you [i.e. about Theaetetus] (263 B4 f). “Theaetetus flies”
(b) The false statement says things different from the things that are (263 B7).
(c) Accordingly it says things that are not as things that are (263 B9).
(d) But things that are different from things that are about you (263 Bn).
(e) For we said that about everything there are many things that are and also many that are-not (263 B11 f). — Seligman P.
Plato, Aristotle, Descartes, Spinoza, Locke, Leibniz, Berkeley, Kant, William James, Moore, Hume, Mill, etc, all subscribed to a correspondence account of truth
— Cartesian trigger-puppets
I very much doubt that. — Wayfarer
The correspondence theory is often traced back to Aristotle’s well-known definition of truth (Metaphysics 1011b25): “To say of what is that it is not, or of what is not that it is, is false, while to say of what is that it is, and of what is not that it is not, is true”—but virtually identical formulations can be found in Plato (Cratylus 385b2, Sophist 263b).
Authors of the modern period generally convey the impression that the correspondence theory of truth is far too obvious to merit much, or any, discussion. Brief statements of some version or other can be found in almost all major writers; see e.g.: Descartes 1639, ATII 597; Spinoza, Ethics, axiom vi; Locke, Essay, 4.5.1; Leibniz, New Essays, 4.5.2; Hume, Treatise, 3.1.1; and Kant 1787, B82. Berkeley, who does not seem to offer any account of truth, is a potentially significant exception.
. . .moderns generally subscribe to a representational theory of the mind (the theory of ideas), they would seem to be ultimately committed to spelling out relations like correspondence or conformity in terms of a psycho-semantic representation relation holding between ideas, or sentential sequences of ideas (Locke’s “mental propositions”), and appropriate portions of reality, thereby effecting a merger between metaphysical and semantic versions of the correspondence theory.
The now classical formulation of a fact-based correspondence theory was foreshadowed by Hume (Treatise, 3.1.1) and Mill (Logic, 1.5.1). It appears in its canonical form early in the 20th century in Moore (1910-11, chap. 15) and Russell: “Thus a belief is true when there is a corresponding fact, and is false when there is no corresponding fact” (1912, p. 129; cf. also his 1905, 1906, 1910, and 1913).
Even philosophers whose overall views may well lead one to expect otherwise tend to agree. Kant: “The nominal definition of truth, that it is the agreement of [a cognition] with its object, is assumed as granted” (1787, B82). William James: “Truth, as any dictionary will tell you, is a property of certain of our ideas. It means their ‘agreement’, as falsity means their disagreement, with ‘reality’” (1907, p. 96). — Marian David
Let's contrast taste with morality. That you do not eat onions is perhaps a preference you would not insist applies to everyone. That folk should not lie is presumably a preference that you and I would insist applies to everyone. That is, one of the characteristics of moral statements is that they are not only about how the speaker should act, but how everyone, in comparable circumstances, should act.
Does that mesh with your view? — Banno
Truth seems to necessitate existence-conditions upon statements whereby the truth of a statement is contingent upon existing; whereas facts can obtain their truth-making relations with a statement whether or not the facts exist. Facts can be a thing that exists in the world, such as an object; or, on the other hand, facts can exist in a subset of possible worlds, such as an abstract entity.
— Cartesian trigger-puppets
Interesting. I tend to define the two terms more or less the opposite way. — Echarmion
2 What is the case — a fact — is the existence of states of affairs.
2.01 A state of affairs (a state of things) is a combination of objects
(things).
2.0122 Things are independent in so far as they can occur in all possible situations, but this form of independence is a form of connexion with
states of affairs, a form of dependence.
2.02 Objects are simple.
2.021 Objects make up the substance of the world. That is why they cannot be composite.
2.0211 If the world had no substance, then whether a proposition had sense would depend on whether another proposition was true.
2.0212 In that case we could not sketch any picture of the world (true or false).
2.024 Substance is what subsists independently of what is the case.
2.0271 Objects are what is unalterable and subsistent; their configuration is what is changing and unstable.
2.0272 The configuration of objects produces states of affairs.
2.03 In a state of affairs objects fit into one another like the links of a chain.
3.203 A name means an object. The object is its meaning. — Wittgenstein
I want you to realize that when I speak of a fact I do not mean a particular existing thing, such as Socrates or the rain or the sun. Socrates himself does not render any statement true or false. What I call a fact is the sort of thing that is expressed by a whole sentence, not by a single name like ‘Socrates.’ . . .We express a fact, for example, when we say that a certain thing has a certain property, or that it has a certain relation to another thing; but the thing which has the property or the relation is not what I call a ‘fact. — Bertrand Russell
If there are moral facts, how can we know them?
— Cartesian trigger-puppets
Psychologically and socially, there is potentially a lot at stake in terms of morality. I think that sometimes (often?) it is because of these high stakes that moral statements become artificially elevated to the level of facts. — baker
Language affords one many options for expression, including sentences like "I find onions awful", "I don't like onions" and "I think onions taste awful".
So why is it that some people say “Onions taste awful,” and others say "I think onions taste awful"?
Is this the result of a conscious choice?
Do people less or more mindlessly repeat the types of sentences they've learned in primary education? — baker
So, perhaps it is similar to the case when we state, “Onions taste awful,” that the syntax is configured in such a way to be making a general statement when in actuality, we are making a particular subjective statement.
— Cartesian trigger-puppets
Language affords one many options for expression, including sentences like "I find onions awful", "I don't like onions" and "I think onions taste awful".
So why is it that some people say “Onions taste awful,” and others say "I think onions taste awful"?
Is this the result of a conscious choice?
Do people less or more mindlessly repeat the types of sentences they've learned in primary education? — baker
Or perhaps it is a realistic truth and our ideas and beliefs are simply streams of synaptic electrochemical nerve signals lighting up the the apparatus of the brain. We just get to interpret them phenomenologically instead of sociologically.
But then how do we explain the differences between people? E.g. some like onions and some don't: does this mean that there is something physiologically or otherwise wrong with one of the groups? — baker
I classify myself as a moral subjectivist.
— Cartesian trigger-puppets
Do you? Why? I don't understand the need to categorise and name - doing philosophy as if it were entomology. It's as if one reached a conclusion and only then looked for the arguments... — Banno
I'll read the substantive part of your post and try to formulate a response. But are you looking for such a critique? — Banno
SO we'd get something like my satiny lying is wrong should be analysed as
'"Lying is wrong" as uttered by Banno at this time is true iff boo to lying!'?
IS that the sort of thing you are suggesting? — Banno
I wonder whether lying is wrong. — Banno
(Lifted from the article, excluding the question...) — Banno
So "Lying is not wrong" just means "Boo to lying!", "Fred believes that lying is wrong" just means "Fred believes 'Boo! to lying'", and so on. — Banno
I think philosophy conventionally subscribes to a correspondence theory of truth and thus takes a realist stance when speaking of facts.
— Cartesian trigger-puppets
Eh, maybe, I'm not versed in the sociology of philosophy. But given that this is one of the main topics of contention in philosophy, I wouldn't use it in an assumption, especially not in a discussion of "moral facts", where, by default, correspondence theory must fail / yield an unambigious "no". — Echarmion
The PhilPapers Survey (conducted in 2009; cf. Bourget and Chalmers 2014), more specifically, the part of the survey targeting all regular faculty members in 99 leading departments of philosophy, reports the following responses to the question: “Truth: correspondence, deflationary, or epistemic?” Accept or lean toward: correspondence 50.8%; deflationary 24.8%; other 17.5%; epistemic 6.9%. The data suggest that correspondence-type theories may enjoy a weak majority among professional philosophers and that the opposition is divided. This fits with the observation that typically, discussions of the nature of truth take some version of the correspondence theory as the default view, the view to be criticized or to be defended against criticism. — Marian David
Would this definition be any different from your definition of "truth" or a "true statement"? — Echarmion
Well, yes. But then empirical knowledge also begins as a descriptive theory and from there we use experience to determine whether or not the theory is true. I think the question of whether or not there are moral facts, whether there is "objective" morality benefits from a comparison with the field where we are most used to speaking about objectivity and facts: Empirical reality. How do we determine the truth of a claim about the empirical world? We apply a specific method, and if that method does not falsify our claim, it has passed said test. If it passes such tests regularly, we are justified in calling it a fact. — Echarmion
I'm saying that evolution has imbued us with a moral sense, that enables us to derive ought from is. — counterpunch
Religion, law, politics, economics and so on, are objective with respect to individuals, and so are in effect, objective moral facts. Not in the moral realist sense, but in the sense that we agree upon values, via social structures like democratic politics, and invest them with authority. — counterpunch
I'm not sure that in the case of a moral statements, there is such a thing... — Banno
What we can drop is an implicit correspondence theory of truth, such that there is a distinct thing that makes the statement true. — Banno
What are facts? There are many theories on the subject, but put in deliberately simple language I'd say the defining characteristic of a "fact" is this:
That it reasserts itself even if you are unaware or even actively opposed to it. — Echarmion
A fact is just a true truth-bearer.
A fact is just an obtaining state of affairs.
A fact is just a sui generis type of entity in which objects exemplify properties or stand in relations. — Kevin Mulligan
This changes only if we view morality as a practical question: not an abstract theory of good and bad, but as a set of practical rules under which an end result - a moral world - is achieved. — Echarmion
In light of modern knowledge, morality is clearly a consequence of evolution. — counterpunch
Religion, law, philosophy, economics, democratic politics etc - are means by which we agree on moral values, in terms of which objective facts "ought" to be understood. These then become, objective moral facts — counterpunch
If humans are more valuable, why? How do you justify this assertion? Any justification seems to have unacceptable ethical consequences. For instance, is it due to their (relative lack of) intelligence? Then, human value must also be gradated on the basis of intelligence, and from there we arrive at eugenics. — hypericin
A philosophy and way of living which seeks to exclude—as far as is possible and practicable—all forms of exploitation of, and cruelty to, animals for food, clothing or any other purpose; and by extension, promotes the development and use of animal-free alternatives for the benefit of animals, humans and the environment. In dietary terms it denotes the practice of dispensing with all products derived wholly or partly from animals.
Do you see the problem of proving a negative vis-à-vis god? To prove that god doesn't exist, one would have to have explored the entire universe - currently impossible - and even beyond - impossible. — TheMadFool
The problem is whether or not the grammatical subject of the statement accurately represents the philosophical subject that is indexed to grammatical predicate.
— Cartesian trigger-puppets
Isn't the same true for "the grass is green"? The moment you lift a predicative finger you are already "misrepresenting" the actuality for predication is not "out there" in the grass nor in the moral agent. But once you think like this, you "relativize" all predication to a language event, and the philosophical subject is always already (to borrow a term) a grammatical subject.
This is why I claim the only way to deal with metaethics is phenomenologically. Then the grammatical or, eidetic subject (putting aside transcendental egos and the like), is deemed part of the existential actuality of the philosophical subject. — Constance
If you are going to relativize to individual historical agencies then the hedonism — Constance
But is this not merely dismissive of the evaluative dimension? As if it presented no qualitatively distinct feature? — Constance
I don't think its ultimately solipsistic. — Pop
Solipsism suggests a singularity, whereas the universe is fundamentally relational. — Pop
Self-organization tends toward a singularity but never manages to achieve it - always remaining an evolving process. — Pop
I can not say I like it, but that's where the logic seems to lead. — Pop
Most, if not all the properties associated with an object (as we experience it) are perceptually constructed and cannot belong to an object in itself independent of perception.
— Cartesian trigger-puppets
If we take this to its logical conclusion, it means there is no consciousness independent world. — Pop
...It doesn’t sound like Cartesian trigger-puppets would accept that empirical facts are dependent on and a product of subjective organization.
— Joshs
All we can do is plant a seed or two and wait to see if they sprout - unfortunately it cant happen overnight. — Pop
Is there a contradiction entailed somewhere by my affirming of those propositions?
— Cartesian trigger-puppets
Yes, I think there is. — Joshs
Your model maintains a fact-value distinction that can’t justify itself — Joshs
All facts get their sense via larger valuative schemes within which they are ensconced. — Joshs
It is incoherent to talk about facts or sense data that is what it is independent of the perceiver. — Joshs
Subjectivity doesn’t just organize and categorize data from an presumed independent world. The subject co-creates the object. — Joshs