• Is pregnancy is a disease?
    - Yes, and if X is a disease then its treatment must, ceteris paribus, be legal, insurance-provided, and an interest of medical research. Further, doctors have a responsibility to treat diseases, and therefore much turns on whether X is classified as a disease. The motivation for making pregnancy a disease is primarily practical, not speculative.
  • Is pregnancy is a disease?
    Are there really non-goofy people who propose calling pregnancy a disease?T Clark

    Those who want to construe things like abortion and contraception as forms of traditional healthcare are eventually forced to claim that pregnancy is a disease.
  • Wittgenstein and How it Elicits Asshole Tendencies.
    - "To examine why philosophy wants X," is to intentionally step outside of philosophy and into psychology (or else anthropology). It is to say, "I am no longer doing the thing that philosophy does."
  • Aristotle's Metaphysics
    Before going into the details of what Aristotle said or did not say, I would like to think about Rorty as the poster child for what Gerson militates against. Rorty is baldly "historicist" in his description of the 'end of philosophy'. I agree with Gerson that Rorty is too general and reductive in how the practice is conceived.Paine

    Yes, good point.

    But is Rorty the best exemplar of what Gerson opposes? I have been questioning the unity imparted by Gerson upon classical texts in previous discussions. The assumed unity of what is being opposed by Gerson needs some consideration.Paine

    It seems to me that Gerson is not assuming a unity in what he opposes. I have understood your critique to be different, namely the claim that he mistakenly assumes the unity of what he proposes (e.g. Aristotle's inclusion). UR is a (overly?) complex thesis, but given that it consists of five "anti's" I don't think it envisions a unified opposition.

    Taken too broadly, this battle of the books will make no distinction between the differences between different models. To pluck out one among many, will the argument about what is innate versus what is developed through events in life hinge only upon the categories by which they are described? Or will the process lead to discoveries yet unknown by studying them?.

    That prompts the question of how Aristotle was searching for something new or not. And that is different from asking how a set of propositions, defended (and opposed) centuries later, relates to contemporary activities.
    Paine

    I may not be fully grasping your point here, but it would seem that for Gerson that difference between Plato and Aristotle (innate versus developed) is an accidental difference, especially when compared to what someone like Rorty is doing. Presumably for Gerson the analogous difference between Descartes and Locke is also not a difference that would place either one of them outside Platonism/philosophy. Aristotle and Locke (and Descartes) were searching for something new, but within certain boundaries.
  • Wittgenstein and How it Elicits Asshole Tendencies.
    Is it?Srap Tasmaner

    Yep.

    Is that also predominantly psychological? No philosophy?Srap Tasmaner

    That's a claim about human nature. This is not only different but, arguably, diametrically opposed to a predominantly psychological claim.
  • Wittgenstein and How it Elicits Asshole Tendencies.
    But Wittgenstein himself only uses Augustine to put forth a very simplistic image of language (and I don't think he is being unfair to Augustine here, he is just not using very much of him). So, his ideas then aren't connected to past thought in a way they might have been.Count Timothy von Icarus

    "Had there been more [engagement with the tradition] he wouldn't have spent as much time in perplexity and reinventing wheels" (Gregory Sadler).

    The way Wittgenstein leads with Augustine in PI rubs me the wrong way. It feels like he is setting up a caricature, both with respect to Augustine's thought and with respect to the tradition which went on to develop Augustine's thought. It looks like Wittgenstein read a few sentences of Augustine's most popular work (The Confessions) and then used this (caricature) as a point of departure or foil for his own approach. There is no attempt to wrestle with or understand either Augustine or that broader tradition, and for this reason the start of the PI seems to be a lesson in how to not do philosophy. This is also a good example of the self-referential posture that is so common with him.

    ---

    - Fair points. :up:
  • Vervaeke-Henriques 'Transcendent Naturalism'
    And I think that's a very small-minded way of looking at it. Vervaeke’s opus is nearer my interests than most of what is written about here, and he's a legitimate academic, he's not fringe or crank. He dialogues with a lot of interesting people and they cover a lot of topics in depth. The reason he's developed a following is because he's saying something that needs to be said, and that a lot of people needed to hear, shame folks here don't appreciate that, but nothing I can say is likely to change it.Wayfarer

    I think Vervaeke's work is worthwhile and important, and represents a much-needed juncture between praxis and theoria. As with Peterson, I often feel that he is forging a new path through the jungle when a well-worn trail is only a few feet to his right, but perhaps that's as it should be. I admire his fidelity to Plato, both in content and in form. He definitely has a therapeutic angle on the traditions he explores, but this too is not in itself a bad thing. I think he is laudably good at moving philosophy out of its superficial ruts, and more than anything I enjoy his receptive demeanor. He is clearly a contemplative with a deep spiritual life, and not someone who merely thinks or talks. For me this is the crucial difference in a Plato, Aristotle, or Aquinas (and many others too, of course). I'd say it is no coincidence that Hume did not access the higher parts of the divided line.

    I also find it pretty interesting the way that Vervaeke comes from a Christian upbringing that was somewhere in the vicinity of fundamentalism, and that because of this he is a bit averse and suspicious of the Christian and later Western traditions. It is very common to see someone shift towards Eastern religions--usually Buddhism--and eventually begin to reassess a broader and deeper Western heritage. That's also what happened with me.

    - Yes, ditto - haha.
  • Aristotle's Metaphysics
    - Okay, well I would be interested in the expansion. I think Aristotle had often been read against Plato, and I think Gerson is in part trying to correct this. It seems that although Aristotle does disagree with Plato at various points, they really do both form a single school vis-a-vis Gerson's "Ur-Platonism." Plato's enemies are always also Aristotle's enemies. There is an interesting two-minute clip from Myles Burnyeat where he touches on this question of anti-materialism, and the way that Plato and Aristotle differ in this matter while being in the same general camp (link).

    Perhaps for Gerson it came down to the question of either including or excluding Aristotle from Ur-Platonism, and the rest follows from being unable to exclude him.
  • Wittgenstein and How it Elicits Asshole Tendencies.
    His writings are not monologues. There is often if not always an interlocutor, even when the interlocutor is silent.Fooloso4

    I think my point holds. A preacher also has an interlocutor, for instance.

    Having been deeply influenced by Plato, my first impression of Wittgenstein was similar to yours. It took me years of struggling to interpret him to change my mind. As with Plato it is a matter of participation, of engagement with the texts, of questioning and challenging, of sorting things one way or another.Fooloso4

    Well, I admit that I was being a bit hyperbolic in the face of Nickles' persistence, but I think Wittgenstein is deeply time-bound in a way that Plato is not. In my estimation no one will read Wittgenstein 50 years hence. Part of it is that Plato's method is better at pulling people in and appealing to a broad audience, but that is part of his magic.

    This already draws from a more shallow pool, or at least tethers one to a more shallow pool, and it leads to pedantic pointing out of how language can lead to confusion, which I am not sure was not pointing out what was obvious for the common reader.. It seems more transformative if you drank the analytic kool-aid beforehand, but then that also makes the readership more shallow, and less relevant.schopenhauer1

    Agreed.

    ...but by doing so he left open and guarded rather then forced closed the problems of life, beauty, and what is higher.Fooloso4

    I am by no means an expert on Wittgenstein, but given the attitude of his adherents this strikes me as doubtful.

    A man will be imprisoned in a room with a door that's unlocked and opens inwards; as long as it does not occur to him to pull rather than push.


    Good. Compare that to Plato's Cave. I think it falls short, though it does have its limited use.

    In general his thought strikes me as cramped and artificial, although I recognize that in relation to what he was surrounded by it was just the opposite. Perhaps he was a corrective more than a lasting figure. Of course I could be wrong.
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    After all, the absolute is not reality with appearances removed, but reality + all appearances.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Right: the absolute does not exclude the relative but the relative does exclude the absolute. I have been wanting to read more Schindler.

    Wouldn't discussions of God fall into this category?Count Timothy von Icarus

    I think this point is even better made one step removed. Theological disagreements are implicit in many mundane disagreements. For example, the disagreement over Original Sin (theological or philosophical anthropology) underlies very many moral and political disagreements.

    The crucial distinction is that signs are always "how we know," whereas more pernicious forms of pluralism often seems to rely on the claim that "signs are what we know." But if everything is signs, "appearance," then there can be no real reality/appearance distinction.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Agreed. I think this is important and I think the oversight of semiotics leads to a lot of problems.

    -

    Yup, but the conclusions which are drawn from this vary quite a bit. We are drawn to ask: "where do theories come from?" That they have cultural, linguistic, and historical determinants is obvious, but there is a weird tendency to move from this insight to the idea that this makes them in some way arbitrary, and thus disconnected from truth. "X is socially and historically determined, thus X cannot tell us about the way the world really is."Count Timothy von Icarus

    Right: the inferences are not sound. I think Hume feeds into these unsound inferences:

    I'd say that Hume's constant conjunction and the probability theories that tread similar ground are intellectually problematic insofar as they pre-pave a meta-rut for cognitive bias. For instance, we are now prone to mistake anthropological habits for natural probabilities.Leontiskos

    The reduction of sense data to constant conjunction brings with it a destruction of a posteriori inference, and with it a posteriori knowledge. This is the logical conclusion, and even those who do not embrace it are still sipping on it unconsciously. Once the idea of demonstrative (a posteriori) inference is abandoned, people can say whatever they like and it will appear just as "rational" as anything else. Thus the claims that things like languages or history exclude truth, despite being inferentially unsound, continue unabated. The real error here is what you have noted: the idea that an absolute cannot account for any form of relativity. It is the idea, for example, that truth cannot be mediated by language or history or what have you.

    ---

    And I think that other way is captured, in part, in your usual suggestion that everything we do and say involves a metaphysics, generally unacknowledged and unexamined, and thus properly called our "metaphysical assumptions."Srap Tasmaner

    Compare the way that Sider connects quantification to truth:

    To avoid triviality, a first step is to restrict our attention to meanings with a “shape” that matches the grammar of quantifiers. We may achieve this indirectly, as follows. Understand a “candidate meaning” henceforth as an assignment of meanings to each sentence of the quantificational language in question, where the assigned meanings are assumed to determine, at the least, truth conditions. “Candidate meanings” here are located in the first instance at the level of the sentence; subsentential expressions (like quantifiers) can be thought of as having meaning insofar as they contribute to the meanings of sentences that contain them. Thus quantifiers are assured to have meanings whose “shapes” suffice to generate truth conditions for sentences containing quantifiers. — Sider, Ontological Realism, 8-9

    And he's right. Infants acquire the idea of object permanence even before the idea of object identity. They're not born with it, so far as we can tell, but it develops predictably, and so that pattern of development is more or less "built in." And it comes before language, and evidently would have to come before anything like rational thought, so it's not like you could reason your way there anyway.Srap Tasmaner

    It seems to me that what very often happens with Humeans is that an assumption is made and everything follows from the assumption, but the assumption is contested and question-begging. For example, the neat and tidy understanding of reason as conscious discursive inference is not at all accepted by pre-moderns. If we accept that notion of reason then the infant is not using reason to know that an object has permanence, but why accept such a notion of reason? According to Aristotle repeated experience with, and memories of, an object(s) provides a condition whereby one is able to understand things about that object, such as its permanence. Knowledge is already had long before one gets to the point where they can write formal inferences on the chalkboard.

    We could assume with Hume that each time we experience the sun and the sunrise we have a purely separate experience, unconnected to previous experience and memory. If this is right then we could never know anything about the sun, whether this knowledge has to do with its rising and setting or its heat. But why make such a silly assumption? The fact that we do know things about the sun is enough to dispel such a strange assumption. Yet if we do make the assumption then reason becomes weakened such that irrational things will appear rational, just as anything follows from a contradiction. If we make those sorts of weak assumptions universally, then our whole philosophy will be brittle and unsteady, along with everything built upon it. At this point the only reason to retain the odd assumptions seems to be that we have built much upon them, and to abandon the assumptions would be to abandon the edifice set upon it. ...Like a poor foundation that cannot be remedied without demolishing the house that sits atop it. But I wonder if this is really the case.

    Our metaphysical assumptions, if there are such things, are probably no more accessible to us than they are to non-linguistic beings.Srap Tasmaner

    These sorts of assumptions, along with the sort of brain-physicalism moves, presuppose a strange skepticism which then makes rationality an epiphenomenon or artifact. Yet the performative self-contradiction again comes to bear, for the brain research you have read is purportedly rational. The scientists who do that research are using reason to access knowledge of the brain and thus behavior, and if rational inferences are nothing more than post-hoc rationalizations of something that occurs for an entirely separate reason, then there can be no reason to favor the scientist's rational inferences to the metaphysician's.

    I want to say that the reason this is mistakenly taken to be rigorous is because of the democratic turn that has occurred. In Plato's day the common opinion was largely understood by the philosophers to be suspect. In our day if enough people (and scientists) promote Scientism or related theories, then even the philosophers accept these theories to be true. The Humean and probabilistic premises support such an approach. Reason has become more of a force to be measured, like the wind, rather than an art to be practiced.

    That's pretty weird, but the main thing is that it suggests there's an entirely separate route to belief available: you saw the car accident happen, I only heard you talk about seeing it, and we both hold beliefs that it happened.Srap Tasmaner

    Er, this is just testimony or natural faith. It is the thing that the Enlightenment was determined to eradicate, and apparently it worked ("Sapere aude!").

    I suppose I'm suggesting that thinking a concept like "object permanence" is actually instantiated in the infant brain might be a sort of category mistake. The whole system will behave in a way that we recognize or categorize as embodying such a conception, but that doesn't mean it's "in there" somewhere.Srap Tasmaner

    Or maybe object permanence is simpler than you think. Maybe the infant can recognize an object, and he also believes that when the object disappears from sight it will reappear again. Maybe that's all we mean by object permanence.

    -

    I was very impressed by the idea (in Mercier and Sperber) that participants in a discussion systematically simplify and exaggerate their positions, in both the definiteness of their view and their confidence in it, and that this is strategic: you're responsible for bringing a view to the table, others bring others, and you argue to some kind of consensus that would enable group action. (Reasons are in part excuses you offer others to make going along with you palatable.) We're crap at judging our own views but pretty good at criticizing others.Srap Tasmaner
    And it's pretty obvious that something like this is right at the root of language use. We talk digital even if we mostly live analog.Srap Tasmaner

    With @Count Timothy von Icarus, I think there are non-sequiturs occurring in these sorts of things. All of this is true, as well as the other things, like neuroscientific research, but does any of it really imply the metaphysical claims at the root of Hume? I don't think so. I'm not really sure why we would think such a thing. "We systematically simplify and exaggerate positions in discussion," ...therefore? What we have here, I aver, are data points that many different philosophical positions can and have taken into account. I don't see how they favor Humean or probabilistic views. :chin:

    ...So yeah. Hume? I don't see the appeal. I was recently looking at Hume's treatise on the passions, and it reminded me that if one is accustomed to Aristotle or Aquinas' deeply syllogistic method, Hume reads like a popular magazine article. I just don't see a lot of strict reasoning occurring there.

    Edit: Worth quoting, I think:

    Phaedo: Likely indeed, he said, but arguments are not like men in this particular.

    Socrates: I was merely following your lead just now. The similarity lies rather in this: it is as when one who lacks skill in arguments puts his trust in an argument as being true, then shortly afterwards believes it to be false—as sometimes it is and sometimes it is not—and so with another argument and then another. You know how those in particular who spend their time c studying contradiction in the end believe themselves to have become very wise and that they alone have understood that there is no soundness or reliability in any object or in any argument, but that all that exists simply fluctuates up and down as if it were in the Euripus10 and does not remain in the same place for any time at all.

    What you say, I said, is certainly true.

    It would be pitiable, Phaedo, he said, when there is a true and reliable argument and one that can be understood, if a man who has dealt with such arguments as appear at one time true, at another time untrue, should not blame himself or his own lack of skill but, because of his distress, in the end gladly shift the blame away from himself to the arguments, and spend the rest of his life hating and reviling reasonable discussion and so be deprived of truth and knowledge of reality.

    Yes, by Zeus, I said, that would be pitiable indeed.

    This then is the first thing we should guard against, he said. We should not allow into our minds the conviction that argumentation has nothing sound about it; much rather we should believe that it is we who are not yet sound and that we must take courage and be eager to attain soundness, you and the others for the sake of your whole life still to come, and I for the sake of death itself.
    — Plato, Phaedo, 90b..., tr. Grube
  • Aristotle's Metaphysics
    - What are the arguments against the idea that Aristotle was an anti-naturalist or anti-materialist, on Gerson's definitions? (Cf. "Platonism versus Naturalism")
  • Wittgenstein and How it Elicits Asshole Tendencies.
    I do think we are circling the gist of the grievance, but you frame it as: “Wittgenstein is either saying something or else he is not.” First, wanting him to just “say something” misses the reason that about half of PI is questions; as I said, questions for you to work out, to change you.Antony Nickles

    Plato's dialogues don't just "say something," they provide questions for you to work out, to change you. Wittgenstein's monologues are comparatively banal and flat, a shallow study of the shadows on the wall of the cave, perhaps helpful to those who are mired very deep in the cave. They don't show evidence of philosophical insight, and I see no reason to conjure up fancy reasons to make up for this fact. Wittgenstein possesses no authority to try to change us, and submitting to his tutelage is harmful. The fact that our age thinks Wittgenstein is above average is a problem with our age. Wittgenstein is nothing like Socrates.
  • Locke's Enquiry, Innateness, and Teleology
    In his "An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding," Locke makes an argument against the "innate ideas" of the rationalists.

    [...]

    However, here he differs from Aristotle quite a bit.
    Count Timothy von Icarus

    You may have seen the paper that I was quoting from in the other thread, "The Nature and Origin of Ideas: The Controversy over Innate Ideas Reconsidered." It is about the contrasting way that Descartes and Locke approach innate ideas, how later thinkers like Kant and Wittgenstein are wrestling with the same problem, and how it differs from Aristotle.
  • Wittgenstein and How it Elicits Asshole Tendencies.
    What enactivists find valuable about Wittgenstein is his recognition that linguistic meaning and intentionality cannot be fully understood via models that begin from the idea thatmentation is a matter of rational representation of a world performed inside a brain.Joshs

    Sure, and I agree, but my concern is that Wittgenstein is falling off the other side of the mean, and that this has implications for the topic of the OP. Although I should note that, according to Simpson, Wittgenstein began rectifying these problems in his later work.
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    - If it could be sufficiently proved that such a sentence follows upon embracing Wittgenstein's philosophy, then the title of schopenhauer1's recent thread would take on a whole new meaning.
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    Sigh. Look at what you quoted:Srap Tasmaner

    If you follow my reply a bit closer, I built up to what you were talking about and implied that the lesser forms are related to inquiries about "secondary substances." The distinction that must be made is between the facticity of something whose mode of existence is not in dispute (e.g. extraterrestrials), and the mode of existence of something like a table. The former is sometimes found in ordinary reasoning, and one could recast disputes over the latter as predication disputes (even though this move will in some cases fall into what Sider calls "hostile translation").

    I do grant your point that ontological disputes of the latter kind are more common in philosophy than in everyday speech, but I am wondering if this has more to do with recent philosophy than historical philosophy, at least after the presocratics.

    (Sorry, I realize I am posting a bit too fast. I will try to rectify that.)
  • Wittgenstein and How it Elicits Asshole Tendencies.
    - Thanks, I will try to find time to return to this. Even if I don't, I will read and consider.
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    But there is quite definitely no great body of everyday discussion of whether certain kinds of things existSrap Tasmaner

    This is interesting. On many forms of realism predication is an attribution of existence, and if this is right then all discussions involve existence claims (Sider basically defines quantifiers in relation to sentences and truth). Or as says, "how people relate concepts and things."

    And there are also claims about primary substances, i.e. hypotheses. "It's cold in this building, therefore the furnace must be out" (i.e. there exists no fire in the furnace). "The crops are dry; there must be a lack of rain." "My car won't start; the (proximity) key must be somewhere else."

    Philosophers and scientists often take hypothesis to the next level, where they construct mental entities that may or may not exist in the world, and then go about arguing over them. Then there are the table arguments. But I do wonder what percentage of philosophers in the history of the world spent appreciable time arguing whether tables exist.
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    I just heard on the radio an interview with a UCLA anthropoligist who's spent time along the migration trails from Central America to the US. He said his new book was intended just to add some nuance to the public conversation about migration, because nothing in life is black and white, and smugglers aren't just good or bad.

    Which way do you want to go here? If this guy is good at his job, and it sounded to me like he is, then we might agree to say he is pursuing the truth, and is in a position to tell us truths we were unaware of. Fine.

    But does that mean the statement "Smugglers are bad" must be true or false?
    Srap Tasmaner

    If De León is right then "Smugglers are just bad" is false and "Smugglers aren't just good or bad" is true. That's what he's doing, he's arguing for a truth.

    Unless I'm mistaken, your post seems to be a roundabout way of arguing that truth doesn't exist or isn't knowable. I know philosophers have "seen it all," and arguments about performative contradiction now come across as passé. What I would say is that they might be age-old, but the are also, well, true.

    But does that mean the statement "Smugglers are bad" must be true or false? Why would it? And what do we say about Jason De León's book? That it's the truth? The whole truth and nothing but the truth? A version of the truth? A part of the truth? But a partial truth can be misleading, so the understanding of truth is not monotonic even if the acquisition of truth is. How do we judge his work? None of us saw what he saw; we can't go back in time and skulk behind a tree to see if his reporting is accurate. We could interview his informants, if we could find them, but even the people that were there might not have noticed something that he did, and anyway some of them are dead now.Srap Tasmaner

    I would say that the commitment to truth is behind us, not in front of us. We can churn up the water and get it as muddy as we like, but we have presupposed truth the whole while. And if there is a question that is too complex to answer, then it is to that extent not truth-apt. But other questions surely are.
  • Imagining a world without the concept of ownership
    Again, how immeasurably greater is the pleasure, when a man feels a thing to be his own; for surely the love of self is a feeling implanted by nature and not given in vain, although selfishness is rightly censured; this, however, is not the mere love of self, but the love of self in excess, like the miser's love of money; for all, or almost all, men love money and other such objects in a measure. And further, there is the greatest pleasure in doing a kindness or service to friends or guests or companions, which can only be rendered when a man has private property. These advantages are lost by excessive unification of the state. The exhibition of two excellences, besides, is visibly annihilated in such a state: first, temperance towards women (for it is an honourable action to abstain from another's wife for temperance sake); secondly, liberality in the matter of property. No one, when men have all things in common, will any longer set an example of liberality or do any liberal action; for liberality consists in the use which is made of property.

    Such legislation may have a specious appearance of benevolence; men readily listen to it, and are easily induced to believe that in some wonderful manner everybody will become everybody's friend-especially when someone is heard denouncing the evils now existing in states, suits about contracts, convictions for perjury, flatteries of rich men and the like, which are said to arise out of the possession of private property. These evils, however, are due not to the absence of communism but to the wickedness of human nature. Indeed, we see that there is much more quarrelling among those who have all things in common, though there are not many of them when compared with the vast numbers who have private property.
    — Aristotle, Politics, II.5, tr. Jowett
  • Wittgenstein and How it Elicits Asshole Tendencies.
    - Yes, good points. A different angle on the same issue. :up:
  • Wittgenstein and How it Elicits Asshole Tendencies.
    In my opinion he should not. An author does not maintain control over how his words are understood or used by others.Fooloso4

    I think the beliefs of someone who is an adherent of a philosopher will be indebted to that philosopher, and therefore the philosopher will be to some extent responsible for those beliefs. This seems straightforwardly true. I don't see how a philosopher can be said to bear no responsibility for the beliefs of their adherents.

    The same holds for methodology, for philosophers should understand that their methodology will be absorbed by those who read them. If, as some have argued, Wittgenstein is methodology-heavy, then the methodology of his adherents is all the more attributable to him.

    So "Should Wittgenstein be faulted for what Wittgenstenians say and do?" Sometimes yes, sometimes no.
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    But I can still play at philosophy, and it's an old habit.Srap Tasmaner

    Lol, okay.

    I could argue against "contextless truth" and "carving nature at the joints" but I wouldn't be arguing for an alternative philosophical position. And I'd spend a lot of time arguing against misunderstanding positions I don't even hold, just out of scrupulousness I guess. Trying to think well is about as much of a program as I have.Srap Tasmaner

    Well, you've already argued against contextless truth, so I don't know what to make of this. I am the one who took your bait, and now it seems that you were engaged in "catch and release." :grin:

    I would make the point with Plato that what you have said already commits you to contextless truth. If that is right, then it's not some abstruse academic argument, but rather an entailment of your own thought that hasn't been seen through to the end (unless you were stating something you do not believe for the sake of argument, to bolster QV). There is nothing less programmatic than the simple idea that truth exists and can be known. That's the presupposition for any thought and any program, good or bad. And this isn't off-topic or far away. It is the very topic of the OP. Is it the very thing Sider is arguing for. In a nutshell: if truth exists then quantifier variance and logical pluralism don't.
  • Wittgenstein and How it Elicits Asshole Tendencies.


    Thanks for your comments in the thread. I find them helpful.

    I think 's thesis is in the process of being refined, so that it does not fall into 's “heads I win, tails you lose.”

    What is the more precise problem at stake? I would say that it is a kind of double standard, where Wittgenstein can never be wrong but everyone else can. Everyone believes that their favorite philosophers are better than other people's favorite philosophers, but because this is not a shared premise it cannot be brought to bear in public dialogue. Wittgenstenians have a tendency to impose this premise on others, resulting in a double standard that is a form of unethical discourse.

    What you say here is one way of getting at this idea:

    One more thing I think is happening sometimes is people take everything Witt writes as if it was a statement, like a claim to knowledge or an argument for the purpose of having a conclusion admitted. But I hear them like conjecture, or even more, like characterizations of remarks, that only lead to asking: “why would we say that?” Or: “look at it in this way”. But the only way to treat a picture like a conclusion is to accept it whole hog, without justification and without means of refuting it, when the picture is just meant to say: “do you see what I see in this (by/for yourself)?”Antony Nickles

    Frank Ramsey's reply to Wittgenstein is on point, "What can't be said can't be said, and it can't be whistled either." Wittgenstein is either saying something or else he is not. It can't be had both ways. If he is saying something then he can be contradicted and he can be wrong; if he is not saying anything then he cannot. But obviously he is saying something, and along with Ramsey I'd say it is a farce to claim that he is not. (I have noticed that Wittgenstenians tend to miss the fact that conjectures and indirect locutions are also ways of saying something.)

    There is something fundamental about this double standard in Wittgenstenian philosophy. "All philosophy is just language gone on holiday (except for mine, of course)." Even the very notions of subjecthood, linguistic intention, and opposing viewpoints seem to get subtly eclipsed in Wittgenstein:

    The knower is as it were a mirror for the known (the microcosm). Whatever this relationship is, and however it is to be properly explained, it is not the kind of relationship which Wittgenstein's simple objects can enter into. The knowing subject is therefore not part of the world, or an object that can be met with in the world alongside the other objects in the world. The self is pure medium, pure mirror for the world; their limits coincide. The self is, in a sense, one with the world. It gives way to it. Solipsism collapses into realism.Peter Simpson, Schopenhauer and Wittgenstein on Self and Object

    Wittgenstein provides himself with no way to account for the knowing subject along with their intentions and locutions. Language becomes a fact, a given, which must be parsed according to "common use" and cannot be parsed vis-a-vis the intentions of individual subjects. What this means is that to disagree with Wittgenstein is a non-starter. Disagreement presupposes knowing subjects in the world, and Wittgenstein's theory provides no room for the existence of such a thing. To think that Wittgenstein is saying something or making a statement would be to fall into the trap of thinking that knowing subjects are part of the world. The effect is that Wittgenstein gets to say things without saying things. He gets to have his cake and eat it too. Perhaps this is part of the reason why the Wittgenstenian is so awkward when it comes to disagreement. They are imposing their own system and that system cannot even theoretically account for disagreement.

    (Note that the problem is already implicit in my question, "How can it be that an approach which claims to privilege the common use of language does not use language in a common way?" If, as you say, we are not to interpret Wittgenstein's language according to common use, then how are we to interpret it without recourse to the categories of intention and knowing subjects? If solipsism were true and there were only one mirror of the world, none of this would be a problem for Wittgenstein.)
  • What do you reckon of Philosophy Stack Exchange ?
    The idea is, you go there to ask questions and elicit answers, NOT to engage in the kind of free-wheeling debates that we have here (if the back and forth yields a debate, it is split off into a different, 'chat room', format, which I've never pursued).Wayfarer

    Right: there is a criterion of "verifiability." If the answers to a question cannot be straightforwardly verified, then SE deems the question "opinion-based" and inadmissible. Ergo: philosophy is basically not allowed. You can talk about philosophy, but you cannot do philosophy. For example, you can ask what Descartes thought of Plato's anthropology, because quotes of Descartes can be adduced in favor of an answer. But you cannot ask whether Plato or Descartes had the more robust anthropology, because this is "opinion-based." It's basically, "If someone can disagree with your answer, then it isn't a good answer." To the extent that an answer required thought or creativity or any substantial form of agency, it isn't a good answer. It drives me a little bonkers, but I suppose it has its uses.
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    Surely "true" here is short for "true in L, under I", but I find it odd they didn't just say that, since all the model-theoretic machinery seems ready to hand.

    So that's caveat number 1 to your point: truth is always truth in a language, under a particular interpretation. It doesn't even make sense -- heh, in this theoretical context -- to say otherwise, to say "just plain true, dammit!"
    Srap Tasmaner

    It seems to me that this is already duplex veritas; it is already a premise of quantifier variance. Hence it is part of the controversy, and someone like Sider (and me!) would already disagree with you here. Sider's (really Aristotle's) notion of "carving reality at the joints" is presupposing contextless truth, as does the idea of "ontological structure." Sider partitions out that argument and distinguishes the variety of QV that denies this notion of carving from the variety of QV that does not deny it—and his distinction is what sparked some of @Count Timothy von Icarus' musings in the first place—but this is surely one of the very things that is at stake, and is not a common presupposition.

    Edit: But I think the question here needs to be refined. It is the question about whether language can speak about something beyond itself:

    The first kind of ideology is, after all, not ideology but just another name for thinking. Edge describes it as the fact that we have no access to a world independent of our senses and judgments. Indeed. No one can think without thinking and, since we are sensing creatures, without sensing either. But Edge then immediately slides into a suggestio falsi by glossing what he said as that we always think, when we think, with an inherited language-picture of the world. He then gives a further gloss that the drive to get beyond such a picture to ‘the resplendent and glorious room of objectivity’ is ‘fruitless’ because we cannot get to a place ‘independent of human thought, talk, language and belief’. Of course not. But whoever thought one had to in order to get to objectivity, to truth, to the way things are? One gets to objectivity by thinking.Peter L. P. Simpson, A Response to Edge

    Pluralism doesn't have to mean everyone's always right. It just means understanding something about how you're right, and that there may be other ways to be right.Srap Tasmaner

    Along the same lines of what @Count Timothy von Icarus has already alluded to, to say that some are equally right (and others could be wrong) would seem to imply that there is a standard of rightness that measures both equally-right views simultaneously. So if I say that a claim made in context X and a claim made in context Y are both equally right, then I have already implicitly appealed to a super-context that is capable of measuring both contexts, X and Y.
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    - Cop out, as usual. :roll:
    It's high time you started taking responsibility for what you say.
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    As already noted, if logic had no ontological implications then there could be no historical progression in logic vis-a-vis ontology, there could be no better or worse logics vis-a-vis ontology, and Wittgenstein's logic could not have excluded dynamism from his ontology, <which it did>.Leontiskos

    Does any one else see this as a bad argument? Count Timothy von Icarus? @Srap Tasmaner?

    If logic does not have ontological implications, then there are no better or worse logics regarding ontology.

    But it remains that there may be better or worse uses of logic in ontological arguments.

    Or is there a more charitable way to read this than as a transcendental argument with a false conclusion?
    Banno

    I think this is a good example of the standard sort of strawman that you engage in. You took "vis-a-vis ontology" and replaced it with "regarding ontology," and then pretended that I was referring to ontological arguments like Anselm's. The context about Wittgenstein should have been enough to preclude such a strawman, for obviously I have not claimed that Wittgenstein gave a bad "ontological argument." But even if it wasn't, the context of this debate that has already taken place earlier in the thread is obviously about the topic you raised: ontological implications of different logics, not ontological conclusions arrived at from pure logic.

    This is bad-faith argumentation, and it's no secret you are engaged in it all the time.

    (I suppose it is worth pointing out here that those who struggle with intellectual vices could use a "principle of charity" as a medicine, whether that vice stems from old age, pride, or other such things. Again, this is a practical consideration, but on point.)
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    There's a touching passage in Tarski's little Introduction to Logic that I'll quote in full hereSrap Tasmaner

    Very interesting. Thanks for sharing. :up:

    I think Tarski is right that logic pulls more weight than it appears to at first glance, and it is for this reason that I think varieties of logical pluralism are especially problematic.
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    I would say it is generally taking arguments in the strongest, most compelling sense possible. However, if one starts to think that the most compelling sense of the arguments is to take them as...Count Timothy von Icarus

    See 's post.

    For my money, so-called "principles of charity" are always destructive of intellectual honesty, even in the one or two sentences where they appear in Aquinas. At best they fail the test of Occam's Razor, and are superfluous.

    Consider the popular "steelman" interpretation. Is it good to steelman someone's argument when you are dialoguing with them? No, actually. You should try to interpret them accurately, neither engaging in "strawman" or "steelman." One does not need to appeal to "charity" to preclude advantageous misrepresentation.

    Now, if one is not in a dialogue context but is instead reading an unfamiliar author, then I would say that one should give them the benefit of the doubt, ceteris paribus. This is a kind of charity, but I would say that it is more accurately a kind of maximization of the philosophical activity. If you are exploring ideas, then you should desire to explore the strongest ideas and arguments, for the sake of this activity.

    I would say that charity pertains to the practical realm, and it influences speculative reason only indirectly, through the practical reason. For the understanding of the speculative reason, it is a non-starter.
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    To be fair, is this obvious?Count Timothy von Icarus

    It is obviously false. As already noted, if logic had no ontological implications then there could be no historical progression in logic vis-a-vis ontology, there could be no better or worse logics vis-a-vis ontology, and Wittgenstein's logic could not have excluded dynamism from his ontology, <which it did>.
  • Wittgenstein and How it Elicits Asshole Tendencies.
    Wittgenstein, of course, should not be faulted for what Wittgensteinians say and do.Fooloso4

    Shouldn't he? The OP seems to presuppose that he can be faulted for this. Or at the very least, that it can be traced back to his writings.
  • Wittgenstein and How it Elicits Asshole Tendencies.
    - Good post.

    In the architectonic form, the thread is entirely derailed into the poster's fairly rigid system.fdrake

    A simpler game of Bingo is to just observe how much language an author uses in a technical sense, and how willing they are to drop the technical connotation. Aristotle almost always begins a discussion by looking at the common opinions and the common ways that words are used. Aquinas is famous for using very simple Latin with a minimum of technical terms (except those inherited from his context). It's fairly common to hear people mock Aristotle for the way he considers common opinion and common language use, but I believe it to be a sign of a good philosopher, one who is not pulling the wool over his eyes with the verbiage of a specialized system. I suppose we are just talking about ideology and ideologues.

    In encountering Wittgenstenians, I have noticed a paradox in that there is an attempt to focus on common usage (perhaps to a fault), but then the utterances of these people are not to be interpreted according to common usage, but rather in accord with the technical color of a Wittgenstenian interpretation. How can it be that an approach which claims to privilege the common use of language does not use language in a common way?
  • What do you reckon of Philosophy Stack Exchange ?
    It's more well suited to disciplines that have explicit agreed upon correct answers...flannel jesus

    Agreed. Stack Exchange is a computer science knowledge compendium that someone tried to repurpose for everything else. It's not a good fit for philosophy, even if there are certain cases or questions where that format is workable. I think it will instill bad methodologies and presuppositions in the students.
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    My thinking was, if you assume QV, then when people who embrace those sorts of systems have disagreements, in a way, QV seems to assume that they are either wrong in their metaphysics or else not saying what they are saying. So the original example I thought of was comparing something like the classical Christian tradition to Shankara. In ways, the conception of infinite being is similar, but Shankara denies the existence of finite being, it being entirely maya—illusion. If QV is maintained by a third party, it seems like they can't take either of these claims in the way they are intended, which doesn't seem charitable.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Yes, I agree with all of this. Earlier I said something similar:

    It is to ignore the possibility that one person might be right and the other might be wrong about what they are intending to claim. This is another instance of the sort of relativism that Nagel generally opposes in The Last Word, for the legitimacy of the two philosophers' first-order arguments are precisely what is being dismissed when one thinks it could only be a conceptual or terminological dispute. Conceptual-or-terminological is a second-order reduction.Leontiskos

    As above, I think what is at stake is peace, not charity. The way that "charity" gets misused in these ways is a pet peeve of mine. Of justice, faith, and charity, only one is blind, not all three. :razz:

    I had a similar discussion with Joshs re truth being true withing a given metaphysics versus being true universally. It seems to me that if you tell a lot of people, "yes, what you're saying is true...but only in your context," you're actually telling them that what they think is false, because they don't think the truth is context dependent in this way.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Right. It is to ignore the fact that the person was not intending to make a context-dependent truth claim. This relates to the edit I made to my last post to you regarding Sider's "hostile translations." Duplex veritas arose because there were multiple conflicting sources of truth (e.g. theology, philosophy, science, etc.). It arises in our culture for the same reason, except the conflicting sources are individuals, for individuals have now been made to be sources of truth in their own right. "To each their own truth."

    I guess my intuition, which might very well be wrong, was that if they do an equally good job then there would be an morphism between them, and so it's pluralism of a limited type—perhaps the way some models for computation end up equivalent.Count Timothy von Icarus

    This seems likely, and perhaps in this case the "principle of charity" makes more sense (because translation is legitimately possible). Still, if translation is possible then it could be determined—even by the parties themselves—that the two parties are saying the same thing without resorting to a "principle of charity."
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    Conceptual relativism on stilts. Which honestly I'm not absolutely against (unlike both Banno and @Leontiskos) but I'm unsympathetic with the whole approach and nothing I've read was at all persuasive.Srap Tasmaner

    I've changed my mind a bit, and now no longer deem this debate a waste of time. I also better see why @J is interested in this topic. I wish I had looked at Sider's paper earlier.

    "Quantifier variance" is the logical instantiation of the pluralism that the West struggles with culturally, religiously, morally, et al. The "principle of charity" is the newest version of the Enlightenment's doctrine of optimism, "Stop fighting wars over religion. The disputes probably aren't that important." The aversion to disagreement is a child of the aversion to wars, and "charity" is just a mask for "peace." All of this has simply been funneled down into the field of logic. Or so I say.

    So I agree that the ideas are dumb, but the motivations are intelligible and they are not going away anytime soon. If logic can overcome "relativism on stilts" then all the better, but I obviously prefer Sider's more robust approach to Finn and Bueno's (or Banno's) flatfooted approach. I wouldn't say that logic is the last line of defense, but if we can't even avoid relativism when it comes to logic then we're probably too far gone.
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    To simply assume that a whole swath of discussions in philosophy must only arise from philosophers' "confusion," rather than real problems is not charitable. At its worst it's question begging. For example, to say that Przywara must be switching languages or domains with the analogia seems to be saying he is wrong in an important way, or even moreso, just refusing to take his thought the way it is intended.Count Timothy von Icarus

    That's right, just as it is question-begging to assume that the different uses of "to be" are compartmentally distinct.

    This is what Sider refers to as a "hostile translation" on page 14. It is interpreting or translating someone's utterance in a way that they themselves reject.

    For example, when Eriugena discusses his five modes of being, he clearly is intending one domainCount Timothy von Icarus

    Sure, but this is not quantifier variance, or even quantifier equivocation. One could represent the five modes with predicates, or else with alternative quantifiers.

    The debates about univocity of being can apply between parties or within the thought of a single party, but quantifier variance occurs between two parties using two different notions of quantification. If the two parties have five different sub-quantifiers, and they agree on all of them, then quantifier variance is not occurring. ...All of this is also reminiscent of the duplex veritas debates of the Middle Ages.

    This definition, at least taken in isolation, seems to avoid the issues above to some degree. "...either because there is no such notion of carving at the joints that applies to candidate meanings, or because there is such a notion and C is maximal with respect to it." It is more the bolded part that leads towards relativism, not different uses of "exists/subsists/etc."Count Timothy von Icarus

    I think that distinction that Sider makes is important, and I see what you are saying. What I would say is that the bolded part leads to a more thoroughgoing conceptual relativism, but the latter option is still a form of conceptual relativism. It's just that in the latter case both candidate meanings do a good job, and an equally good job, of carving at the joints. This latter form, when applied to logic, represents Banno's logical pluralism.

    ---

    The "is" of predication, identity, and existence are not separated out in the same way in this tradition. In part, this is because they were seen as deeply related.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Right. I'm glad you saw this on your own.

    Given the view that things just are their properties (which are relational), a not unpopular view in contemporary metaphysics, the the sum total of what can be predicated of a thing is its identity, or at least something very close to it.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Right. See the paper I linked earlier, "Schopenhauer and Wittgenstein on Self and Object," for an argument that Fregian logic is unable to capture ontological dynamism.

    In such a view, there is no Porphyryean tree that has infinite and finite being alongside each other.Count Timothy von Icarus

    It should perhaps be noted that analogical predication (or also analogical being) cannot be captured by anything like a Venn diagram. To say that two kinds of being are equivocal is to separate them, and to say that two kinds of being are univocal is to collapse them into one. Analogy is the strange mean. I said more on this earlier in the thread.
  • Wittgenstein and How it Elicits Asshole Tendencies.
    That is very far from saying "that everyone who lived before modern optics must have been a naive realist".Janus

    The whole premise of your argument is that those who lived prior to modern optics were naive realists. Drop that premise and the whole argument disappears. Here it is again:

    It seems that, by and large, the ancient and medieval philosophers were naive realists even if they believed in the reality of a higher realm. This is arguably because, before the modern sciences of optics and visual perception, the eyes were thought to be the 'windows' through which the soul looked out onto the world, so there would have been no notion of "distortion" which may be posited in relation to the senses as they are now understood.Janus

    We haven't even gotten into how unintelligent this argument really is. One does not require modern optics to recognize the possibility of visual distortion. Eye disease, perspective, differing visual capabilities, and the fact that far-away objects are difficult to see all demonstrate such a thing. The ironic thing here is that the presuppositions of those who think the ancients were dumb, are dumb. "They didn't have modern optics therefore they couldn't understand visual distortion." That's a bad, bad argument.