I'm not sure whether you are talking logic or child development here. But it seems to me that, from a child development perspective, this must be right. The development of empathy in small children has been much studied - admittedly the primary focus is on emotional empathy, but awareness of the different perspectives of other people (emotional and cognitive) is included. The philosophical relevance is that this is where the concept of knowledge becomes necessary for understanding what people do - or don't do. (Belief, it seems to me, must come later.)I'd suggest that here truth is foundational, and knowledge derivative. — Banno
I'm not sure whether you are talking logic or child development here. — Ludwig V
H'm. I can see that one might use the words in those ways. But I would have called what you call the brute given, what I know by introspection, and called what you call introspection ordinary knowledge. But there is a fuzzy line between the experience of pain and the interpretations of pain (as caused by falling down or whatever). My doubts about what you are saying are around the fact that what you call he "brute given" is only by extension something that I know about. That requires me to distance myself from the experience itself and think about it in a way quite different from the simple reaction ("Ouch!"), which does not mean "I am in pain", which requires conceptualization.Introspection is not immune from mistakes, because it is most always inferential. That one experiences what one presently experiences is, on the other hand, a brute given. — javra
I think the practice is all right. When I say "I saw X in a dream", I defuse the standard meaning of "see" by adding "in a dream". That signals that I'm aware that I didn't "really" see X. (Contrast the small child who wakes up in the middle of the night terrified by the wolves all round the house.)As one very common example, visual experiences that occur during REM periods of sleep are all seen with the mind’s eye. So then people can’t say, “I saw X in a dream last night”? Yet this is common practice. — javra
Yes. That's not an accident. But what I'm especially interested in is, put it this way, the glitches in natural language that require us to develop or learn conceptual dodges that enable us to cope. My reply to @J earlier (bottom of last page) is a nice example. It's in a grey area between logic and psychology, but it is where, IMO, the later Wittgenstein is operating. The Blue Book is an excellent example, just because he is developing his methodology.Logic. But I'm thinking of Davidson here, too - interpretation and the principle of charity fit in with your comments regarding empathy... — Banno
That's true. But it requires, not just introspection, but an awareness of other people as different in certain ways. Arguably, that awareness is even essential to self-awareness and introspection beyond what Wittgenstein calls expressions in his discussion of pain, as in " the verbal expression of pain replaces crying, it does not describe it" (PI 244) and "How can I even attempt to interpose language between the expression of pain and the pain?" (PI 245.Belief only makes sense against a background of truth; it is, after all, what is thought true as opposed what is actually true. — Banno
I don't quite understand this. Our community ascribes false beliefs to people all the time and that's why they are called "intentional" — Ludwig V
I cannot justify that I have that knowledge to you, if you believe me you take it on faith. — Janus
But your description is excluding the "straightforward" answer that the drunk is hallucinating a pink elephant. — Ludwig V
In a sense, of course, it just kicks the can down the road, — Ludwig V
Do I have to know that X is true in order to use it as the T in a JTB statement? — J
Under the strongest possible interpretation of truth-conditional semantics (the principle of maximal charity), the meaning of your use of a sentence S refers to the actual cause of your use of S; — sime
On the other hand, if the community gets to decide the truth-maker of your use of S irrespective of whatever caused you to utter S (the principle of minimal charity), then you cannot know that S is true until after you have used S and received feedback. In which case, the truth of S isn't a quality of your mental state when you used S. — sime
"That is a prime number" is true (or false) regardless of what John thinks about it. The question is, How confident can he be that he knows which is which? — J
My doubts about what you are saying are around the fact that what you call he "brute given" is only by extension something that I know about. That requires me to distance myself from the experience itself and think about it in a way quite different from the simple reaction ("Ouch!"), which does not mean "I am in pain", which requires conceptualization. — Ludwig V
I think the practice is all right. When I say "I saw X in a dream", I defuse the standard meaning of "see" by adding "in a dream". That signals that I'm aware that I didn't "really" see X. — Ludwig V
No. But it has to be true. This was my first reply to you in the present conversation:Do I have to know that X is true in order to use it as the T in a JTB statement? — J
Seems to me that folk read JTB as the claim that in order to know something, we must know that it is true. It's hard to get across that this is not what the JTB account is saying. It's not that the proposal is justified, believed and known to be true, but that it is justified, believed and true. — Banno
Agreed. I think we're speaking of self-justification here. Can you justify to yourself that "I am thinking X" is necessarily true? — J
Justification is only for beliefs, not for those things known with certainty. — Janus
OK, that seems like a good way to look at it, with perhaps the caveat that it's reasonable also to ask, "Why are you certain?" or "What makes you rely on this experience?" (similarity to previous ones, presumably). — J
The problem I have is that he doubts things on the mere logical possibility that he might be deceived by an Evil Demon. — Janus
It isn't. Which is why the relationship between the object of the belief and the mental state of the believer is not a causal relationship.But if this relationship is a causal relationship between the object of the belief and the mental state of the believer, then how is a false belief possible? — sime
That's a very good point. But the object will be framed in a language, and that language will be the framework will have been learned from the community.the intentionality of a mental state has nothing to do with the opinions and linguistic biases of a community, — sime
Well, the first option is not an option, so it must be the second. But it's not quite right to say that the truth-maker of specific beliefs is decided by the community. The community teaches us about truth and falsity and how to determine it in general. Individuals then apply that framework to specific cases; disagreements will be discussed within the community and, often but not always, an agreement will be reached. (Sometimes the belief will be one that is not determined by the shared rules.)And hence as with the example of a thermometer, either humans have intentional belief states, in which case their beliefs cannot be false due to the object of their beliefs being whatever caused their beliefs, else their beliefs are permitted to be false, in which case the truth-maker of their belief is decided externally by their community. — sime
Not quite right. Given that I have learned how to determine truth and falsity, I can make a decision. I don't need feedback on each case. Nonetheless, the feedback that I receive is important in maintaining the framework that we have all learned. (It is not impossible for the community to be wrong.)On the other hand, if the community gets to decide the truth-maker of your use of S irrespective of whatever caused you to utter S (the principle of minimal charity), then you cannot know that S is true until after you have used S and received feedback. In which case, the truth of S isn't a quality of your mental state when you used S. — sime
Yes and no. I think it is more accurate to say that the requirement of truth is a kind of absolute liability. I make my judgements, but they may turn out to be wrong later on. In that case, I have to withdraw my claim.the question seems to be whether I have to know that X is true. — J
It's true that we rarely consciously and specifically apply the JTB. It's a formalization of what (normally) we actually do in a messy, informal way. I don't understand what it would be for something to be "pre-JTB".We can loosen that requirement, and say that "X is true" is pre-JTB and therefore not a knowable instance of truth. This seems to resemble more closely our actual practice. — J
Asking the question "what is a hallucination?" in the sense that you seem to mean it presupposes that a hallucination is an object. It leads us to posit various other pseudo-objects as if they could magically explain away what puzzles us. But they can't. The whole point is that there is no object. But if you ask what leads us to say that someone is hallucinating, we look at what someone says and does - attributing a hallucination to them presents what's going on in a way we can understand. It is still puzzling and we look for explanations - there's no way round that.For what is a hallucination, and how do we talk about it? Is there an obvious consensus? Some would describe hallucinating as "seeing something that isn't there"; others would describe it as "thinking you see something that isn't there". Is there a meaningful difference, apart from choice of terms? — J
Very true. It is odd that there seem to be no philosophers who actually accept scepticism. They all try to explain it away or neutralize it. Mostly, other philosophers accept the destructive moment, but reject the constructive response.He detested skepticism and believed he had refuted it. (And we have a perfectly good modern version of the Evil Demon: the "Matrix hypothesis.") — J
The problem is that he does not consider what actual limitations there are on doubts, and reduces it to the possibility of saying "I doubt that..." in front of almost any proposition. But if we ask what the content, the reality, the significance, of the doubt is, we find nothing.He points out that it would be possible to doubt them. — J
I think that the justifications are mostly the same sorts of facts that would show whether X is true or false. But there can be justifications to the effect that I am in a position, have the skills, to know - which are of a different kind or level.Let's say I'm in a "JTB situation"; that is, I want to find out whether I possess a piece of knowledge. Will the justifications that I cite -- the J in JTB -- for why I believe X refer to the same sorts of facts that, out in the world, would show whether statement X is true or false? — J
I don't think that JTB is the kind of thing that the later Wittgenstein would want to accept or reject - pointing out the consequences of acceptance and rejection and leaving us to make up our own minds is much more his style.I'm not convinced that Wittgenstein accepted JTB, in the way Sam26 seems to think. I read him in On Certainty more as pointing out that if we do accept JTB then these are the consequences - there are for instance things that we might casually say we know that are rules out as knowledge by the JTB account. — Banno
I get the point. Applying JTB to a dog seems inappropriate, because the dog doesn't speak. As always with animals, applying our descriptions of what we know and feel to them needs to be done quite carefully. But I think we can attribute beliefs to dogs - and other animals, and we can ask how why they believe what they believe and assess whether their beliefs are true or not. The same applies to experiences - there's no doubt, IMO, that they feel pain, sometimes less and sometimes more. So I don't understand why you say this - unless you are thinking of our inability to know what it's like to be a bat.We can't know how a dog that has been run over feels. — Banno
I think that the justifications are mostly the same sorts of facts that would show whether X is true or false. But there can be justifications to the effect that I am in a position, have the skills, to know - which are of a different kind or level. — Ludwig V
We can loosen that requirement, and say that "X is true" is pre-JTB and therefore not a knowable instance of truth. This seems to resemble more closely our actual practice.
— J
It's true that we rarely consciously and specifically apply the JTB. It's a formalization of what (normally) we actually do in a messy, informal way. I don't understand what it would be for something to be "pre-JTB". — Ludwig V
Asking the question "what is a hallucination?" in the sense that you seem to mean it presupposes that a hallucination is an object. — Ludwig V
The problem is that he does not consider what actual limitations there are on doubts, and reduces it to the possibility of saying "I doubt that..." in front of almost any proposition. But if we ask what the content, the reality, the significance, of the doubt is, we find nothing. — Ludwig V
I'm a bit confused by all this. Someone passes on to me a piece of information. Normally, I would just accept what I'm told because this informant is very reliable. But for some reason I decide to examine this claim more closely. So I set aside my assumptions including my belief that what I have been told is true. Then I ask myself the questions... Short story, anyone with any sense entering a "JTB situation" would and should set aside any assumptions that have already been made.By pre-JTB I mean that we would enter the "JTB situation" already believing that X is true. Our belief in X is not a result of what is about to happen if we successfully apply JTB, hence not knowledge. The difference between believing and knowing is important here. If, in trying to determine whether I possess a piece of knowledge, I ask myself, "Is X true?" (a JTB requirement for knowledge), I can only reply, "I believe so." I can't say, "I know it is," because this initiates the vicious circle. — J
I think one defeats a claim to knowledge if it is false. Possibly false is far too strong and leads to us abandoning swathes of what we know quite unnecessarily. "possible" does not imply "actual".The problem that I have with the idea of knowledge being defeasible is that if it isn't true it isn't knowledge, so if what I think I know is possibly false, then I don't really know it—so I say instead that I believe it and that it is belief, not knowledge, which is defeasible. — Janus
Hallucinating isn't usually something that I do; it's something that happens to me. I think of it as an event or process. The point of the concept of hallucination is to allow us to recognize Macbeth's behaviour ("Is this a dagger I see before me?" etc. etc.) as what it is, the behaviour of someone who is seeing a dagger, but cancelling the actual dagger. Compare pretending or acting.It can just as well be an activity or an event. We can still ask what it is, taking "is" in one of its many familiar usages. The question was whether there's a "correct way" to describe the activity of hallucinating using the word "see." I'm saying, no, it's terminological; "see" can work either way. — J
Oh dear! My memories of that are, I'm afraid, a bit vague. Perhaps I am being too harsh. I would accept that there is a balance to be struck. But I am quite sure that not all possibilities are equally possible. The awkward bit is that the dividing line between them is not at all clear. There's possibilities like the ones that Eliza dreams about when she sings "wouldn't it be loverly" in My Fair Lady or we can be fascinated by like "Battle Star Galactica". I classify these as fantasies and I think they have only have significance for psychology or the philosophy of psychology. There's other possibilities like whether there is still honey for tea or the cream is still fresh. They do have significance for epistemology. Possibilities can change their status. Something that is a fantasy at one time can become a dream and ultimately a reality.We've talked about this in the context of Williams' book on Descartes. I think you're being too harsh. — J
any verdict I give on the truth or not of the information is inescapably only what I know or believe. — Ludwig V
I think it is true that we can equally say that Macbeth is seeing something that isn't there or Macbeth thinks he sees something that isn't there. — Ludwig V
We've talked about this in the context of Williams' book on Descartes. I think you're being too harsh.
— J
Oh dear! My memories of that are, I'm afraid, a bit vague. Perhaps I am being too harsh. — Ludwig V
This comes out in an anecdote related by Fania Pascal, who knew him in Cambridge in the 1930s:
I had my tonsils out and was in the Evelyn Nursing Home feeling sorry for myself. Wittgenstein called. I croaked: “I feel just like a dog that has been run over.” He was disgusted: “You don’t know what a dog that has been run over feels like.” — On Bullshit Harry Frankfurt
Notice that you are not asking if p is true, but how you find out if p is true, and so again asking about an attitude. The facts that help you decide on your attitude are irrelevant to whether p is true or not.Would the facts necessary (to find out whether X is true) be the exact same ones cited as my justifications for believing X? — J
He wants the grand prize -- absolute certainty, beyond even the possibility of doubt. I personally feel that we don't need that in order to do metaphysics and epistemology; Descartes disagreed, hence his Method. But we really shouldn't see him as raising "philosophers' doubts" for the sake of skepticism. He detested skepticism and believed he had refuted it. (And we have a perfectly good modern version of the Evil Demon: the "Matrix hypothesis.") — J
The problem that I have with the idea of knowledge being defeasible is that if it isn't true it isn't knowledge, so if what I think I know is possibly false, then I don't really know it—so I say instead that I believe it and that it is belief, not knowledge, which is defeasible.
— Janus
I think one defeats a claim to knowledge if it is false. Possibly false is far too strong and leads to us abandoning swathes of what we know quite unnecessarily. "possible" does not imply "actual". — Ludwig V
If knowledge were a matter of accumulated atomic pieces, then you are right. But it isn't. We learn how to do colour and at least some of the colours at the same time, and elaborate from there. We learn about solid objects as we encounter them before we can even conceive of them. Then we can deal with individual solid objects as they crop up, whether we have encountered that specific kind before or not.Because to already know that the piece of information is true, that knowledge would have to have been verified via JTB. — J
Have you got a better candidate? I don't recall encountering one.(This all assumes you think JTB is a good yardstick for knowledge, of course.) — J
Knowing what a knife is is only partly a question of knowing that it has a sharp edge and a handle. It also involves having the know-how to identify knives and distinguish them from spoons and swords. That requires input from other people, who have been teaching me what objects are and how to classify them since before I could speak.If he cannot know that he knows what a knife is, then he can, at best, merely know that he believes he is experiencing a knife. — Count Timothy von Icarus
If metaphysics is about the non-cognitive (which needs a bit more fleshing out), are we sure that certainty and plausibility even apply?in fact in the case of metaphysics I would say there can be no certainty at all, that it all comes down to plausibility, because we are dealing with the non-cognitive. — Janus
Yes, that's right. In the case of the Matrix, it turns out that the real world is the same kind of world that the simulation places us in, so the fundamentals haven't changed. In fact, as we know, there is a case for saying that we already know that the real world is radically different from the world as we know it. No solid objects, everything consists of wavicles. What a nightmare!The Matrix Hypothesis I think is absurd, because it posits that there is a real world in which the virtual world we inhabit is sustained, and this means the need for explanation is just pushed one step further back. — Janus
Well, if there were something to be gained, it might be a change worth making. But so long as we distinguish between true beliefs and false ones, the issues remain. But what are the issues? As I sit here, it is possible that a meteorite or similar is hurtling towards me and will land on my head. I could move and so avoid that disaster. But the possibility applies to anywhere else I might move to. So not only is the probability uncomputable and vanishingly small, but there is nothing I can do to avoid it - apart from living a mile underground, which would have its own limitations and dangers. So I take my cue from my society and ignore the possibility. I haven't been wrong yet.Why do we need to talk in terms of 'knowledge that' when nothing is lost by talking instead of 'justifiably believing that'? — Janus
We can only pretend something that is possible. So if something is possibly false and we can pretend to know it, then it must be possible to actually know it.I would say that it we determine that something is possibly false then we don't at all need to "abandon it" but merely to abandon the pretense that we know it to be so, for the more modest claim that we believe it to be so. — Janus
I take your point. Whether I believe that p and on what grounds is a matter that is entirely distinct from the question whether p is true. That distinction is important when I am considering the beliefs of other people. But when I ask myself whether I believe that p, surely I need to consider whether p? When I have decided whether p, I know whether I believe it or not. From my point of view, there are not two questions here, but only one.The facts that help you decide on your attitude are irrelevant to whether p is true or not. — Banno
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.