Comments

  • A Measurable Morality


    First, as I requested, please stop using the term normative so that this stays simple and clear. We're not talking about any claim, but "moral claims". A moral claim involves 'should'.

    Fair enough; sorry, I meant moral claim here.

    'Should' requires a reason. If there is no reason, then there is no 'should'. If there is no 'should' there is no objective morality.

    I asked why do normative “moral” claims need a reason and you said because “if there is no reason, then there is no ‘should’”: why?

    This seems to imply that I cannot assert “one should not torture babies” without an underlying reason; but I clearly can, no?

    Platonism's truth has nothing to do with whether it should be. For example, someone kills a baby. I can claim they should not have killed a baby. But its still true they killed a baby. When we say something 'should' exist, we say it that it is preferable that it be versus not be. So we can ask, "Why should Platonism exist?" To answer why Platonism or anything else should exist, we really have to answer the question, "Why should anything exist?" first.

    No. Again, I think you missed the point: if platonism were true, then “I should not torture babies” does get reasoned down to “why should anything exist?” or “something should exist”: it is true in virtue of a Platonic Form. I am merely bringing this up because one of your points in your argument was that all chains of reasoning about moral claims boils down to “why should anything exist?”: they don’t.

    I think, and correct me if I am wrong, you are noting that whatever moral claims may be true they are not useful to the subject if the subject doesn’t think they should exist; and then you are applying that to existence itself: “to be or not to be?”. But, crucially, it can go the other way around just as easily: “one should help the sick” implies that “one should continue existing”--in this case, the former is not true in virtue of the latter but actually vice-versa.

    A. There exists a reason that nothing should exist.
    B. If that is the case, then the reason that nothing should exist, should not exist.
    Therefore, there should not exist a reason that justifies non-existence.

    There’s no logical contradiction in that syllogism, and I wholly agree with its form. In fact, I am glad you wrote this because that is way more precisely what I was trying to convey then what I was saying! (: — Bob Ross

    We are in agreement then! We can then agree the only logical conclusion is that nothing should not be. Assuming an objective morality, the only thing we can start with then is that something is what should be. With that, we can move onto the next points.

    I think you may have misread my response there: I disagree with you that there is a contradiction in A B C argument you have. In order for there to be a contradiction, there must be something wrong with the form (for logic) or they most be incoherent (in content), I am failing to see that in:

    A. There exists a reason that nothing should exist.
    B. If that is the case, then the reason that nothing should exist, should not exist.
    Therefore, there should not exist a reason that justifies non-existence.

    What’s the contradiction?
  • A Case for Moral Subjectivism


    Ok, that's a big chunk for you Bob! I know its busy because its Christmas season, so happy holidays if I don't hear from you before then!

    Merry Christmas to you too!

    I want to, firstly, express my gratitude for your elaborate response: I can tell you read through it all and I know how much effort it is to respond that lengthy and substantively—so thank you!

    Before I respond, I originally was going to wait to post my normative ethical theory until it was more refined and polished up, but, like you said, it doesn’t seem to make a different how precise I think I am using my terminology nor how exact the idea is—as someone is going to find something wrong with it from their perspective. Since I don’t think we are making all that much progress here metaethically and I think you enjoy the normative ethics stuff more, I suggest we go to my new thread to discuss normative ethics and then segue back here if need be...but I will leave it up to you as I am down for either.

    Since our responses are getting quite lengthy, I am going to summarize what I got out of your response instead of trying to go paragraph by paragraph because that will end up being an essay longer than the OP (:

    So, for my own sake of keeping track, I think you should pick a couple or perhaps one and we focus in on it first; otherwise, there is so many disputes going on here I don’t know we can safely maneuver all of them at once (;

    Here’s some of our disputes:

    1. Moral judgments expressing something subjective vs. being subjective themselves. You seem to be focusing on the latter, while I the former.
    2. You believe I didn’t provide a positive case for prong-2 of my thesis, but I think the proof of (1) moral judgments being propositional, (2) some moral judgments being true, and (3) that moral judgments do not express something objective entails that moral judgments express something subjective.
    3. Truth-aptness for you is not contingent on a statement/sentence, but for me it is.
    4. The liar paradox, stated as ‘this statement is false’, for you is truth-apt, for me it is not.
    5. For you, it seems to be a problem that we cannot acquire 100% certain knowledge of what is objective because we only know it through ourselves as subjects, which I don’t see anything wrong with. I have no problem admitting that we only have conditional knowledge of the things-in-themselves, in the sense that we only every analyze representations of things-in-themselves: this doesn’t mean that we are just analyzing things which are purely subjective.
    6. You seem to think that it is a flaw in my theory that moral judgments cannot never be false relative to the psychology of the person at hand, but this just seems like it is the central idea behind the theory itself.
    7. I think that moral permissibility is the allowance to do something, which doesn’t entail that one should or should not do it, and you seem to think it means that one should do it; and this is why I think you think there is a symmetry behind my example of eating a sandwhich = permissible and not eating a sandwich = impermissible; but I would say being permissible is not the same thing as one being obligated to do it.
    8. I don’t think moral nihilism is the view that there is no objective morality; but you seem to think we can simplify it down to that claim.
    9. You seem to think you can simplify “moral judgments are propositional” to “true moral judgments are proposition”; but, to me, those are clearly too separate claims.
    10. At one point, you said I don’t believe there are true moral judgments, but I do.
    11. Number 11 here is this:

    1. If there is not an objective morality, it means all possible claims of what should or should not happen,
    even contradictory claims, correlate with reality.

    This is not at all what objective morality means [in metaethics].


    As a side note:

    The "thing in itself" does not refer to an object. An object is a subjective attempt at understanding what a 'thing in itself is'. Our thoughts are 'things in themselves'. Their intentions, judgements, etc. about other things in themselves.

    This is fair. I don’t really have a problem saying that we also don’t know ourselves except for how we externally and internally affect our sensibility. So, yeah, I agree that things-in-themselves are not objects. But truth isn’t a thing-in-itself in that sense...that just seems super weird to say that the relationship itself exists as an entity, a thing-in-itself, out there that we are grasping. This seems platonistic to me.

    Which would you like to talk about, or would you like to pause and discuss normative ethics?

    Bob
  • A Measurable Morality


    Yes, it does have to stop somewhere. But a reason does not have to have a prior reason. I'm saying the ultimate reason is, "It is". This is by necessity as there is nothing prior, nor nothing to negate 'what is'.

    You would be absolutely correct if all reasons had an underlying reason. I'm noting that we reach a point in which there is no underlying reason, but a foundation. Recall we are assuming morality exists. So if this is the case, and we've reached a foundation, that is what we build upon.

    I think I am understanding better now: you are saying that the “existing should be” is grounded in a the reason that “it is”, which would entail that every normative claim, assuming that’s the most fundamental one, does have a reason. But why think that all normative claims need a reason? Why can’t “existing should be” just have no reason?

    For example:

    I would say that's a reason. "I should help the world because I feel like it" is a reason. The point is I could then ask, "Why should your feelings matter?" In other words, asking the reason behind the reason.

    What if someone just says “well, if you can have no reason for why it is, then I don’t need a reason for why it should be”: what’s the symmetry breaker here?

    I could just as easily say, "I should eat children because God tells me to." A claim does not make it so. But you make a good point in the fact I have not explicitly stated a "true reason"

    So in your example of Plato's forms, I could say, "What's the proof behind Plato's forms?" But lets say that it is true. Plato's forms DO exist. I then would ask, "Why should Plato's forms exist?" Do you see the chain now?

    I think this missed my point, although I see what you are saying. You claimed all chains of reasoning boils down to “should existence be, or not?”...but my example clearly, if platonism were granted as true, that this is not true. The point was not that platonism is true, it is that if there are moral facts, then the chain of reasoning for a normative statements ends at the fact that makes it true, and not necessarily “should existence be, or not?”.

    Because we're doing a test. We're saying, "If morality, or what 'should' be is apart from humanity, what logically would that be? We must first define it, only then can we apply it. To say that morality exists apart from human opinion but leave it without what that would entail means we don't know what we're talking about.

    This doesn’t explain how this is a calculus of the universe: your answer seems to be that we just assume it. I guess this just boils down to me granting it for the sake of the conversation, so let’s just move past that point.

    A. There exists a reason that nothing should exist.
    B. If that is the case, then the reason that nothing should exist, should not exist.
    Therefore, there should not exist a reason that justifies non-existence.

    There’s no logical contradiction in that syllogism, and I wholly agree with its form. In fact, I am glad you wrote this because that is way more precisely what I was trying to convey then what I was saying! (:

    So, if you think there is a logical contradiction in that syllogism, then you will have to demonstrate it to me,because I don’t see it. If there exists a reason that nothing should exist, then it totally logically follows that that reason shouldn’t exist either. I don’t see any “p ^ !p” in that argument at all. Let me explicate the logic. I think you think the logic is:

    A: p
    B: p → !p
    C: !p

    But this is incorrect, it is actually:

    A: p
    B: p → q
    C: q

    “there exists a reason that nothing should exist” != “there should not exist the reason that nothing should exist”, and that is required for there to be a (logical) contradiction in the argument which would be at the consequent of B.

    Are you claiming that there is an incoherence, i.e., like a non-logical contradiction, in it, perhaps? Maybe having a reason for that very reason to not exist seems incoherent to you?
  • A Case for Moral Subjectivism


    I appreciate your response!

    Firstly, I agree that the simplest way to convey something is the best but, as of now, with all due respect, I think your simplifications are over-simplifications; and, believe it or not, the OP is the most concise, precise, and simplest way I have found to convey my metaethical theory.

    Secondly, with respect to the terms, I hate semantics just as much as the next guy! So I agree that we should not get caught up on the terminology: the reason I use the terms I have been using is they are the most widely accepted and precise ways of conveying exactly what I want to convey—so why would I makeup new words or use less precise words to convey the exact same thing?

    Thirdly, I think there is one core issue in our conversation that needs sorting out before we can continue, namely that you seem to think metaethics is useless and normative ethics is all that matters. Of course, this metaethical theory doesn’t address what is permissible, omissible, or obligatory...it isn’t supposed to! That’s for normative ethics. So, I think I need to provide a case not for moral subjectivism (specifically) but, rather, for the study of metaethics. If you don’t see any value in metaethics, then there’s no point in discussing moral subjectivism, since it is a metaethical theory.

    As a side note, I am working on a normative ethical theory, I just haven’t posted it yet. It isn’t posted with this metaethical theory because (1) I find it is useful to split the two so as to hone in on metaethical and normative ethical disputes separately and (2) I haven’t finished my normative ethical theory yet (to my liking).

    Now, let me address some points you made to hopefully demonstrate why metaethics is important; but, first, let me outline some general points. Metaethics is about the nature of moral judgments and properties, and not what is right or wrong. This is incredibly important because it is important to know, beyond what is being expressed as right or wrong, what a moral judgment itself actually is (e.g., is it truth-apt? Is it expressing something subjective or objective? Are any of them true?). As an example, let’s take the metaethical claim that ‘there is at least one true moral judgment’: if this is false, then morality is pointless and always incorrect—hence, error theory. Let’s take ‘moral judgments are proposition’: if they aren’t, then we cannot use them as propositions which, in turn, entails we cannot apply logic to them—hence moral non-cognitivism. Let’s take ‘moral judgments express something objective’: if this is false, then there is no moral fact out there that makes a moral judgment true—hence moral subjectivism. You are saying all of this is useless…..but your own normative ethical theory we are discussing in the other form implicitly assumes metaethical claims.

    Any statement is truth-apt Bob.

    I would like to note the following:

    1. Judgments are not necessarily statements. A moral non-cognitivist would say that moral judgments are emotional dispositions (i.e., they are conative not cognitive) that are along the lines of ‘boo to torturing babies!!!!!!!’, where they are not saying the moral judgment is the statement ‘boo to torturing babies!!!!!!’ but, rather, the underlying emotional attitude which can be expressed without a statement (e.g., someone looks very angry and astonished when witnessing someone torturing a baby, etc.). So when you say statements are truth-apt, even if it is true, it doesn’t get you moral cognitivism. You would have to demonstrate moral judgments are truth-apt; and you seem to just blow this off and ignore the entire literature on moral non-cognitivism.

    2. Statements are not always truth-apt. For example, I would say that the statement “this statement is false” is not truth-apt because it cannot be evaluated as true or false...it lacks that capacity.

    If its true, its 1+1=2. We don't call it "Cognitive number theory vs non-cognitive number theory". We call it math.

    The proposition “1+1=2” presupposes that it is truth-apt; but you seem to be trying to argue that it is truth-apt because it is a proposition—that isn’t valid. If ‘1+1=2’ can be true, then you have already conceded it is truth-apt, but we are questioning why. Why think it is truth-apt? That would be a meta-mathematical debate. However, this is a metaethical debate about whether moral judgments like ‘one ought not torture babies for fun’ are truth-apt or not.

    Mathematics would presuppose, and does presuppose, that mathematical judgments are proposition; just like how your normative ethical theory presupposes that moral judgments are propositional.

    4. Morality is what is permissible. You have not given a clear example of what is permissible with any proof. Only that we can make moral judgements, and if they correspond with reality, or what is objective, its true.

    Of course not! That’s what a normative ethical theory is for! The point of moral subjectivism is to note that whatever a person judges morally, it is made true by being a fact about their psychology and not some moral fact out there in the world. I think you have missed the point if you are demanding actual normative claims out of the theory.

    4. Because we are subjects, morality is subjective.

    I’ve never argued this. This is clearly false.

    There is nothing implicit about it though. For something to be permissible, there is an implication that something is not permissible. Does that mean that not eating a sandwich implicitly concedes it is impermissible?

    No, because not eating the sandwich could have implied one finds it morally permissible not to eat it. Whereas, eating it immediately implies that it is permissible to do so—it wouldn’t make sense if it implied they thought it was impermissible.

    Also, I don’t why it would be the case that “for something to be permissible, there is an implication that something is not permissible”, unless you mean that X being morally permissible entails that it is morally impermissible for X to not be morally permissible? But, then, I don’t see your point.

    A theory has a conclusion with proof.

    I gave an argument for all three prongs of the thesis, so it is theory. You haven’t actually dealt with all of them. They were not definitions.

    Did you come up with a theory of morality that is meaningful and useful to others? That's all that matters.

    As long as it is useful to me, then that’s good with me. Also, it isn’t a fair criticism to claim that a theory is false because no one thinks it is useful. Likewise, most people don’t find many things I find useful useful: why does that matter?

    Take my advice here as an equal: eliminate any words or phrases that does not make your arguments as simple and clear as possible. Use George Orwells six points of writing. It is an ongoing battle for myself as well, but it is the way to make clear and meaningful arguments. An insistence on a normative and metaethical separation is missing the trees in the forest

    I agree that one should keep it simple, but you seem (to me) to be oversimplifying it. With all due respect, you keep conflating the two in important ways, and that is why I keep bringing it up. For example, in your other thread you assume moral realism is true without proving it...you didn’t even attempt to. Likewise with moral cognitivism and moral non-nihilism. You just flatly assert or implicitly assume that they are true without providing an argument. That’s why each prong I have has an argument for it, even if one, at the end of the day, doesn’t agree with them.

    Taken as a thesis and not a proof, this is fine. This still does not negate that there is not really anything meaningful stated here.

    Correct. It is a prong of a thesis, not an argument. I outlined the thesis first, then argued for it. The argument for it is later on in the OP.

    Replace, 'true moral judgements' with 'true statements' and its still the same thing. So my criticism of this lacking any meaningful weight still holds for me

    That’s not the point of moral non-nihilism: it is the position that there are true moral judgments—i.e., they are not all false. Error theorists, i.e., moral nihilists, claim that moral judgments are truth-apt and express something objective but they are all false. I am explicitly denying that with this prong of the thesis, and proceed to give an argument for it later on in the OP.

    If truth is objective, then yes, true moral judgements are not subjective.

    No and yes. Truth being objective just means that the correspondence exists mind-independently, but to say that moral judgments express something objective does not follow from that.

    2. True moral judgments express something subjective [moral non-objectivism]
    I would tweak this once again to, "We can make subjective moral judgements that are true."

    You cannot do that validly: they are two different claims. The moral judgment is subjective and it expresses something subjective—i.e., judgments are always subjective because they are themselves an issuance by a subject and these particular judgments (moral ones) are true in virtue of projections of one’s pyschology and not some non-pyschological fact about reality.

    You statement “we can make subjective moral judgments that are true” could be compatible with a moral realist’s claim that “moral judgments express something objective” just as much as a moral anti-realist’s claim that “moral judgments express something subjective”.

    Ah, I see with point one. To more accurately reflect this I would change
    1. Moral judgments are propositional [moral cognitivism]
    into
    1. True moral judgments are propositional [moral cognitivism]

    You cannot do that, because something being propositional does not entail that it is true, it entails that it has the capacity to be true or false.

    By agreeing to ‘moral judgments are propositional’, the person has in no way conceded that ‘there is at least one true moral judgment’. But with your revision, they would have to accept both.

    Morality is about comparing states of affairs and deciding which one is permissable, omissable, or obligatory.

    If for example a baby is about to get shot, you have time to decide what the future reality will be. You could shoot the shooter first. Step in front of the baby. Dive Hollywoodesque in slow motion to move the baby out of the way. These choices come about because we have in our head at a minimum two outcomes. Dead baby or living baby in a future state of reality. What is permissable? We only know this by comparing the two outcomes.

    This is fine, but I think we may have talked passed each other. P1 would dictate that in this baby example there is no fact you can cite which makes any of the moral judgments true, such as ‘one should step in front of the baby first’. What I am not saying, nor does P1 imply that, states of affairs inform our moral judgments—rather, P1 dictates that there is no amount of consideration of what is the case nor the possible outcomes in this baby example that tells me anything about fundamentally what I should morally judge, it just supplements it.

    In other words, the moral judgments are sui generis of your psychology: there’s no moral fact you are able to cite in this baby example that tells you what to do, instead the non-moral facts inform you, based off of your psychology of what you approve or disapprove of, what you should do. The non-moral facts are not enough to dictate what should happen, there is a moral judgment, or multiple, that are just facts about your psychology that make you morally judge one way or another given the circumstances. For a moral realist, this is not the case, from the baby example there is a moral fact-of-the-matter out there in that possible world or this actual one that dictates what one should do, and one is just trying to discover what that is—they aren’t projecting their own opinions on what one should do.

    All you seem to be noting, and correct me if I am wrong, is that we use the current and potential states of affairs to supplement our moral judgments, which is totally fine and I absolutely agree with...but I disagree that if you were to just give me the facts about the baby scenario, that I would be able to know what I should do—there is some ‘should’ or ‘shoulds’ which are being projected by my psychology that ultimately dictate, once I am informed of the facts about the baby example, what I decide I ought to do.

    If you eliminate states of affairs, or make "reality" the combined set of all states of affairs, then you ALSO eliminate morality.

    Not quite. Since I believe moral judgments are not made true by moral facts out there, I think that we project what we approve or disapprove of and use that to determine what to do. I am quite literally arguing that there are no moral states-of-affairs that exist mind-independently: “there are no moral phenomena, just moral interpretations of phenomena” as nietzsche put it.

    Someone morally judging a situation based off of that situation and potential states-of-affairs is perfectly compatible with P1. P1 just says that there is no way to infer strictly from those mind-independent states-of-affairs what should be.

    But even knowledge cannot know truth, as truth is an objective thing in itself.

    I would say that truth is not a thing-in-itself, because things-in-themselves are objects. This is why I find it hard to say truth is objective but also that truth isn’t. There isn’t a object, abstract or not, that exists which is the correspondence of thought with reality. The mere relationship between thought and reality such that they correspond is what truth is, and this can be acquired from a subjective viewpoint so long as that subject agrees that there are objects. They don’t come to know truth itself like an object that they observe, it is the abstract relationship between thinking and being: between mind and not mind. If it were an object, like an apple, then you would be right.

    Truth is only objective in the sense that that abstract relationship is not contingent on subject’s determinations of it. If you are just noting that we can’t be absolutely certain that that relationship exists from our subjective standpoint, then I wholly agree.

    I look forward to hearing from you.
    Bob
  • A Case for Moral Subjectivism


    A belief never makes a moral judgment true. — Leontiskos
    Why? Doesn’t me believing vanilla ice cream tastes good make it true that my stance is that ice cream tastes good? — Bob Ross

    That's not a moral judgment, as you just admitted.

    That wasn’t the point: it was an analogy. If I say “I believe one ought not torture babies for fun” is a moral judgment that is true in virtue of the belief, then you will say I am question begging.

    You want to say that there are beliefs that are true simply in virtue of themselves existing. My point was that while infallible judgments do exist ("I feel pain"), they are not beliefs. We do not say, "I believe I feel pain." An infallible judgment is a matter of strict knowledge, not belief.

    It is the same reasoning that leads you to believe that “I feel pain” is infallible makes “I believe one ought not torture babies” infallible: they are self-referential. “I believe I feel pain” is not self-referential: it is a belief about a fact about one’s current state of pain or lack thereof. “I feel pain”, in the sense I think you are talking about, is self-referential: if I have it, then I have it: it isn’t referring to something else, like ‘I think 1+1=2’. Same thing with moral judgments.

    "I love yogurt." "I have brown hair," is not like, "Everyone has brown hair."

    “I believe no one everyone should have brown hair” is like the former statements, and not the latter.

    Ok, so, at the end of the day we are talking in circle because you keep asserting “beliefs have nothing to do with the moral judgment’s truthity” and I assert the opposite. To resolve this, instead of looping around and around, we need to provide arguments. My arguments are in the moral subjectivism OP: if one accepts there are true moral judgments and they are propositional and they are not expressing something objective, then they are expressing something subjective. You would have to contend with those arguments if you want to change my mind.

    How is it a strawman when you agree with my claim entirely?

    You used a misleading example that doesn’t fit what I am targeting. If you wanted to make your point, you should have demonstrated why “I disapprove of it for everyone” is incoherent and not “I disapprove of it for myself, therefore I disapprove of it for others”: the latter was never an inference I was making.

    So then you think this is a rational exchange:
    • Leontiskos: Why should I not torture babies?
    • Bob Ross: Because I believe you shouldn't.

    I think it is rational insofar as my hypothetical response here would justify myself in stopping you but not justify you in not doing it. I would have to convince you that you shouldn’t torture babies (by means I have described in length in the OP), but the my justification for stopping you in this case is valid but doesn’t provide you with any good reasons to believe it yourself.

    The point here is that we have a moral claim that we know to be true, such as, "No one should torture babies." If moral subjectivism is unable to rationally justify such a truth, then moral subjectivism is an inadequate moral theory.

    “No one should torture babies” seems an awful lot, within the context of what you are saying, as expressing something objective, which obviously moral subjectivism cannot account for because it doesn’t think those exist. If you mean “I believe no one should torture babies, and that justifies me in stopping people from torturing babies”, then, yes, my theory can handle that just fine.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    No, the child cannot consent to being tortured for society's sake; but I see your point and will have to think about it: if, let's say, it was an adult then they would have implicitly consented to potentially being 'drafted' to be the one tortured. That's a fair critique.
  • A Case for Moral Subjectivism


    But “Vanilla ice cream tastes good,” is nothing like, “One ought not torture babies.” Only from the latter can we infer something about what is permissible, omissible, or obligatory

    That’s true, but that wasn’t the point. It was to demonstrate why your analogy to math failed.

    A belief never makes a moral judgment true

    Why? Doesn’t me believing vanilla ice cream tastes good make it true that my stance is that ice cream tastes good?

    “Jane believes ice cream tastes good,” is a third-person proposition, and what you say of it is obviously false. A first-person statement like, “I feel pain,” is infallible, but belief statements are not like this. To say, “I believe I feel pain,” is therefore already confused, and is therefore an unused sort of locution. The same holds with, “I enjoy ice cream”/“I believe I enjoy ice cream.” Infallible statements are usually not belief statements, and to make them so is to stretch the sense of 'belief'. But again, these are non-moral according to your definition in the OP.

    All reasoning for why a proposition is true is fallible; so I am not sure what you mean here. Third-person vs. first-person sentences has nothing to do with the fallibility of the statements or lack thereof. I can believe that “I love yogurt” and be wrong about that, same as I can believe that I believe I love yogurt and be wrong about that too: they are not infallible statements.

    If I said, “Leontiskos believes everyone has brown hair,” this would be a false statement, and particularly problematic insofar as I know that not everyone has brown hair

    You would be wrong about that if you actually don’t believe it; and of course whether or not people have brown hair is independent of your belief on it because there is a fact of the matter that makes it true...this isn’t the case with morality.

    Saying that it is “true relative to myself” is a non-response.

    The statement “I love yogurt” can be true relative to me and false relative to you, because we need to know who we are referring to by ‘I’.

    If I disapprove of something for myself, it does not follow that I disapprove of it in others.

    This is a straw man: if you disapprove it for everyone, then you disapprove it for everyone. Obviously, if you only disapprove of yourself doing something, then, of course, you don’t necessarily disapprove of it for other people.

    Look, do you yourself even think personal/subjective reasons are able to justify claims about other persons?

    What do you mean by “personal/subjective reasons”? I would say that some propositions are made true in virtue of beliefs we have—e.g., “I believe people shouldn’t torture babies”, “I like chocolate ice cream”, etc.

    The reason it is irrational to say that someone should eat chocolate ice cream on the basis of my own idiosyncratic taste is because the putative reason does not have justificatory force for the sort of claim in question

    You are just begging the question with “justificatory force”: sure, I don’t approve of forcing someone to eat chocolate ice cream, but if I did then I wouldn’t have a problem with—hence approval/disapproval.

    Your deeper claim seems to be, "Yes, it is irrational. But your moral realism is irrational too, so I am justified in doing this." But even if moral realism were irrational, this would not justify you in doing irrational things.

    Again, show me the contradiction or incoherent with two propositions I am holding with moral subjectivism, and I will concede it is irrational. Until then, I don’t think it is.

    You seem to be like another gentleman/lady I was discussing with that thought that pyshopathic serial killers cannot act rationally with respect to their torturing and killing of innocent people because their actions are immoral and that makes it irrational. I am not saying you think that, but saying people who are consistent with their goals are irrational (which is what you are saying) are irrational seems similar to me.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    I would say that a draft is ethical under at least my original deontological theory because people implicitly consent to it via social contract. If a person is living completely sans a society and some random society tries to abduct them and draft them into their military, then that would be wrong. However, one is not using them as a means to an end in the sense that it is meant as a violation of a person because their participation in society is consent to defend it if need be. It also depends on why the draft is happening as well: is the society just going to war for the fun of it? Or is that society being attacked?
  • A Measurable Morality


    Ok, let’s move on and have some fun! (:

    For starters, I disagree with 2, 4, 8, and 12. Let me briefly elaborate one-by-one, and I will let you decided where you would like us to go.

    2. If something 'should' be, there is a reason for it.

    Three things:

    1. If someone claims that ‘there should be <...>’ and that it is just an upshot of their emotions, then they have no reason for it. What is incoherent with that under your view?

    2. The chain of reasons has to stop somewhere, so the very foundational reason will have no reason; and that foundational reason may very well be a claim like ‘because there should be <...>’. In fact, this gets your point 12 in a lot of trouble:

    3. This seems incoherent with point 12. You say, on one hand, that every claim of ‘something should be’ has a reason underpinning and then claim in 12 that ‘existing should be’ is valid yet has not reason underpinning it: “Existence is, and has no prior reason for being besides the fact that it is. As such, it is the foundational good. It is the prime reason behind all questions of what should be.”--but ‘existing should be’ is the foundational claim of your theory, and it has no reason for it because allegedly existence doesn’t have a prior reason for it.

    4. All chain of reasoning reduces down to the final question, "Should existence be, or not"?

    I don’t see why this is the case. Moral realists can just have to ground the normative claim in a moral fact. For example, I could say that ‘I should not eat children’ is true because there is a Platonic Form that dictates such and that would be the end of the chain of reasoning. I don’t need to further ask “why exist?” to ground why “I should not eat children” if it is made true by a moral fact. This is unnecessary.

    Also, likewise, my example here isn’t about personal opinion and it doesn’t reduce down to “should existence be, or not?”.

    I need briefly pause:

    We're asking why it should be beyond our own opinions. We're looking for the calculus of the universe.

    This is exactly the problem with assuming moral realism without explaining it: what calculus of the universe determines what is morally right or wrong? You seem to think it is “to be or not to be, that is the question”...but what makes this a calculus of the universe and not just a human existential question? The way gravity behaves is clearly rules or laws in the universe, but asking “to be or not to be?” does not seem (by my lights) to have an analogous correlate.

    8. There can be no reason to explain why nothing should be, as there is 'no reason' if there is nothing.

    This is a non-sequitur: the reason can exist and be true that nothing should exist. The fact that the reason must exist has nothing to do with whether or not that reason is valid such that nothing should exist.

    12. Existence is, and has no prior reason for being besides the fact that it is. As such, it is the foundational good. It is the prime reason behind all questions of what should be. It is the prime reason upon which all other moral questions are built upon.

    Besides being incoherent with point 2 and that it seems to presuppose a similar non-sequitur like point 8, it having no reason for why it is has nothing to do with whether it is good. That also seems like a non-sequitur.
  • A Case for Moral Subjectivism


    My apologies! I reskimmed and missed it. Your argument is dense, so I did not retain it after I had finished reading your OP the first time. That's on me. :)

    Absolutely no worries! I do the same thing all the time!

    If all statements are subjective, why not just say "statement"? "Subjective statement" is redundant at that point as there is no contrast. The term subjective is only uniquely useful in contrast with an "objective statement".

    I think you are thinking that the term ‘subjective’ only has any meaning in relation to a statement itself, which I don’t agree with. Of course, a ‘subjective statement’ is redundant, but a ‘statement that expresses something subjective’ is not.

    Subjectivity is useful insofar as it is contrasted with objectivity, which statements are categorized under the former. Statements are always contingent on the stance and mind of a subject...unless your are a platonist (;

    If you eliminate the vocabulary of objective statement, then you may as well eliminate the term "subjective statement" as well.

    I never used the term ‘subjective statement’: I would just say ‘statement’. I am not sure what the contention is here. Moral subjectivism has three prongs to its thesis, and prong 2 is that moral judgments express something subjective: this is not redundant.

    There is still the question of making a statement in regards to utilizing only your personal viewpoint, or making a statement that can be logically agreed upon by all potential viewpoints.

    I would say there is no such thing as analyzing a statement completely sans one’s viewpoint. A statement is generated by one’s viewpoint; and the use of logic doesn’t make the statement objective: the statement can express something which is objective, such as the use of logic.

    ‘trueness’ is the property ascribed to statements of which what they allege of (refer to about) reality correspond/agree with reality with respect to that specific regard — Bob Ross

    What you've done here is make trueness subjective.
    Not at all. The statement is subjective, and it’s correspondence is what it true; and that truth is not dependent on the statement.
    But to say that it is neither objective nor subjective is false. To be mind independent is to be free of any mind. To be mind dependent is to have at least an iota of mind in there. :) It is still mind dependent, as without a mind, you cannot make a true statement.

    This is by-at-large a fair critique. I would say that the correspondence of thought and reality is itself objective because that relationship exists mind-independently. My original reasoning was that truth being the correspondence of thought with reality would make it dependent on thought and reality and therefore it is neither subjective nor objective but, rather, a mixture of both. However, I recognize that the actual relationship (which is truth) of thought and reality such that they correspond exists mind-independently. So truth is objective and absolute. Good point Philosophim!

    This is again the problem of 'everything is now subjective' and it devalues any meaning to the term.

    I was just saying that statement are subjective, not that everything is now subjective. The statement can be expressing something objective, and there are things that are objective which are never uttered in a statement.

    If the intention is, "What ought to be is despite what is", I agree. This assumes that what is could be something different, which is a core consideration of a moral statement.

    The idea is that normativity and objectivity are exclusive categories. It doesn’t matter what is the case nor what potentially could be the case nor what would be the case but, rather, only what should be the case.

    You cannot come to know something objective according to your terminology. Objectivity is mind independent. Meaning that its existence is what is without any mind ever attempting to correspond to it.

    I disagree. We come to know what is objective through reasoning and observance. We intuit that there is stuff which exists without us trying to think about them and that is what is objective.

    Once any attempt at correspondence is made, it is now subjective, or mind dependent

    No. The claim or statement is trying to express something objective. Of course, we only approach the limit of what objectively is out there; but that doesn’t mean that it doesn’t exist nor that we don’t have good reasons to believe it does. It is uncontroversial that we are subjects and everything we directly know is mind-dependent because that is the filter by which we come to know the objective things—this doesn’t mean that those objective things aren’t there.

    "An object exists independently and we can come to know that object truthfully".

    This just begs the question by invoking “truthfully”; as truth is the correspondence of thought (subjectivity) with reality (objectivity).

    Likewise, a ‘fact’ is a ‘statement which is true’ or, more precisely, ‘a statement which is truth-apt (i.e., a proposition) which corresponds appropriately with reality’. — Bob Ross

    Therefore, we can refine P2 to mean:
    Moral facts are judgements that a particular state of reality is preferable over another possible state of reality, and that these judgements are true.

    Moral facticity is not just what you described there. If a fact is a statement that corresponds to reality such that what it purports thereof is and ‘moral’ language signifies ‘what is permissible, omissible, or obligatory’, then a moral fact is a statement which accurately purports a state-of-affairs about reality that in virtue of which makes the moral judgment true (and thusly a fact). This means that there are states-of-affairs, if there are moral facts, that do inform us how reality ought to be, which violates P1.

    As is, P2 is merely a definition without an assertion of its truth or falsity.

    P2 is a description of what a ‘moral fact’ is based off of my correspondence theory of truth and my analysis of what ‘moral’ language signifies. To disagree with it is to disagree with one or both of those theories which are prerequisites to my metaethical theory. We can certainly discuss those if you would like!

    If I had to guess what you were originally going for, I think you were neglecting potential states as part of the moral consideration and simply noting that reality at any time/state could not indicate what it should be in the next state

    A potential state of reality in the sense of what could possibly happen due to the current state does not inform us of what ought to be either. You could tell me “this ball will probably hit this other ball” and I would not know from that claim anything normative, although I would know something about the next potential state of reality.

    Likewise, you telling me “well, this could happen and if combine with what is happening then this should happen” and I don’t think that is valid: I cannot infer from something possibly happening nor what is happening what ought to happen.

    But perhaps the above is irrelevant if we look at your next argument.
    1. Moral judgments are propositional [moral cognitivism]; and
    2. Moral judgments express something subjective [moral non-objectivism]; and
    3. There is at least one true moral judgment [moral non-nihilism]. — Bob Ross

    Just for clarification, this is not an argument I gave—it is a thesis. The arguments for those three prongs of the thesis are different and after this portion of the OP.

    Lets translate this into simpler terms:
    1. Moral judgements are made by subjects (minds)
    2. Moral judgements are expressions of subjects.
    3. At least one moral judgement corresponds with reality.

    #1 here is not a summary of prong-1 (of the thesis). Prong-1 is moral cognitivism, which is the view that moral judgments are truth-apt statements (i.e., propositions) and not that moral judgments are made by subjects.

    #2 is also false. Moral judgments expressing something subjective is not the same thing as judgments being expressions of subjects. Again, this is a conflation between statements and judgments being subjective and whether or not they express something objective/subjective.

    #3 True! (:

    The problem is this isn't anything meaningful. I can replace "moral judgements" with the word statements, and statements meaning "Any thought, word, belief, or expression".

    Each prong is meaningful because it takes a stance on each relevance metaethical dilemma:

    1. Are moral judgments propositional? i.e., are they truth-apt? Moral non-cognitivists, like emotivists, will say no...they are conative aspects of our psychology.

    2. Are moral judgments expressing something objective? i.e., if there are true moral judgments, then are they true because they correspond to a mind-dependent or mind-independent state-of-affairs?

    3. Is there at least one true moral judgment? i.e., do any moral judgments we make, even if they express something objective or subjective, actually correspond to a state-of-affairs in reality? Moral nihilists say no. They say that, yes, moral judgments express something objective but none of them are true.

    Of course, we haven't actually proved number 3 with our setup.

    Again, my thesis isn’t an argument. The arguments for each prong are titles with that prong number and the name that was in brackets.

    As we can see, all this argument notes is that we can think say or do things, and maybe they correspond with reality. This indicates nothing that should be done.

    It indicates what moral properties subsist in or of and what their nature is. Of course it doesn’t indicate what should be done, because it isn’t a normative ethical theory. That’s what I was trying to convey in the other thread! Metaethical theories should not be conflated with normative theories!

    It does not indicate any criteria as to what defines morality

    Depends on what you mean. It certainly answers what the nature of morality is and what moral properties subsist in or of and answers various metatethical concerns underpinning normative ethics.
    Is what "should" be done central to the individual, or is there something universal we can all agree on with logic?

    Is there a logic that we must all rationally agree upon which leads to a morality everyone can logically ascertain?

    This is a false dilemma. Logic is just the form of an argument, and the logic involved in any substantive and sophisticated metaethical theory is going to be sound. Something being logically consistent does not make it something one should believe.

    I agree, for example, that the logic is sound with moral non-naturalism; but that doesn’t make the theory true.

    1. Moral cognitivism is the idea that there are true moral judgments.

    But, you then attempt to prove that there is at least one moral judgement that is true. And if that is the case we can replace point 3 with that true statement and the argument will work.

    No. Moral cognitivism is that moral judgments are statements that are truth-apt. Whether or not any of them are true needs a different argument because it is a different claim.

    1. Moral cognitivism is the idea that there are true moral judgments
    2. Assume moral cognitivism is false, that there are no moral judgements which are true.
    3. I have the moral statement: "When I am drunk, I shouldn't drive and instead call a taxi."
    4. Holding to point 2, this moral judgement is not true.
    5. But point 3 is true.
    C: Therefore moral cognitivism is true.

    The problem is point 5 has not been proven to be true

    That’s fine, the point was to provide a basic syllogism that gives an argument for why one would be a moral cognitivism. At the end of the day, this is going to boil down to intuitions. It seems to be very clear that P2 is true, but of course you could deny that. It seems perfectly logically valid: I see nothing wrong with it with respect to its logical form; but if moral cognitivism is true then there has to be something wrong with its logical form because it is non-propositional.

    But if there are no true moral judgements, then we don't have to consider that there is anything morally permissible. There is nothing to permit or deny. Meaning my objection still holds.

    I think you are trying to step outside of morality, but I say that action implicitly concedes that morality exists. You cannot go and eat a sandwich without implicitly, in action, conceding it is morally permissible to do. You can say “morality doesn’t exist”, but your actions do not match your words.

    Alright, a rather long one from me! I'm still off for the holidays so I have time on my hands. I'm enjoying the exploration Bob, keep at it!

    As always, great points! I always enjoy our conversations!

    Bob
  • A Measurable Morality


    Bob, this has nothing to do with the argument. I'm not conflating anything. When the author is not using vocabulary that you then introduce, then you say the author is not meeting the standards of that vocabulary you have introduced, you are committing a straw man fallacy. I am not using metaethical or normative claims in the argument.

    With all due respect, you are though! It doesn’t matter what terms you call them. At the end of the day you are claiming that “morality is objective” without providing any justification for it; or the justification you have given doesn’t prove it is objective, because it has nothing to do with that metaethical claim.

    For the clarity of the conversation, lets us also understand 'subjective' in the normative view, not your own interpretation. Meaning a subjective moralist would be one who believes that what is moral is based on one's personal benefit, or even collective subjective culture

    My biggest quibble here is just that you are claiming, on one end, to not be making metaethical claims and then, on the other, making metaethical claims in the next breath. When I point out how you haven’t provide any basis for those metaethical claims, you say I am straw-manning your position because you don’t use the term ‘metaethical’.

    The meaning of subjective is absolutely not used in the sense of ‘one who believes that what is moral is based on one’s personal benefit, or even collective subjective culture’: this is a clear misapprehension of the literature. The claim that morality is ‘subjective’ is a metaethical claim, and your definition of was a normative claim: again, conflating them. A person who believes that what is moral is based on one’s personal benefit is a moral egoist—which may or may not be grounded in a moral subjectivist view or not. Likewise, a person who believes that what is moral is based on societies benefit is not necessarily a moral subjectivist, that could be also a moral realist or a different anti-realist theory.

    "Does objective morality exist?" If you say no, then of course we're left with either subjective morality or existential nihilism.

    Again, you say I am straw-manning you, and then explicitly invoke the central metaethical prong (#2) that I referenced before. You are assuming moral realism is true without giving any justification for it.

    Also, moral anti-realism does not leave us with either moral subjectivism or moral nihilism: there’s also moral non-cognitivism.

    The argument is not proving that objective morality exists. Its simply proving that all moral questions boil down to this binary, and proving what objective morality must be if it does exist

    What’s the proof for the underlined portion? That’s a metaethical claim.

    To enter the discussion, you do not have to agree that objective morality exists, you simply have to assume it does. If it does, what logically would it be, and how would it build? So going forward in this discussion, simply assume objective morality exists. We really can't continue to discuss until that happens. Don't worry, it doesn't mean you agree with it personally, we're just exploring the logical consequences if this is the case.

    I am more than happy to grant that your view demonstrates the three prongs of the moral realist thesis and seeing where that goes. Let’s just move on, because I don’t think we are making any headway in the metaethical sphere here.

    My argument is that within a binary argument in which one option must be false while the other is true, proving one option as false necessarily makes the other true. If an objective morality exists, then this is the binary we are left with.

    That’s fine, and this goes back to my syllogism:

    P1: Either ‘something should be’ or ‘nothing should be’ is true, but not both.
    P2: ‘nothing should be’ is false.
    C: TF, ‘something should be’.

    What is your syllogistic argument for P2?

    My point here is not to argue that there is an objective morality or argue against a subjective morality. Its taking an objective morality as assumed, then logically piecing together what that would be if true. Go with that and I think we'll have some fun exploring this Bob.

    I am more than happy to just grant moral realism for the sake of the conversation, but this seems backwards to me. If you haven’t even attempted to justify moral realism then it makes no sense to me why your position would move on to normative ethics. Why assume moral realism is true? Or are you just saying I should for the sake of the conversation?

    It is a choice between moral nihilism and moral objectivity.

    Again, forgive me, but I have to stress this point: you are making a metaethical claim here and then saying that you aren’t; and this is just a plain misrepresentation of the literature in metaethics. The options are not ‘moral objectivity’ or ‘moral nihilism’. You haven’t even, as of yet, recognized moral non-cogntivism as a valid position within moral anti-realist positions.

    I believe that subjective morality also descends into moral nihilism, but lets not have that discussion here. I think we're having that discussion in another of your threads.

    Fair enough. I do think, though, that it counts against your theory that it does not at least cite what moral realist account it is making. I have no problem with assuming it for the sake of normative ethics.

    If we need to revisit at some point whether we need to see if a subjective morality can exist as a viable alternative, I will gladly revisit it. Its just out of the scope of the argument at this time and not what I really want to explore at this time.

    Fair enough, but I just would like to note that moral subjectivism is not a contender or a normative ethical theory. Every argument you have given is can be made compatible with moral subjectivism just as much as moral naturalism/non-naturalism and moral non-cognitivism. My moral subjectivism thread does not offer a normative ethical theory: it is strictly laying out a metaethical theory.

    Anyways, to move forward, I will ask: what is your argument for P2? Or is that argument I gave not what you were getting at with your depiction of it as 'binary'?
  • A Case for Moral Subjectivism


    Sorry, I didn’t get a notification of this response!

    After reading I think this all comes down to the terms subjective and objective. Now that I've seen your definition, its necessary they be included in your 'pre-requisites' section

    This is already in the OP under ‘Brief Exposition of a Correspondence Theory of Truth’, which, I would say, is where it should be:

    ‘Objectivity’ is ‘that which exists mind(stance)-independently’ and ‘subjectivity’ is the negation of objectivity.

    The only quibble I have with myself is technically I need to change ‘subjectivity’ to ‘that which exists mind(stance)-dependently’ and not a negation of objectivity, because I consider certain things emergent from both which are certainly not just one or the other. So I will modify that part.

    If you do not define them specifically, then people are going to assume they are the traditional definitions of subjective and objective. The argument won't go anywhere because they'll think you mean the normative terms, not your revisions.

    As is, your statements about subjective and objective veer wildly from their original intent.

    I think you are assuming that Wiki is the standard of how people use the terms—I don’t. People in colloquial speech use those terms very ambiguously and inconsistently. In metaethics, I don’t think my definitions are very controversial granted a correspondence theory of truth.

    Can you clarify what the (stance) means as well?

    A stance is a disposition, attitude, belief, preference, etc. that a subject has formulated.

    Even further, this begs the question that your definition of subjective and objective are true. Why do we need to redefine these terms?

    Honestly, I don’t think I am redefining them outside of the norm in metaethics, and I do not grant that people use them in any precise manner at all in colloquial speech. However, I am not all that interested in derailing into semantics, so if someone, at the end of the day, affirms my moral subjectivism while stipulating that I use the term ‘subjective’ weird, then I am fine with that.

    This would be a widely misinterpreted argument to give to others if you've deviated strongly from the terms' original meaning without very carefully clarifying what you mean.

    The misinterpretation lies in the ambiguity and inconsistency of their deployments in colloquial speech: my definitions are highly refined (or at least so I think (; ).

    An object can make no objective or subjective judgements. Only a subject can. The reason we have the terms objective and subjective are to give meaning to the judgements a subject makes.

    You are saying the same thing I am saying, but less refined. I say there is no such thing as an objective statement because all statements are subjective, you are merely predicating that subjective statement with ‘objective’ if it is true in virtue of corresponding to some mind-independently existing state-of-affairs.

    The reason we have the terms objective and subjective are to give meaning to the judgements a subject makes

    Correct. But the judgment is not objective, which is what it would technically mean when you say “there are objective judgments”. What I think you are actually conveying is that judgments are subjective and they can either express something objective or subjective themselves; and this is perfectly compatible and precisely conveyed with my terminology.

    When you state the term objective means "that which is mind independent", what is 'that'? Is it existence?

    A state-of-affairs in reality to be specific, which are ‘arrangements’ of existent entities: I do not tie ‘state-of-affair’ to temporal or spatial relations only. I can also modify that in the OP as well.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    I see your line of thinking, but I think we could justify going to war under deontology which would preclude any justification for torturing a child to save us all.

    Just as an example, a deontologist that believes that one does not have the duty to uphold the rights of a person who is engaged in the violation of other peoples' rights, which is usually called a principle of forfeiture, will have no problem going to war with people that have forfeited those rights. However, that innocent child has not done anything warranting forfeiture of their rights, and we would actually be the one forfeiting our rights by violating the child's.

    This is the danger I see with consequentialism, is it gets people sucked into the view that 'the greater good is best' and blurs the lines of what a 'right' even is anymore and whether we actually have any.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    I genuinely have no clue what you are talking about: you are upset that I added in the question that is the essence of the OP? Both are very clear questions, and have nothing to do with justifying moral nihilism, so I don't see why you would have a problem answering them.
  • A Measurable Morality


    I appreciate your 1-13 points, although I disagree with most of them, but to focus on the most core issue I have with it I am going to write out only the relevant parts in a syllogism. You are, in its most abstract, arguing:

    P1: Either ‘something should be’ or ‘nothing should be’ is true, but not both.
    P2: ‘nothing should be’ is false.
    C: TF, ‘something should be’.

    Why P2 and P1 are true is irrelevant to my point, as I can grant those: this argument has no metaethical claims in it. I am almost certain now that you are conflating normative judgments with metaethical judgments.

    You provide an argument, that I am granting each premise as true, for why ‘something should be’ which is a normative claim and then tacking on without justification that metaethically this claim is a moral fact. To demonstrate this clearly, I can accept the argument shown above and that moral subjectivism is true because it is a metaethical thesis and has nothing to do with normative ethics.

    I would say, if I accepted this as a moral subjectivist, that the shorthand ‘something should be’ and ‘nothing should be’ are both moral statements which express something subjective and when evaluated relative to myself I do believe that ‘something should be’ and do not believe ‘nothing should be’. Now, you are claiming, on top of C being true, that ‘something should be’ is or is grounded in a moral fact: what justification do you have for that claim? The reason I think you are conflating normative judgments with metaethical ones is because every time I ask this question you give the above argument (more or less) which is a normative argument.

    I don’t agree with most of your 13 points, but for now I would like to stay focused on the above because the other disputes don’t matter if we can’t make headway on the above. So, I am going to skip over the parts of your responses, for now, that don’t address this central issue for the sake of brevity and to keep up on track. Then, we can move on to the other stuff.

    It is not subjective because it is necessary to avoid a contradiction in the question of morality, and necessary for morality to exist.

    This is a metaethical claim, and what justification or argument do you have for it? Avoiding contradictions, as a normative judgment, is not necessarily a judgment that expresses something objective. For example, by contrast to my view, I accept that ‘one ought to abide by the law of noncontradiction’ but I reject that that judgment is expressing something objective. So you would have to argue a case for why you think that it is expressing something objective: that is the crucial prong-2 of the moral realist’s thesis (that I reject).

    Yes, the moral property is, "There should be existence"

    That is not a moral property: it is a moral (normative) judgment. Moral properties include ‘goodness’, ‘rightness’, ‘wrongness’, ‘shouldness’, ‘badness’, etc. Asserting ‘there should be existence’ just indicates that it is better for something to existence than to not; and does not mention what the moral property of ‘shouldness’ or ‘betterness’ subsist in or of, which is a metaethical question. I can affirm, as a moral subjectivist, that ‘there should be existence’ and reject that that judgment expresses something objective without being incoherent. You have to provide an argument for why I should accept not ‘there should be existence’ but that that moral judgment is expressing something objective.

    A. Morality exists
    B. Morality does not exist

    This is too vague: what do you mean by ‘morality exists’? That there is at least one true moral judgment? That moral judgments are propositional? That they express something objective?

    I had concluded this long ago, and it suddenly came back to me. This is 'the choice'. Do you decide that morality exists, or not? If not, then we are done

    This seems like your argument collapsed into moral non-objectivism: if the truth of a moral judgment is contingent on my choice, then it is certainly not expressing something objective. However, if you are just noting that moral nihilism is incompatible with your view; well, then, you still have to give an argument for why there is at least one true moral judgment: it is not a valid defense to say “we are [just] done”.

    I look forward to your response!

    Bob
  • A Case for Moral Subjectivism


    Hello Bob, I'm happy to explore morality with you on multiple fronts here, as its a very deep topic and requires a lot of consideration from all possible sides.

    I always enjoy our conversations and look forward to your take on my OP!

    I think I need to provide some clarity on my position:

    1. By ‘objective’, I mean ‘that which exists mind(stance)-independently’; and by ‘subjective’, I mean ‘exists mind(stance)-dependently’.

    2. I do not think truth is objective nor subjective but, rather, absolute and emergent from both subjectivity and objectivity. Here’s my thread on that. More on this later.

    3. My correspondence theory of truth, which can be summarized as ‘truth is correspondence of thought with reality’, requires both a subject and object; otherwise, one would have to concede that thoughts can originate from non-subjects and reality is not objective.

    With that out of the way, let me try to adequately respond to your points.

    In very simple terms, this doesn't work because you forgot the possibility of different states of reality.

    I don’t think comparing potential states of affairs (of reality) helps get around P1. P1 is the claim that it doesn’t matter what is the case about reality at all when it comes to what ought to be: what ought to be is despite what is. If someone says “yes, that’s true, but potential states of affairs do relate to what ought to be”, then I think that is perfectly compatible with P1 but affords no moral facticity: (mind-independent) potential states-of-affairs cannot be what a moral statement corresponds to such that it is true because they don’t exist. If the person insists that moral facts are grounded in potential states-of-affairs, then the real premise in contention is P2, not P1.

    "Something is subjective if it is dependent on a mind (biases, perception, emotions, opinions, imagination, or conscious experience).

    Something is objective if it can be confirmed independent of a mind."

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Subjectivity_and_objectivity_(philosophy)

    I think these are fairly uncontroversial and straight forward definitions, so lets start here.

    More or less I would agree to these terms (notwithstanding the definitions I gave above), but I would quibble with “can be confirmed” part of the definition of ‘objectivity’: that makes it sound like we can confirm things that are completely sans any subject. I would just say that objectivity is that which exists mind(stance)-independently and we come to know it subjectively because we are subjects—what tool can we use that isn’t ultimately contingent on us observing it?

    Now, is truth subjective, or objective?

    Neither. It is absolute; meaning that any proposition one has, it is either true or false and that proposition is not true relative to a subject.

    If there is a true moral judgement, then it must be an objective moral judgement.

    No. I think you are conflating a moral judgment with what it expresses. Moral judgments are always subjective, irregardless of whether one is a moral realist or anti-realist. This is because judgments are formulated by subjects—they aren’t floating out there mind-independently in reality. Prong-2 of my thesis and the thesis of moral realism is aimed at ‘what does those moral judgments express?’. Are those moral judgments true in virtue of corresponding to some mind(stance)-independent state-of-affairs in reality? Or are they true in virtue of corresponding to some mind(stance)-dependent state-of-affairs in reality (such as our psychologies)?

    A moral judgment being true just means that some state-of-affairs in reality corresponds with it such that it makes the judgment true—but this could be just a fact about one’s psychology, which is just a projection of one’s own psyche: it is a stance-dependent state-of-affairs.

    "If a claim is true exclusively when considering the claim from the viewpoint of a sentient being, it is subjectively true. For example, one person may consider the weather to be pleasantly warm, and another person may consider the same weather to be too hot; both views are subjective. The word subjectivity comes from subject in a philosophical sense, meaning an individual who possesses unique conscious experiences, such as perspectives, feelings, beliefs, and desires, or who (consciously) acts upon or wields power over some other entity (an object).

    If a claim is true even when considering it outside the viewpoint of a sentient being (how ?), then it is labelled objectively true. Scientific objectivity is practicing science while intentionally reducing partiality, biases, or external influences. Moral objectivity is the concept of moral or ethical codes being compared to one another through a set of universal facts or a universal perspective and not through differing conflicting perspectives. Journalistic objectivity is the reporting of facts and news with minimal personal bias or in an impartial or politically neutral manner."

    I would just say that something is subjective if it exists mind(stance)-dependently and objective if it exists mind(stance)-independently.

    Lets examine the idea of 'subjective truth'. Person A states, "Its hot" while person B states, "Its cool". From their perspectives, this is true. But how is it true? How is it 'in correspondence with reality" if we've claimed truth is objective?

    If someone claims something “is hot” and another claims that other something “is cool” then either (1) they need to be more precise with what they are claiming and they both are right (e.g., when I say “it is hot” I really mean the proposition “it feels hot to me” which certainly can be true, given truth is absolute, while another person claims it is false since ‘me’ is indexical) or (2) one of them is wrong:

    Its because we've left out the implicit information within their statements.

    Person A: From my subjective experience, I feel its hot.
    Person B: From my subjective experience, I feel its cold.

    Exactly!

    Bob Ross: From my subjective viewpoint, I believe moral judgements are based on psychology, therefore all moral judgements are based on psychology.

    As we can see, this is a subjective claim, and not objective.

    I am not claiming that it is subjectively true that “moral judgments are the upshot of one’s psychology”, that is a true proposition and it is absolute.

    Also, in the claim “I believe moral judgments are based on psychology”, the belief does not itself make it true that “moral judgments are based on psychology” so I agree that it could be true that I believe it and it is false. This is not the case with moral judgments: I believe one ought not torture babies is the cognitive attitude (or disposition) which makes it true because it is just an upshot of my psychology. For example, by analogy, “I believe chocolate ice cream is the best ice cream flavor” is true (relative to me, but absolute statement because it refers an indexical pronoun ‘I’) in virtue of me believing it (as an upshot of my pyschology) which is very different than “I believe that 1+1 = 2” since “1 + 1 = 2” is not true in virtue of my cognitive disposition.

    Your own definition of truth counters this statement. Your definition of truth indicated no necessity that a person have knowledge or justification of something being true. A true moral judgement simply needs to be in correspondence with reality. The only thing you can state with your definition of truth is:

    "For there to be true moral judgments, is just to say that our moral judgement corresponds to reality."

    By ‘good reasons’ I was referring to our epistemic access to ‘true moral judgments’ and not referencing truth. I was saying to epistemically claim there are true moral judgments, we must have good reasons to believe that there are true moral judgments, and I don’t see anything wrong with that.

    P1: If there are no true moral judgments, then one would have to ‘lie down and starve to death’. — Bob Ross

    This statement is a contradiction. If there are no moral judgements, then there is nothing one has to do. Therefore one would not have to 'lie down and starve to death'.

    Not quite. I was claiming that doing something entails at a minimum the concession that it is morally permissible; so if one can’t even agree that it is permissible to do X, then they can’t do X because they don’t affirm that it is permissible. I think you would have to contend with the collapse of morals into actions to say that one can do something even if they don’t find it morally permissible.

    P1: If there are true moral judgments and they are not an expression of something objective, then they must be an expression of something subjective. — Bob Ross

    Except that if something is true, it is in correspondence with reality objectively. The subjective knowledge or lack of knowledge is irrelevant. Therefore if there are true moral judgements, then they are objective.

    Again, I think you are conflating moral judgments with what they express. I am talking about what makes the moral judgment true: obviously, it is a state-of-affairs in reality, but are those state-of-affairs mind(stance)-independent? If they are preferences we have, then they aren’t and are thusly true in virtue of something subjective. It corresponding to reality is going to be an absolute calculation: either it does or it doesn’t, and this is not contingent on what I or you believe; but the state-of-affairs that it corresponds to certainly can be something projected by our psyches. E.g., “I believe ice cream tastes so good” is true in virtue of facts about my pyschology, which are subjective judgments themselves.
  • A Measurable Morality


    Thank you for your patience Bob. I'm back from vacation!

    Absolutely no worries! I hope you had a good vacation!

    Goodness is simply material existence and its expressions. It has nothing to do with culture, intention, emotions, and would be whether humanity had opinions about it or not.

    Thank you for the clarification: I think I understand your claim better now. Unfortunately, I don’t see why goodness is reducible to ‘material existence and its expressions’: I don’t see why that would be the case at all. Let me see if I can elaborate on that.

    It is the end result we come to when we ask the question, "Why should X exist?" This is because it all reduces to the ultimate question of "Why should anything exist?"

    I would like to point out that the answer to this is subjective (by my lights) and if it isn’t then I would need to know how you know that moral properties subsist in something mind-independent and what that is. I think you are claiming that the moral properties subsist in ‘existence’ itself, but what justification do you have for that? It is a normative question to ask “why should anything exist?” and the answer is a normative claim, and if it is a moral fact that justifies the normative claim, then there is a fact out there about some mind-independent state-of-affairs that in virtue of which makes it true that ‘yes’ ‘something should exist’--I don’t see what fact you are exactly pointing to that would justify this...however, I think perhaps it is this:

    This leads us with the binary of existence, or non-existence. I cannot justify non-existence as what should be without there being existence to make the justification. I cannot justify existence without there being existence to make the justification.

    I think this is the underpinning of your reasoning for saying that it is a moral fact that ‘there should be something existing’. My quarrel is primarily with:

    I cannot justify non-existence as what should be without there being existence to make the justification.

    Two problems I see with this:

    1. It is entirely possible to affirm that ‘nothing should exist’ without presupposing that anything exists, and I am not sure why you think this is false. Saying ‘nothing should exist’ entails that there shouldn’t be anything, and this certainly does not presuppose anything existing.

    2. Even if, for the sake of argument, one could not affirm ‘nothing should exist’ without presupposing something exists, this doesn’t entail that one should affirm that ‘something should exist’: there’s a hidden normative premise that you are not explicating. For example, you would have to argue along these lines if you put it into a valid syllogism:

    P1: One should abide by the law of noncontradiction.
    P2: Affirming ‘nothing should exist’ entails a contradiction.
    C: TF, one should not affirm ‘nothing should exist’.

    From there, you could then use the law of excluded middle to affirm that ‘something should exist’. Notice that the normative conclusion (C) is grounded in P1 and not P2, which is another normative claim. Why is P1 expressing something objective (that is also normative)? If it isn’t, then ‘nothing should exist’ would have to be morally factually false; otherwise, you are just using moral judgments which express something subjective to ground your claim that there are moral judgments which express something objective. By my lights, both ‘nothing should exist’ and P1 are expressing something subjective. Once explicated in this manner, it is clear (at least to me) that you haven’t demonstrate any sort of normative statement which expresses something objective (even if I grant your argument). Just because we cannot claim “nothing should exist” without accepting a contradiction it does not follow that there are any moral properties which are reducible to existence nor that any exist (mind-independently) at all.

    This is why I was asking you to write your argument for ‘existence is good’ in a form of a syllogism, because I would be willing to bet it doesn’t have any normative facts in it (; Of course I could be wrong though.

    If it helps to see where we are going, simply see if you can justify that non-existence is preferable to no existence at all. If you cannot, then what I've stated is the only alternative, and what we have to build on.

    I don’t think this is good epistemology: if you have two exhaustive options, A and B, and A cannot be justified as true, then it is not justified thereby to affirm B as true. B needs support for why it should be regarded as true or A needs to be demonstrated as false.

    So, my first point, is that if I couldn’t justify ‘non-existence is good’ to you, it would not entail any support for your thesis that ‘existence is good’. From my perspective, I would say that ‘existent being good’ is subjective, so it could be good to one person and not good to another and they both would be right.

    Moreover, I could just makeup a reason for saying that ‘non-existence is good’--e.g., it ends suffering, I just like the sound of it, etc.--and even if it was a convincing reason it wouldn’t explain whether or not the property of goodness is reducible to ‘non-existence’. I think you may be conflating metaethical judgments with normative judgments: the former is an analysis of the properties of morality and the latter is an assessment of what meets those standards. If I argued, let’s just say, ‘successfully’ and convince you that ‘non-existence is good’ that would be a normative claim we both agree on, but it would still be an open question whether or not that normative judgment expresses something objective (i.e., the metaethical claim is still open-ended).

    I think it may be best if you give me a syllogism for your argument that ‘existence is good’ in the sense that ‘goodness’ itself is reducible to it, and then I can give a much more precise elaboration on what I am talking about here as it specifically relates to your theory.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    Absolutely yes. We torture our and kill our food every day for our own survival.

    The intent to torture an animal is wrong, even if we end up eating it. We can kill and eat animals in ways that give them basic respect, which would involve not unnecessarily torturing them.

    I torture bugs beneath my feet that I accidently step on in the grass and leave them to slowly die from a crushed exoskeleton.

    That is fair; but the intent to crush and torture a bug with no good reason behind it is wrong. Likewise, I don’t think it is analogous to the OP because we were not talking about a bug: it is a human child.

    Does that mean I stop walking? No.

    Imagine that in order to walk on that sidewalk, instead of crushing a bug, you had to brutally pummel and crush a human child: I think now the answer is an emphatic YES. You can’t really compare a bug or even eating pigs/cows to perpetually torturing a human being.

    We throw pollution up into the air that kills thousands of animals and even people every year. Many don't die, but simply become perpetually sick. Yet this pollution saves hundreds of thousands more from death and suffering.

    Yes, human society turns a blind eye to a lot of things: I don’t see why we couldn’t pollute (to some extent) without getting people sick—there has to be a way to do it that isn’t killing people. However, this also isn’t very analogous to the OP: what if you were thinking about opening a factory that you knew would kill 1,000 people a year from the pollution, do you think that’s permissible to do? Does it depend on how many people you think will be saved from whatever you are manufacturing?
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    I just don't have enough fleshed out yet, I am working on it and will share when it is substantive enough.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    I would be interested in seeing you work this out

    Once I have it fleshed out, I will create a new discussion—just like my moral subjectivism discussion board. For now, I am just inquiring other peoples’ views and contemplating them.

    Myself, I think consequentialism is the answer. But, a consequentialism that takes injustice into account. You can't just examine raw outcomes, you have to also consider injustices that have been brought about. So, the 99% who live marginally better at the expense of the 1% would not be a good consequence, as the injustice done to the 1% would outweigh the benefit to the 99%.

    I would be inclined to weigh injustice very highly. But, not so highly that the injustice done to the boy outweighs the deaths of everyone else, which themselves would be terrible injustices. I think the active/passive distinction is ultimately illusory, a choice is a choice.

    It just seems wrong to be to violate someone’s rights to save other people, like in the 1 to 5 trolley example. However, depending on how you factor in ‘injustice’ I may be able to get on board.

    For example, what if a doctor has 100,000 super sick patients that are going to die insufferable deaths and the doctor knows that abducting, killing, and harvesting the organs of one innocent, healthy person (to transplant parts to the 100,000) would definitely save those sick patients: should they do it? To me, it doesn’t matter how many sick patients there are: it is wrong to abduct, kill, and harvest the organs of that one person—period.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    Instead, what if we modify the original example. You don't have to kill or torture the child. Just, slap him around for 10 minutes or so. He will cry, and will probably suffer a bit of long term trauma. Either commit this active violation of the child, or passively allow everyone on earth to die. Which do you choose?

    Prima facie, I would say slap him around, but, I am inclined to say no because this is how torturing people gets justified: where is the line we are drawing here? Can I slap him? Yes. Can I punch him? How many times? Can I just cut a bit of his flesh off? Is that too far?

    Perhaps the answer is yes to slapping him, and it is just intuited from considering the balance between other people and the rights of that particular person. To me, I am starting to think there is no equation possible that accurately calculates right and wrong for every possible situation; and that's why I am trying to work on a virtue ethical theory instead. Maybe if we have the proper virtues instilled in our characters, then we would intuit that slapping him for 10 minutes is the right thing to do, but punching him for 10 minutes is taking it too far. Not sure yet, but that is a good thought experiment!
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    I didn't know that: interesting. Can you please elaborate?
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    People as a means to an end? We find it permissible to hire people as a means to an end which is making our own living as much as they make their own living by doing business with us, and some may find morally permissible even to do business over currently illegal jobs like prostitution, selling organs, dealing drugs.

    That is fair. I think deontologists usually mean it in the sense of their rights, and they don’t consider those to be rights we have. So “we cannot use a person as a means to an end” is short-hand for ‘you cannot violate their rights, whatever they may be’.

    How about living creatures, animals? Can you torture and kill animals as a means to people’s end? One might obviously argue that we already do this, we eat animals after all, and the food industry from start to end is a torturing experience for animals. So what makes human beings so special?

    This is the main reason I reject Kantian ethics. I don’t think humans are all that special, and I think persons are objects of respect, which includes animals (or at least the vast majority of them). I just think it is permissible to kill them (as painlessly as possible and treated prior to death with respect) for the sake of our own health.

    Why am I not blameworthy for the annihilation of the remaining human species, exactly? My choice to sacrifice the remaining human species as a means to save a child would still break the rule “do not sacrifice any life to save another for whatever reason in all possible scenarios”.
    There is no room for distinguishing choice abstention from choosing to sacrifice (not to mention that even abstentions are often perceived as morally blameworthy).

    You are not blameworthy because the reason they will all die is out of your control and is there prior to your decision: you killing the child is an intervention to try and prevent the annihilation of the human species. You did not actively violate anyones rights by refusing to kill the child.

    By analogy, imagine a pyschopath serial killer walks up to you, shows you sufficient evidence that they are torturing 12 people in their basement, tells you if you stab an innocent person that is walking by they will let the 12 people go, and let’s say you know 100% they are telling the truth (so they will actually let them go if you stab that innocent person to death) and everything else is equal (so forget about calling the cops). Can you stab that innnocent person to save the 12? I say no. You are not blameworthy for what is happening to those 12 people: the serial killer is. You are, however, blameworthy if you stab that innocent person to death.

    I’m reluctant to accept the distinction between consequentialism and deontology because I’m not sure to find it intelligible.

    Analyzing consequences of actions or having duties to rules does not make one a consequentialist or deontologist respectively: the kernel of the view has to center around such.

    Scenario 1: We may save either mother or baby during a difficult delivery, but not both. Yet we know the kid has developed a torturing and deadly disease which will make it die any time soon after birth, should we let the mother die so we are not blameworthy to kill the baby?

    This is a good thought experiment: the deontologist route would be yes. We cannot violate that kid’s right to exist because we anticipate it to die (or actually know with 100% certainty it will) shortly thereafter. A person is someone which we cannot violate (in terms of their rights). I see how this seems, though, like the right answer is kill the kid.

    I would say that since I know in this scenario that the kid is going to die that I would go the consequentialist route, or at least my intuition leads me that way, but in practical life where I don’t know it for certain I would say we cannot violate that person’s rights because we don’t actually know 100% they will die. Of course, that isn’t relevant to the thought experiment you said.

    - Scenario 2: We may save either mother or kid, but not both, and if we do not intervene they both will die. Killing a mother/baby even to save the other is immoral, so we let both die but we wouldn’t be blameworthy for it?

    This is also a good example. I would say kill one of them...so consequences win on this one.

    You can at least draft arguments for why people must follow what you claim to be “moral rules”, can’t you?

    I am still working on my normative ethics, and originally was going down the deontologist route; but I am now working on a virtue ethics account. I don’t want to share that yet because it is too premature.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    Interesting: I am leaning towards a virtue ethical theory myself. I just always thought Aristotelian ethics was a form of moral realism.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    Rephrasing my question in terms of your quoted appraisal: Of what ethical good is intending to keep one's established duties if so doing produces unethical results?

    You can’t control the consequences of one’s actions but, rather, only one’s intentions. Sure, if I am negligent in my reasoning and some bad consequent becomes of it, then I may be punished for it; but the point of deontology is that analyzing the consequences of an action doesn’t relate to whether anything is good or bad: if you have a duty to not violate a person’s rights, then what does it matter what consequences one calculates in relation to violating a person’s rights to save another? It doesn’t. You just can’t do it: period.

    I see your point though: shouldn’t we at least analyze the reasonable consequences of our actions? Isn’t it negligent to just focus on intentions? I sort of agree, but I don’t think the deontologist is against using consequences to make inform decisions, they just disagree with determining what is good from it. I can determine that if I perform action X it will most likely result in saving this person’s life and since I have a duty to uphold their sanctity, then I should do it. Notice that the consequence just informs the intention, but this is not the case in consequentialism.

    The maintaining of duties within a community of slave-holders and slaves resulting in the lynching of those slaves that don't uphold said duties

    I don’t see how this is a critique of deontology. It is perhaps a contention with a deontological theory that I haven’t heard of, but deontology in general is not contended with here in your example (as far as I can tell). Most deontologists don’t think we have a duty to just anything.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    Suppose a good friend comes over, whom you know to be a strict Kantian. The Gestapo know this as well, and question him regularly. He notices a yarmulke inexplicitly lying on the couch. "Is someone staying here?" he blurts.

    I completely agree that Kantianism is counter-intuitive; but I was wondering about deontology in general. On this specific point, I think a deontologists, and even a neo-Kantian, can circumvent this example by appealing to ‘rights forfeiture’.

    You are taking a relaxing day off, fishing in your rowboat. Around a river bend, you come upon a drowning man. "Oh, thank God!", he cries. "Save me!"

    "Sorry, friend!", you respond with a grin. "I didn't push you in, I'm afraid it's not my problem. But, best of luck!"

    His final moments before submerging for the last time are spent watching you in astonishment as you row your boat down the river, whistling gaily.

    Are you
    a) As morally culpable as if you had pushed him in the river?
    b) Less morally culpable than if you had pushed him in the river?
    c) Not culpable at all?

    I choose A.

    I like this. My intuition is that at least B is true. I am not advocating that a person should not save someone when it is of little cost to themselves on the grounds of ‘letting it happen’ entails no culpability. I am saying that if I had to throw you over board (knowing you will drown) to free up a life vest that would save them for this other person, then I cannot violate you to save them. I am not culpable like the person who pushed that person into the water knowing they would drown: I didn’t violate their rights. Perhaps me morally blaming me for going by instead of saving them at little cost to myself is contradictory to the ‘letting’ vs ‘actively participating in’ the violation of a person...not sure.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    Consequentialism comes in a very wide variety of forms: from “the proof is in the pudding” type mentality that can be used as evidence that might makes right (with its associated potential atrocities) to notions such as that of karma (which at base is about cause and consequence).

    True, and they all have to contend with similar issues like this thought experiment in the OP.

    Of what good is deontology if it doesn’t produce good results, i.e. good consequences? If no satisfactory answer can be given to this question other than that of affirming it to be good on account of its good consequences, then deontology (as can then be likewise said of virtue ethics and so forth) will itself be a form of consequentialism broadly defined.

    Deontology is exactly not consequentialism: if a deontologist cites the consequences as the kernel of why they thought something was moral/immoral, then they are not a deontologist. Good is measured in deontology by intentions towards one’s duties and not the consequences they bring about. Consequences can help inform deontological decisions, but they are not what makes something good or bad.

    At this juncture, I’ll simply object to its supposition of necessity

    This is not a valid response: it is not a false dilemma—that is why it is a thought experiment. If I say “hypothetical if you had to choose A or B, which would you choose?” and you answer “neither, because I don’t have to choose A or B” then you have misunderstood the nature of hypothetical scenarios.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    Would you lie to the Gestapo about Jews hiding in your house?

    Yes, because they have forfeited their right to be told the truth by actively engaging in the violation of other peoples’ rights: I don’t see how this is incompatible with deontology, although certainly incompatible with Kantianism (or at least its original formulation).

    But what of the rights of everyone else? Are you not maximally violating the rights of every person on earth, by making the decision to preserve the child?

    I would say no. There’s a difference between violating someone’s rights (which requires active participation therein) and letting someone’s rights get violated (which is an inactive, passive, allowing of it to happen). In the latter, one is not morally blameworthy; whereas in the former they are.

    If my child is about to get run over by a car and I save them by pushing you in the way, then I have actively participated in the violation of your rights, and are blameworthy for that violation. If I let my child get run over because the only way would have been to push you in the way but I refrained, then I am not, all else being equal, morally blameworthy for my child getting run over: it is the drunk driver, or what not, that is presumably at fault (all else being equal). No one would say “why didn’t you sacrifice that other person by shoving them in the way to save your child?”.

    Same with not killing the child to stop the immanent death of all people: I am not blameworthy for whatever event is going to wipeout the human population—I am not killing everyone—but I am at fault if I kill that child.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    Neither deontology nor consequentialism seem to fully match our intuitions, since you can construct cases where either violate them. An approach that somehow combines both would probably be needed. I think I lean towards consequentialism, while acknowledging there are cases it cannot account for.

    Interesting. What problems can you construct for deontology? I lean much more towards that than consequentialism.

    In unnatural situations like this one, which our intuitions weren't designed for, things are bound to fall apart.

    It isn’t that unnatural, and that’s why “The One’s Who Walk Away from Omelas” is such a good, quick read. Enslaving 1% of the population would increase the well-being of the 99% (if we presuppose specifically utilitarianism), wouldn’t it? Etc.

    My own intuition says, torture the child, since it doesn't really distinguish between that and killing them. Would you agree to kill the child?

    Nope. Seems like we shouldn’t violate that child’s rights to me.

    Why a child? What if it were middle aged, or elderly?

    Good idea: what about 99 year old man that you know is going to die tomorrow anyways? I still say nah.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    I would suggest reading it yourself: there's free PDFs online and it is only like 5 pages (if I remember correctly).
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    Even if you meant that in at least one scenario the child would be safe, one may wonder: how would a child even live and evolve as a psychologically and biologically sound human being if the rest of humanity would be immediately annihilated?

    Fair question, but not the point of the thought experiment. It could be the case that no one is morally justified in sacrificing that child and that the child would have, if they were the sole survivor, no feasible living arrangement afterwards.

    Perhaps this factors into your moral reasoning though: to you, does that reason count in favor of potentially sacrificing the child? I don’t believe so.

    if we must choose, would it be permissible to have child X to be safe at the expense of the rest of the human species to be immediately annihilated?

    My answer would also be no. That child nor I can use other people as a means to and end, even if that end is saving other people. I cannot throw you into a moving car to stop it from running over my child.

    Because if neither killing/torturing a child is permissible even when the rest of humanity would be safe, nor having the rest of humanity safe at the expense of killing/torturing a child, and we must choose anyways (why exactly?)

    You have the choice to refrain from actively violating someone’s rights in both scenarios: what you don’t have control over is the predestined stipulations of the thought-experiment. You can say no and simply not be morally blameworthy for the annihilation of the human species (by my lights).

    what lesson do you wish to draw from this hypothetical predicament?

    Is consequentialist normative ethical theories valid in any scenario? That’s the question.

    I do wonder: what’s even the point of moral reasoning over thought experiments designed to fail in guiding choice and action exactly?

    To make our moral intuitions and principles consistent and coherent.

    let’s imagine that that child X whom nobody is permitted to sacrifice, is somebody who will soon develop a torturing mortal disease for natural causes and die atrociously even if the rest of the human species was immediately annihilated to save the child, or that the child a psychopathic which enjoys torturing living creatures before killing them for the rest of his life or a Hitler on steroids which will torture and exterminate the entire human species anyways and repeatedly if he only had the chance. What would be morally legitimate to do?

    I like it (: and I would say an emphatic NO, you cannot violate that child’s rights, period. Doesn’t make baby hitler right in doing atrocities later in life, but we cannot violate peoples rights period; especially over ‘forseeable’ consequences of their existence (which I find really unreliable, but that’s irrelevant to my main point).

    What if the lesson we draw from the thought experiment varies remarkably depending on how the thought experiment is construed?

    That is anticipated and good for working out one’s normative ethical theory. Afterall, there’s no way one will magically just know that their theory works as expected in applied ethics without putting in the work to test it.

    The problem is not much that there is a moral rule (where?!) that says “do not torture or kill any child ever for whatever reason” but more why would we be committed to such rule exactly? Saying because it is moral, it would shift the problem: how did this rule get the label “moral” in the first place? What is there in claiming “morality” that would me make me feel (?!) or taken (?!) to be committed to it or compelled BY DEFAULT and without consulting me first? And if it is not that what is implied, what else is exactly?

    Metaethically, I would say there aren’t any moral facts. With respect to normative ethics, I would say we must treat persons with respect as objects of intrinsic respect. Admittedly, I am still working out the details.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    I think you missed the point of the OP, it is not about would but should.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    I don't quite follow: doesn't Aristotle believe that the good is objective?
  • A Case for Moral Subjectivism


    I think the crux of our disagreement about beliefs and judgments is as follows. Let’s take the example of the proposition “Jane believes X” and call it Y.

    You seem to think that X is the judgment and Y is the belief; whereas, I am saying that Y in relation to X is a judgment about X: the belief and judgment are intertwined such that one cannot have one without the other.

    Likewise, you seem to be saying that Y does not entail truth about X, which is only true in the case that X is about something beyond out psychology. E.g.,:

    There is a crucially significant difference. From, "Jane believes X," one cannot infer anything about what is permissible, omissible, or obligatory; just as from, "Jane believes 28^28=33.13*10^39," one cannot infer anything about mathematics

    If X in “Jane believes X” was “vanilla ice cream tastes good”, then I don’t think you have a hard time seeing why your analogy to math fails. Some beliefs, which are also necessarily judgments, are not about facts out there in the world but, rather, are projections of our psychology. So I agree in the case of your math example, but disagree that it is analogous to morality because, well, that’s exactly what’s in contention in moral realism vs. anti-realism!

    Likewise, if you are saying that Y is a belief which is not a judgment but X is a belief that is a judgment, then we can validly expand “Jane believes X” to “Jane believes that Jane believes X” which is either redundant or, and this one I am more inclined towards, it is now just a second order belief (i.e., a belief about beliefs) which has nothing to do with X itself.

    Fair enough. I am limiting my involvement, arguing that C is false.

    That’s fair enough as well. I am more than happy to discuss why you believe C to be false and perhaps you will convince me.

    That’s fair. I actually edited this with my addition of an elaboration on how moral judgments express something that is subjective. — Bob Ross

    Hmm, okay...

    I was just noting that I adjusted it as I said I would, and just wanted to let you know that’s fixed now. However, does my refurbishment undermine my argument for moral cognitivism? I think probably for you, yes, and for me, not really (;

    This is equivocal. "I believe X" usually means, "I believe that X is true." You want it to mean, "I happen to hold belief X." You want it to be parallel to, "She believes X." But in the third-person case the ambiguity disappears, because there is no implication that the speaker (the "I") also believes/judges regarding X.

    I am not sure I followed this part, to be honest. I would say that “I believe X” is a belief state of the subject at hand, which is a judgment about X. When I say “I believe X” I am thereby judging that X is true...you seem to be saying that it is a belief that isn’t making a judgment but, rather, the judgment is in X.

    This goes back to that equivocation and I vs. She (and, in the first-person case, belief qua belief vs. belief qua judgment).

    I would say “I believe X” is a belief qua belief and qua judgment.
    A moral judgment is not a statement about belief, it is a statement about what is permissible, omissible, or obligatory. It makes no difference that a belief ends up being about what is moral.

    This would be true if I accepted moral realism. The belief is what makes the judgment true in moral subjectivism.

    For example, let’s go back to the “Jane believes ice cream tastes good”: does this belief not in virtue of its own judgment make it true? I think so. Sure, it is an upshot of also conative aspects of one’s pysche, but the belief also factors in.

    I can say, "She believes X," without myself believing X,

    That’s true and expected under moral subjectivism: ‘She believes X’ is indexical.

    The other thing to note is that to judge that (no)one ought torture babies, is to judge that everyone is bound to not-torture babies (and not merely myself).

    Yes, so this goes back to our dispute about subjective vs objective universalization: I find nothing incoherent with “Jane believes everyone should not torture babies” even though it is only true relative to herself—I would imagine you beg to differ on that one (;

    And so what is the subjective thing that a moral proposition expresses?

    Cognitive approval/disapproval, which is an upshot of other cognitive and conative aspects of one’s psyche.
  • A Normative Ethical Dilemma: The One's Who Walk Away from Omelas


    I agree. What normative ethical theory do you subscribe to? A form of deontology, perhaps virtue ethics?
  • A Case for Moral Subjectivism


    Yes, but more precisely than (2), "P2: There are true moral judgments and they are not an expression of something objective." It is precisely the non-objectivity that I am concerned with.

    It is entirely negative. It is a disjunctive syllogism, as noted above.

    My point is that rejecting A and B is insufficient when C is also implausible. C must be supported positively.

    Non-objectivity is subjectivity EDIT: (sort of); and I agree it is negative. However, my argument for moral judgments expressing something subjective is that (1) they are not expressing something objective (which was positively argued for) and (2) that there are true moral judgments (which was positively argued for): what else would be required, in terms of a positive argument, to affirm C?

    In other words, affirming prong-1 and prong-3 while disaffirming prong-2 of the moral realist thesis is moral subjectivism: this entails that moral judgments are expressing something subjective because they exist, some of them are true, and they aren’t expressing something objective. You would have to contend with that even if you think we have good reasons to also reject moral judgments as expressing something subjective.

    If I say either A, B, or C are true and A is false and B is false, then C must be true. If you turn around and say ‘I also think C is false’, then you are wrong about one of them being false. If you think C is false, then which of the other two do you think is true?

    In your OP, in the section, "A Case for Moral Cognitivism [Prong-1]," you state something quite different. You give a moral proposition about driving drunk and claim it is truth-apt. If we are to argue about this moral proposition then it must be objectively truth-apt.

    That’s fair. I actually edited this with my addition of an elaboration on how moral judgments express something that is subjective.

    This is not a moral proposition, but it is truth-apt and objectively true or false. Yet the subject of cognitivism (and binding morality) is moral propositions, not belief propositions.

    That’s the whole point of contention: moral subjectivism allows moral judgments to be beliefs.

    ‘I believe one ought not ...’ is the moral judgment under moral subjectivism and not ‘one ought not...’. It still meets my definition of ‘moral’ signification because it is still a subject-referencing normative statement which expresses ‘what one ought to find permissible, omissible, or obligatory’.

    According to your own OP, mere statements about someone's beliefs are not part of moral language.

    Where did I say that in the OP? I need to revise that if I did.

    No. As noted in your previous thread, I reject your exclusive distinction between what is moral and what is psychological. Beliefs are always psychological, as is the mathematical belief I set out in my last post. No one believes we have non-psychological beliefs.

    I am not saying that we have non-psychological beliefs, I am saying that moral judgments are not expressing something objective: the belief we have, which is always pyschological, is an upshot of our psychology (in general)...it is an upshot of other beliefs, intentions, desires, etc.

    The truth of a moral statement regards the truth of a moral judgment, and statements about belief are not moral statements. The statement, "Jane believes one should not torture babies," is not a moral statement, it is only a statement about what Jane believes. Jane's statement, "One should not torture babies," is a moral statement, because it pertains to what is "permissible, omissible, or obligatory."

    Hmmm…isn’t “Jane believes one should not torture babies” refer to what is ‘permissible, omissible, or obligatory’? Seems to be to me, even if it is just an expression of what jane subjectively believes.

    Note that if you claim that Jane's belief is "psychological" in the sense that it is grounded by one of her values, then the exact same question applies to that value. We must then ask if the value is truth-apt, and if so, if it is true or false. Only if the value is true can the moral statement be true (and therefore binding).

    In this sense of ‘value’ you are describing, I would say it is going to bottom out at something not truth-apt, although first and second principles (etc.) could be other beliefs and thusly truth-apt.

    Okay, good. Again, the key here is that preferences are not judgments and judgments are not preferences.

    Correct. Judgments are beliefs.

    The corollary is that truth-apt judgments cannot flow from non truth-apt preferences, unless the judgment is merely about the preference/belief (as explained above)

    I would say that it is the latter in my case, if I am understanding correctly. This is what I mean by the moral judgment (the belief) being an upshot of one’s pyschology and not a moral fact out there.

    Yet if it is merely about the preference/belief, then it cannot be moral in the sense you set out (pertaining to what is permissible, omissible, or obligatory).

    Why? “I believe one ought not ...” is expressing something pertaining to what one ought to hold as permissible, omissible, or obligatory, no?

    Statements about belief cannot be binding at all because they are not moral statements

    Moral judgments (which are beliefs about what one ought to be permissible, omissible, or obligatory under my view) are binding to the subject at hand. I can’t say “I believe one ought not torture babies” and then in the next breath say “but I don’t believe that it is impermissible to torture babies”: which one is it?

    And do you go on to say that the moral subjectivist believes that moral propositions express something subjective?

    Yes. I am not sure what the contention was here: perhaps I am misunderstanding you. So prong-2 of my thesis is that they express something subjective: a sentence expressing something non-objective is to express something subjective—they mean the same thing to me. Are you saying something could be non-objective and not subjective?...Actually, I see now: truth, under my view, would be an example of this (:

    Perhaps I could revise it to expound more on how moral judgments expressing something non-objective entails it is expressing something subjective. To me, it seems like it is impossible for a statement to express something that is non-objective and non-subjective: truth, on the other hand, is an emergent property, so to speak, of statements’ relationship to reality and is beyond those bounds.