You may claim that you have experience of something, but how do I know that something was not your fantasy, imagination or dreams?
The OP does not deny the existence of the world, but it is asking for the reasons for believing in the world's existence.
We are looking for more objective reasons than personal experience for the evidence i.e. you may claim that you have experienced something therefore that something must exit, but why should I trust that claim? The claim is lacking objectivity.
I think you are begging the question again, and, like in the past, you very much need to define what you mean by 'fact'. All of your arguments depend on your premise that there are no moral facts, and yet you never end up saying what you mean by a fact such that your statement could be reliably assessed.
I might be repeating @Banno here by Hume's Guillotine says one cannot logically derive (moral) norms from non-normative facts. The moral anti-realist assumes that 'normative facts do not exist', even though they do as evident in (e.g.) public health, medical & ecological sciences as well as institutional facts like money, traffic signs, marriage vows. The vast majority of considered facts are, in fact, theory/value-laden (i.e. normative), so Hume's Guillotine makes sense to me and 'moral anti-realism' does not.
If you assume that only statements about material things or sense data are facts, then of course you will conclude that moral statements are not facts. You will have done no more than reiterated your assumption.
So you are forced to deny what is blatantly evident, that these are indeed true statements, facts, simply to keep your ideology.
A moral realist might claim that the statement "one ought not harm another" is made true by the mind-independent fact that one ought not harm another (much like someone might claim that the statement "electrons are negatively charged particles" is made true by the mind-independent fact that electrons are negatively charged particles).
[P1] That one ought not kick puppies for fun is a moral statement.
[P2] It is a true statement that one ought not kick puppies for fun.
[P3] Facts are true statements.
[C] Therefore there are moral facts.
1. The moral nihilist will argue that no statements of this kind are true.
2. The moral anti-realist will argue that some statements of this kind are true and are made true by some mind-dependent feature of the world.
3. The moral realist will argue that some statements of this kind are true and are made true by some mind-independent feature of the world.
For experiencing something, you don't need the world. But you need a world.
There are many worlds that you can experience, but a world you experience doesn't have to be part of the world
They exist in totally different ways and in different forms, which have nothing or little to do with the physical world we live in
But before that, what is the definition of the world?
I use ‘world’ and ‘reality’ synonymously, and by both I mean ‘that which is the totality of existence’. However, this doesn’t semantically fit the discussion here: instead, we could just suppose that a ‘world’ is the totality of a locale of existences, one of which encompasses you. What exactly the boundaries are isn’t really important for proving there is at least one ‘world’.
With above points in mind, to experience a virtual world in a computer game
I don't think you need the world to have experience logically and epistemically
1. You ought make whatever the Godfather says should be true, true.
2. The godfather says “today is Tom’s last day on earth"
3. You ought make “today is Tom’s last day on earth" true.
4. You should kill Tom.
It is the context which allows us to determine the "ought" given a descriptive statement issued with confidence or from an authority in the present in refrence to the future.
…
Here is a case where we can derive an "ought" from an "is"
The usage of "ought" for general normative statements is correct, since Hume wasn't only concerned with moral statements.
I don't see a problem with using colloquial language. In the philosophy of language, we don't look for a perfect language anymore. All we do is explore how language works in real life, following the example of Wittgenstein, who reminded everyone to let philosophy leave everything as it is
Not just propositions, but true propositions. Here is 2 reasons we should prefer true propositions to be cognitive content over platonic forms
1. Platonic forms lack intentional content. There is no meaning to them in refrence to themselves. Platonic forms don't think they are true. We with our minds do.
Let's suppose true statements existed as Platonic forms, then we would only be able to access true statements by coming into contact with platonic forms, but our minds cannot contact them or comprehend them.
Mathematics isn't an estimation of the world. You are confusing physics with mathematics. Yes, numbers may represent apples and chairs, but it's ludicrous to conflate them.
Mathematical theorems rest on axioms and inferences our minds derive from them. That's it. The axioms are taken as self-evident, not some a posteriori fact about the world.
If you say your door is 2 meters long and "2" doesn't exist, then your statement is false.
But you do have a mind which can conceptualize "2", even if it's a rough approximation, so your statement is somewhat right
If you improved your instrument, you would get a better measurement, but it still depends on the existence of some number inside your head.
Now, look at physics. It describes the universe with numbers before any mind existed in the universe. Such a theory is wrong if there were no numbers, the theory can't even be approximately correct.
So there must have been some mind which comprehended mathematical numbers/concepts
As for numbers being platonic entities, refer to my objection above
Are you saying there are only finitely true mathematical statements because of that ?
1. True statements can only exist as cognitive content
2. Cognitive content depends on the existence of a mind which can comprehend it
3. There are infinitely many statements that are necessarily true, independent of spacetime itself
Reason 1 : How can our physical theories which describe our universe to a great degree of accuracy prior to the existence of any symbolic language be true if the mathematical entities they refer to or depend on constructions which never even existed ? Your physical theory is definitely false if its meaning and truth-falsity depends on something which is non-existent.
Reason 2 : Let's suppose mathematical statements are just symbols we draw with some rules. Given the fact our universe can only contain finite information, there can only be finite mathematical statements that are true, but this is false on face value ( There is no logical impossibility in adding additional axioms and theorems to the most comprehensive mathematical system )
I would like to see the logical and epistemic arguments laid out for the reason for believing in the existence of the world
Both the moral nihilist and non-cognitivist believe that ethical sentences cannot be true or false
And wouldn't this justify calling non-cognitivism a flavour of moral nihilism?
The error theorist is a cognitivist: maintaining that moral judgment consists of beliefs and assertions. However, the error theorist thinks that these beliefs and assertions are never true
One might deny that in making a moral judgment we are engaging in the assignment of properties at all. Such a rejection is, roughly speaking, the noncognitivist proposal
The main two arguments I have came across in favor of moral nihilism is that 1. moral thinking differs between cultures and people, so it is a subjective practice, and 2. that there is nothing tangible to attach moral facts too, therefore they do not exist.
I wouldn't say that morality has the same type of facts that the natural world has, meaning that if intelligent life didn't exist, neither would morality.
However, abstract human constructions often do have facts. For example, mathematics is a human construction with inherent facts. The infinite number of primes is an abstract fact of mathematics that has no basis outside of the intelligent mind. You could say that the way we describe a mathematical system is the reason that it can contain facts, meaning that since math as a language leaves little room for subjective interpretation of its findings means that it is an objective practice. However, I would say that is a fundamental problem with how we talk about morality rather than a stark difference between mathematics and morality.
I'm not going to argue with you about Nietzsche's view and the fact that he's already considered that and written about it. If the morality of customs (which moral facts) leads to the autonomous non-moral being as its ripest fruit of that process -- I would say that implies what your saying -- but not limiting it to "only beneficial to non moral facts" because the moral fact would indeed be beneficial for its own factual existence as its own proof there of basically, and it's that tension of morality that teaches the individual how to guarantee themselves as a future. It's like a "strange loop" that self references.
Transcendental arguments are not intended for empirical conditions, so, no, there wouldn’t be one. No need to argue for that which gives you a bloody nose, or a headache, or hurts your eyes if you look at it too long
There isn’t a proof. Remember….we’re not even conscious of this part of the system as a whole. The transcendental argument sets the technical groundwork, nonetheless, as the first part of the work.
No. Like….how is it called a cup-in-itself.