Thus this God can have, on this construction, no fixed aspect at all, and since everything that exists in reality has some fixed aspect, it must be that God does not exist in reality. — tim wood
Further, it is adduced without proof that objects in reality are greater than objects of thought. Yet lots of things are clearly greater as objects of thought than as instantiated in reality. E.g., two, justice, love, The American Way, and even God himself. — tim wood
And finally, as a being conceived - in any way whatever - He must be conceived by a conceiver. And who might that be? It cannot be God. Me? You? Banno? We will all have different conceptions; does that mean different Gods? — tim wood
I see your point; but I am thinking that wouldn’t the ‘being alive’ be a result of those parts interacting with each other properly? Viz., if you give a dead person an organ transplant and get their neurons to start firing again and what not then wouldn’t they be alive? A part of the physical constitution of a thing is the process which is has (e.g., you can have an engine with all the parts in the right place and yet it isn’t burning fuel [i.e., on], but if you know how to start it up then it starts working properly). — Bob Ross
Here is Ed Feser discussing change: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Sl3uoCi9VjI starting at 25:15. — Bob Ross
Yes, but by ‘motion’ the medieval’s and pre-medieval’s meant any actualization of a potential and not locomotion. If you think about it, this would make sense; since for Aristotle (and Ed Feser) God keeps us in existing right now: they are not arguing merely for a being which started the locomotion at the beginning of the universe (or something like that). That would require this idea of a “hierarchical series” which is a per se series of composition which is analyzed in terms of what causes each thing to remain the same (e.g., Ed Feser likes to use the example of H20: the atoms that make up that molecule don’t themselves have any reason to be H2O—something else actualizes that and keeps it that way [and its the keeping it that way that seems to break the law of inertia]). — Bob Ross
Thus the soundness of the concept of a c-proposition depends on there being this structure to the thought of someone who uses a sentence to make an assertion: thinking it correct to use the sentence in the way that she does, she thinks that a c-proposition is true at the context in which she uses it. — ibid. page 30
Accordingly, linguistic expressions refer to what their users intend by them to refer to in a given context, that is, what they think of while using the expression either properly, or improperly.8 So referring was held to be a context-dependent property of terms: according to this view, the same expression in different propositional contexts may refer to different things, or refer to something in one context, while refer to nothing in another. — Gyula Klima, St. Anselm's Proof
The question becomes, on what basis does that "structure of thought" involve verification from what is presumed to exist outside of it. At that point, I do not see it as a matter of how "Pat" or "Quenton" choose what is happening. — Paine
A general point to note: within the premodern metaphysical vision, particularly in Neoplatonism and Christian theology, being was understood as a form of plenitude—what the ancients called the Pleroma, the 'fullness of being'. From this perspective, being is not a neutral or arbitrary descriptor, but an expression of fullness, goodness, and actuality, compared to which non-existence or non-being is a privation or deficiency. — Wayfarer
(3) any thought object that can be thought to exist in reality can be thought to be greater than any thought object that is only in the intellect — Gyula Klima, St. Anselm's Proof - Section 2
Also worth noting that for the medievals, arguments for God’s existence were devotional as much as polemical — Wayfarer
The ontological argument, in this context, is not merely a logical proof but an intellectual prayer — Wayfarer
So I'll set aside Leon's endless requests to repeat myself and take the criticism of (1) as read. — Banno
He defines god as the greatest thing that can be thought of, and there is no guarantee that there is any such thing. — Banno
But if the thought of god is not coherent, then (2) collapses. — Banno
(3). ∀x∀y(I(x)∧R(y)→M(y,x))
This says that for any x and any y, where x is in the intellect but y is real, y can be thought greater than x. This requires some attention, because it is mainly here that the presumption that god exists slips in. It's sitting there in plain sight, in that we have it that from (1) that there is a greatest thing, and here the presumption that that greatest thing is real. — Banno
Even if we admit (1), why shouldn't we just suppose that the greatest thing can be conceived of, but not be real? Why could it not be the case that the greatest thing can be imagined, and yet might not exist? — Banno
But before starting, am I to understand you have no problems with it? — tim wood
Then this thought object cannot be quantified in any way, for to be quantified entails that another, greater, can be thought. And this here is fatal. Need we go on? — tim wood
What a prat. — Banno
Your animosity towards me leads you to simply gainsay my every point. — Banno
But as it seems the thread was also about Anselm's proof, I opted in. — tim wood
Its focal point is St. Anselm’s famous proof for God’s existence, although that proof is not what the paper is ultimately centered on. — Leontiskos
God, it appears, is by Anselm reckoned as that than which & etc. And that seems a matter of definition and presupposition - thus not proved. — tim wood
By the meaning of the term,
(1) God is the thought object than which no thought object can be thought to be greater
Now suppose that
(2) God is only in the intellect (i.e. God is thought of, but does not exist)
But certainly
(3) any thought object that can be thought to exist in reality can be thought to be greater than any thought object that is only in the intellect
And it cannot be doubted that
(4) God can be thought to exist in reality
Therefore,
(5) Some thought object can be thought to be greater than the thought object than which no thought object can be thought to be greater [1,2,3,4]
which is a contradiction, whence we have to abandon our supposition that God is only in the intellect, so he has to exist in reality, too. — Gyula Klima, St. Anselm's Proof - Section 2
That's an example of ampliation, where we use natural numbers to reach beyond themselves. — Banno
He defines god as the greatest thing that can be thought of, and there is no guarantee that there is any such thing. — Banno
g:=ix¬(∃y)M(y,x) does not work becasue there might simply always be some y such that y is greater than x. — Banno
But Leon, this is not a candidate for the greatest number. That's the point. It's the first (defined by "min") of a whole new sequence of numbers greater than any natural number.
Similarly, no sooner do you think of a being greater than any other, than you can think of a being greater than that individual. The series need have no end. — Banno
And you misrepresent my saying that the parsing of his argument, the formatting, was ugly as my saying that the argument was ugly. — Banno
He is specifically advocating not becoming involved in the sort of discussion now occurring here, that the parties 'should not seek sheer “winning” in a debate'. — Banno
But that it was essentially the same conception of reference that was at work in his mind when he formulated his arguments in the Proslogion is clearly shown by his insistence against Gaunilo that his crucial description “that than which nothing greater can be thought of” is in no way to be equated with “greater than everything”. It is precisely the ampliative force, recognized as such by 12th-century logicians, that is missing from the latter, and is missed from it, though not described as such, by Saint Anselm in his response to Gaunilo’s objection. — Gyula Klima, St. Anselm's Proof - Section 1
ω:=min{x∣x is an ordinal and ∀n∈N,n<x} — Banno
Will someone be good enough to provide as an aid to navigation a simple proposition expressing exactly what they think Anselm proves? — tim wood
And the same service for Gyula Klima's paper? — tim wood
And so far I am only looking at premise (1), no further. We can go on when this bit has been understood. — Banno
One of the points I made is that Klima does not make use of the "ampliation" in (1), and he ought. — Banno
Yep. Concepts that contradict themselves. Like "The largest number". — Banno
So you want me to flesh out your concept of god for you. — Banno
Gaunilo of Marmoutier took this approach by positing an "island greater than which none can be conceived," in order to try to show that Anselm's argument can be used to demonstrate the existence of all sorts of things. — Count Timothy von Icarus
But I think real problem for ontological arguments is that they are unconvincing. I don't think anyone has been converted by an ontological argument, or that many people of faith feel their faith significantly bolstered by such arguments. — Count Timothy von Icarus
The move from ens rationis to ens reale only works if we already accept that "existing in reality" is a necessary property of the greatest conceivable being. — Banno
So you can't just write g:=ix¬(∃y)M(y,x) without a problem, becasue it may be that there is no greatest individual. — Banno
But if you manage that, you have the analogue of the transfinite numbers - no sooner have you defined g as the greatest, and then you can bring to mind something greater than g, and the problem repeats itself.
So even as there is good reason to think that it is not possible to make sense of "the largest number", it is difficult to see how to make sense of "the greatest individual". — Banno
IF the argument is valid, and it shows that something exists, then that must be assumed in the argument somewhere. That's how logic works. The problem isn’t just that the argument assumes its conclusion, since as Tim pointed out all valid deductive arguments do that. — Banno
(Some of my own philosophical arguments have been accused of something very like ‘begging the question’ – I concede the phrase was not used – simply because they were formally valid arguments for a conclusion the accusers thought was false. Their reasoning seems to have been something like this: if the conclusion of an argument can be formally deduced from its premises, then that conclusion is, as one might put it, logically contained in the premises – and thus one who affirms those premises is assuming that the conclusion is true. As R. M. Chisholm once remarked when confronted with a similar criticism, ‘I stand accused of the fallacy of affirming the antecedent.’) — Peter van Inwagen, Begging the Question
The argument becomes "God exists therefore god exists". — Banno
I'm gonna Pontifications from 30,000 feet again. The generic flaw in ontological arguments is that if they are valid then they assume the conclusion somewhere in the argument. The task for the logician is to find out where.
They must do this because existence cannot result from a deduction. It can only be presumed, either in the argument or in the interpretation. — Banno
To be sure, it is not clear that the definition g:=ix¬(∃y)M(y,x) can be made coherently... — Banno
...it is not clear that [it] can be made coherently... — Banno
The generic flaw in ontological arguments is that if they are valid then they assume the conclusion somewhere in the argument. — Banno
I was wrong about the paper. Sorry for being so stubborn and impatient, and for unnecessarily derailing the thread. — Banno
g:=ix¬(∃y)M(y,x) — Banno
I did fix the ugly: g:=ix¬(∃y)M(y,x). I asked you if it was acceptable, and did not yet get a reply. — Banno
The generic flaw in ontological arguments is that if they are valid then they assume the conclusion somewhere int he argument. — Banno
So the argument will not be of much use in convincing non-theists. — Banno
No. Kids will ask wha the highest number is. Takes them a while to see that there isn't one. — Banno
Notice that the existence (as a thought) of such an individual is here just assumed. — Banno
What a mess. So god is not the thing greater than everything, but the thing greater than the thing greater than everything. — Banno
Might be. — Banno
What? Those are the symbols in the HTML text you linked. — Banno
($y) — Banno
Consider an analogous argument defining the highest number as that number which is higher than any other number. The definition is fine, except that there is no such highest number. — Banno
Damn, that's ugly. — Banno
followed the guidelines — Banno
In what way? — bongo fury
Not necessarily, but the claim wants explaining. What is meant to be wrong with the slogan, and what has the doctrine of quantifiers being second order predicates got to do with it? — bongo fury
6 W.V.O. Quine: “On What There Is”, in: Quine, W.V.O. 1971. p. 3. By the way, it is interesting that Quine apparently never asked himself: to whom does the name “Wyman” refer? — nobody? — then how do I know that Wyman is not the same as McX? For despite the fact that nothing in the world “wymanizes”, let alone “mcxizes”, Wyman and McX are quite distinguishable imaginary characters in Quine’s paper: Wyman, e.g., is introduced to us as a “subtler mind”, than McX. As we shall see, these questions are easily answerable on the basis of the theory of reference advanced in this paper. Not so on the basis of Quine’s. — Gyula Klima, St. Anselm's Proof - Section 1
The three dogs are you, me, and the pooch. — Moliere
I'd call you a sly dog in order to demonstrate that "dog"'s referrent isn't fixed by convention — Moliere
Right: the (conventional) association between Truman and 'Truman' is already "affixed" before the true sentence is uttered. — Leontiskos
but it's not like conventions make reference factual — Moliere
What I take from this is that it doesn't need to be one or the other, verbal communication can contain information about and reference both things and the speaker's intentions about things. — Count Timothy von Icarus
But if the alignment of determinate intentions is possible, then I think there is a strong sense in which reference must be. — Count Timothy von Icarus
To even make the inscrutability argument, one has to assume that determinate intentions exist, so that one is given, but then it obviously seems possible to communicate them as well. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Hell, even poorly trained dogs can communicate well enough to direct our attention to what they view as a threat. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Quine, as a nominalist, would rather not encourage any similar assumption about a predicate. — bongo fury
Consider now Quine's insight, on which the quantifier account is based, that it is bound variables rather than singular terms that carry ontological commitment. To implement this insight, Quine simply eliminated singular terms from the language. — Ontological Commitment | SEP
[Russell's] account, coupled with the Kantian-Fregean idea of existence as a second-order predicate, i.e., a quantifier, quite naturally leads to Quine’s slogan: “to be is to be a value of a bound variable”.[2] — Gyula Klima, St. Anselm's Proof - Section 1
With this understanding of Anselm’s conception of the relationship between existence and reference we can see that his argument constitutes a valid proof of God’s existence without committing him either to an ontology overpopulated with entities of dubious status or to the question-begging assumption that the referent of his description exists. In fact, we can see this even within the framework of standard quantification theory, provided we keep in mind that in the context of Anselm’s argument, this context being an ampliative context, we should interpret our variables as ranging over objects of thought, only some of which are objects simpliciter. — Gyula Klima, St. Anselm's Proof: A Problem of Reference, Intentional Identity and Mutual Understanding - Section 2
Though supposing we were in this room and there were three dogs — Moliere
"There are no fixed referents," vs, "We could be wrong some of the time." Do you see how the latter does not justify the former? — Leontiskos
Presumably we all agree that words signify by convention ("nomina significant ad placitum").
So then a token like J-o-h-n will be indeterminate if there is more than one person named John (or if our interlocutor knows more than one person named John).
If that is all that is meant by inscrutability of reference then it strikes me as trivial. — Leontiskos
But I won't be defending this at any length as an alternative. — Banno
Try to make it past the first sentence before finding an offending whole two words that "render the paper obsolete." — Count Timothy von Icarus
I will make a thread that includes the topic of intentional reference/identity sometime in at least the next month. It will be a reading group, so trolling will not be tolerated. — Leontiskos
First, even if one supposes that Klima, being a medieval specialist, absolutely cannot be well acquainted with modern philosophy of language (dubious) — Count Timothy von Icarus
The relentless grind of progress, eh. Philosophical ideas certainly have short use-by dates in our day and age. — Wayfarer
Why? I'm not making McDowell's argument. If you think he has a case, then you can make it. — Banno
The "Need" McDowel sees to "distinguish the experience" suggests a profound misapprehension of Davidson's much more subtle argument. — Banno
According to this conception, in an appropriate ampliative context we can successfully refer to what we can think of according to the proper meaning of the terms involved. But thinking of something does not imply the existence of what is thought of. Thus, in the same way, referring to something does not imply the existence of what is referred to, or, as the medievals put it, significare (‘to signify’) and supponere (‘to refer’) ampliate their object-terms to nonexistents in the same way as intelligere (‘to think’, ‘to understand’) and other verbs signifying mental acts do.[14] — Gyula Klima, St. Anselm's Proof: A Problem of Reference, Intentional Identity and Mutual Understanding - Section 1
(1) Bucephalus is dead
(2) What is dead does not exist
Therefore,
(3) Bucephalus does not exist
Therefore,
(4) something does not exist
In my opinion, this is a conclusive argument for the thesis that something does not exist. As is well-known, however, many philosophers regard this thesis as paradoxical in a way, and, consequently, they would raise several objections to the simple reasoning that led to it above... — Klima | Existence, Quantification and the Medieval Theory of Ampliation
And the premise you stated [...] is arguably false, and clearly designed for the purpose of that refutation. It looks like a very clear cut example of begging the question to me. — Metaphysician Undercover
That's how arguments work. You design premises to reach a conclusion. — Leontiskos
(Some of my own philosophical arguments have been accused of something very like ‘begging the question’ – I concede the phrase was not used – simply because they were formally valid arguments for a conclusion the accusers thought was false. Their reasoning seems to have been something like this: if the conclusion of an argument can be formally deduced from its premises, then that conclusion is, as one might put it, logically contained in the premises – and thus one who affirms those premises is assuming that the conclusion is true. As R. M. Chisholm once remarked when confronted with a similar criticism, ‘I stand accused of the fallacy of affirming the antecedent.’) — Peter van Inwagen, Begging the Question