I merely said that we disvalue death because it can cut short potentially good experiences. Personally, I don't think that it has any positive/negative value (aside from the process). I did not ignore anything you had said, but I apologise if I did so accidentally. — DA671
I am not talking about why people disvalue death. That's a sociological question, not a philosophical one.
Our reason tells us to avoid death under most circumstances. That implies it is harmful, yes?
The deprivation account is demonstrably false. If it was true, then death would not be a harm if your life is drab or if you are in agony and death is the only escape. The death is still a harm in those circumstances, is it not? It is the lesser of two evils. But the lesser of two evils is still an evil. So, the deprivation account is false. It does not matter that many people 'think' it is true. So what? Have they thought about it carefully, as I have? No. Have they noticed that if the deprivation account is true, then death is good, not bad, when it is visited on those whose lives are slightly drab or on those whose lives are agony. No.
So, the deprivation account is false.
Whether or not we have a "reason" (in the sense of something being preferable for us) to avoid death depends on the framework one has. — DA671
No it doesn't. That's like thinking that whether the world is spherical or flat depends on your framework. No it doesn't. It depends on what shape it is.
Christians think they're going to heaven when they die. Do you think that means they are? Is that all one needs to do? If you think it, it will be so? Have you not noticed that this is not at all how the world works?
You also mischaracterize what a 'reason' is. A reason is not a personal preference. A reason to do something is known as a 'normative reason'. Our personal preferences can inform what we have reason to do - if I really want to do x, then probably that will generate a reason for me to do it - but a reason to do something is not made of our personal preferences. Tom has a reason not to kill Jane even if he really wants to, yes? Well, if 'reason to' just meant 'prefers to' then that would make no sense. But Tom has a reason not to kill Jane even if he wants to - so clearly reasons to do things are not made of our own preferences and talk of reasons to do things is not just a convoluted way of talking about what we prefer to do.
Let's say you wake up one morning and you happen to want to kill yourself. Does that mean you now do have reason to kill yourself? That, magically, it is now rational for you to kill yourself? No, obviously not. It would depend. If you wanted to kill yourself with such intensity that frustrating that desire would mean the rest of your life here would be a torment, then - perhaps - you might now have reason to kill yourself. But just having a passing desire to kill yourself does not entail that one has reason to kill oneself. So reasons to do things are not a disguised way of talking about our preferences, even though our preferences can inform what we have reason to do.
We have reason to avoid death. The evidence for that? The reason of virtually everyone says so.
That's the evidence that 2 + 3 = 5. The reason of virtually everyone represents 2 + 3 = 5. It is the evidence that this argument is valid:
1. If P, then Q
2. P
3. Therefore Q
The reason of virtually everyone represents it to be valid.
And so on. All appeals to evidence are appeals to reason.
And the reason of virtually everyone represents us to have reason to avoid death in all but the most extreme circumstances.
That does not mean that we do have reason to avoid death in all but the most extreme circumstances, but it is overwhelmingly good evidence that we do and the burden of proof is squarely on the person who would insist that we have no reason to avoid death in the main. And if all they can do in the way of defence is appeal to some bonkers worldview that has nothing to be said for it apart from taht it was believed by vikings or americans, then they have not discharged the burden.
Now, if our reason represents death to be something we have reason to avoid and only relents when our situation has become characterized by intense suffering, doesn't this imply that death is a harm, and a very serious one?
Typically, if we have reason not to do something it is because a) doing it will harm us, or b) because doing it will harm someone else, or c) because doing it is intrinsically immoral.
Which plausibly applies to our reason not to die? Well, not b, for my reason represents me to have reason not to die even when my death would not affect anyone else. So it is only plausibly a or c. I think c is fairly implausible as we generally do not have moral obligations to ourselves, but only to others. If I smack you in the face, that's wrong; but if I smack myself in the face, that's just stupid, but not immoral. Yet if I have reason to avoid death even when my death would not affect others, then if that's a moral reason it'd express an obligation to myself. Plus, in the unlikely event that I really do have a moral, rather than prudential, obligation not to kill myself, it would be because of the harm it would visit upon me. And so really 'a' seems to be the most plausible explanation of why we have reason not to kill ourselves and to avoid death.
So, we have overwhelming evidence that we have reason to avoid death in all but the most extreme circumstances, and we have good evidence that this is because death will harm us.
And we know that the deprivation account of the harm of death is false.
So, it harms us becasue it does something to us - it harms us because it alters our condition, not because it deprives us of anything.
1. The badness of dying (which isn't the exact same as being dead) is about experience. — DA671
Irrelevant, as my point is about death. Not the process of dying. Death. Death is a harm, as I have argued and as appears self-evident to the reason of most. Pointing out that other things related to death are also harmful only adds to my case, but does not challenge it.
The badness of death itself might only be about the loss of potential life. — DA671
No, that's the deprivation account again. And it is false.
I also think that you've made some hasty generalisations that aren't justifiable. "So-so" lives is a vague term that matters differently for different people. — DA671
By a so-so life I mean a life characterized by mild pleasures and pains and in which the balance of mild pleasure over pain is either slightly negative or even. If it was a company, it would be a company that was not turning a profit or was turning a slight loss and had no prospect of a profit in the future. If it was a company, a sensible business person would, other things being equal, close it down. But it is not a company, it is a life. And we have reason not to shut such lives down.
To extend the company metaphor, imagine that there is a huge company that is turning a slight loss, year on year. There is no prospect of it turning a profit - the accountants and analysts deliver the same verdict: this company is going to keep turning a slight loss. Yet its billionaire owner doesn't shut it down. Why? Well, what if closing it down would mean incurring huge redundancy pay-out costs? That is, it is losing $1m a year, but closing it would mean having to pay out $1billion in redundancy payments. Well, now it is in the billionaire's best financial interest to keep the company running, even though it is not making a profit. So, if a billionaire owns a giant company that keeps making a loss - and shows no prospect of making a profit - and yet the billionaire does not close it down, you can reasonably infer that something like the situation I just described is the case. That's the more sensible inference - more sensible than, say, inferring that the billionaire is stupid with money or just enjoys wasting it.
Our reason is the billionaire. It tells us to keep the company that is our life here going even when it is turning a slight loss and shows no prospect of turning a profit. What should we infer from that? We should infer that shutting our lives down will incur huge costs that far outweigh the costs we are incurring by keeping them going. That is, death is a harm of such magnitude that it eclipses all the harms we keep incurring by continuing living.