(3) The features of the object of knowing included in our judgments are those features adequate to our needs. — Srap Tasmaner
This isn't my conclusion. What I'm saying is that knowing only how reality relates to us (and not exhaustively as it is) is not a problem, because we only deal with reality in relation to ourselves.
What you tell them is, for their purposes, true, even though for other purposes what you are telling them may be false.
But this is not what (1) claimed. This is
(1') We are committed to the truth of some judgments we can prove are false. — Srap Tasmaner
That is not what I said, nor is it implied. Still, it has some merit.
What in (1) I am following Aristotle's observation that we cannot prove everything. So, we must accept some things as given. Reflecting, what we accept as given is what is given in experience.
Raw experience is infallible, because whatever we are aware of is what we are aware of. Still, there is a difference between being aware of something (knowledge by acquaintance) and making judgements. Since we are infallibly aware of whatever we are aware of, there is no question of its truth, but there is a question of the truth or falsity of judgements. That question derives from abstraction.
Universal concepts are derived from abstraction, but they may not be the result of abstraction alone, but also of construction -- combining associated data from different experiences. Concepts are universal because each of their instances is capable of evoking the same concept. But, it may be that the aspects (notes of intelligibility) one object that evoke a concept are not the same as the aspects of a different object that evokes the same concept. For example, we have may have seen Jane nude and know she is female, and Kathy made up and dressed in a skirt, and think she is also female. Perhaps, Kathy is a transvestite or transgendered, and biologically male. Then we have erred in judgement.
How did we err? Not by a mistake in awareness, but by miscategorizing -- by attributing to Kathy aspects we did not experience and she did not have.
We need to reflect on how we make experiential judgements and what justifies them. If the identical object that evokes the concept <tiger> also evokes the concept <sharp teeth>, I am justified in judging <the tiger has sharp teeth>. This is fully justified as long as my concepts do not carry the baggage of other experiences, but, almost invariably, they do. It is this associative baggage that is typical the source of false judgements.
It is, then, theoretically possible, but very difficult, to make reliable experiential judgements -- because the habit of association, while corrigible, is typically unconscious.
So, back to (1) and (1'): It is a fact that we can't prove everything. So, we have to commit to things we can't prove, but that does not mean that we can't analyze them and root out sources of error. Of course, we don't root out all our errors. So we wind up being committed to things that can be proven false. Still, there is hope. As social animals we can expose our assumptions to others with different life experiences and perspectives, and so root out further errors. One way of doing this is to value the reflections of previous generations enough to hear them.
Your claim is that there is no requirement to take into account the contexts in which the judgment is false; — Srap Tasmaner
I don't think I claimed that. If we're to be serious thinkers, we need to reflect on the limits of what we know.
we only think there is such a requirement because we imagine a context in which we have knowledge not relativized to our needs, "objective" knowledge, which would therefore be exhaustive. — Srap Tasmaner
And so, impossible for human beings. This is the error of making divine omniscience the paradigm against which we judge human knowing. All we need to do is be humble and admit, that while we know many things, we don't know everything about anything.
(iii) What we leave out are features of the object of knowledge irrelevant to our needs. — Srap Tasmaner
Not quite. What we actually leave out (in coming to know) is what does not interest us, and hope that what does interest us is adequate.
(iv*) Therefore if we leave out a feature of the object of knowledge, it must be a feature irrelevant to our needs. — Srap Tasmaner
No, which is why I did not accept your (iii). Still, this often happens in practice. Critical evidence or lines of reasoning may be ignored because we have "made up our minds" -- which means we have closed our minds.
What are you leaving out is that you know what you are telling your students to be false. — Srap Tasmaner
No, it is not false. That is the point. It is an adequate to what they will deal with. If you do measurements in the Newtonian regime and compare them to the equations, you will find no discrepancies. The scientific method will never give us absolute truth. It may, and often does, give us a theory that represents our observations adequately.
What we say is never exhaustive. Every discourse is limited. Even the most "objective" news stories include some facts and exclude others. If these inclusions and exclusions are made in good faith, we place no blame. Still, the story is (and has to be) intrinsically imperfect. So also is it with teaching, journal articles, books and so on. We will accept these imperfect discourses as true if they do not lead us into error -- if they are adequate to our needs.
what you are telling them is true "for all practical purposes"; it is an approximation, and will serve in the contexts in which they will make use of it. — Srap Tasmaner
That is the very nature of science. The so-called "theory of everything" (TOE) is a theory of everything but 96% of the stuff. Darwin's theory of evolution knew nothing of DNA transcription errors, toolkit genes or punctuated equilibrium. Our best understanding of quantum physics contradicts our best understanding of gravity. We accept these theories not because we think they are metaphysical truths, but because they provide adequate accounts of the aspects of reality we apply them to. That is why naturalists who treat them with religious reverence are so foolish.
(a) Because it will not matter to them that it is false, relative to their needs it is true. — Srap Tasmaner
Perhaps you are having difficulty because I haven't made it sufficiently clear that I don't see truth as a univocal concept. That is, "truth" does not mean the same thing in every context. Instead, "truth" is analogically predicated by an analogy of proportionality. What that means is that the requirements for being true are proportioned to the needs the truth is intended to meet. If we're doing metaphysics, we want it to be exceptionless, but if we're building a bridge, a set of reliable equations adequately modelling the conditions to be encountered are a true description -- in fact, one that
corresponds to the relevant domain of reality, even though it may not correspond to irrelevant domains.
The complete formulation would be "P is true in context C", or "P is true relative to needs N" or something like that. (b*) imagines there is truth relative to no particular needs, that there is (I can't resist) "needless truth" — Srap Tasmaner
I think this is close. I am not sure that there actually is "needless truth."
This sounds reasonable enough, but if we want eventually to come back to (b*) and define "truth (full stop)" as "truth relative to human needs", we will engage in further abstraction, but what will we compare humans to? Is abstraction enough to get you there, or will we compare humans to other animals, and then be forced to talk about the judgments of animals? — Srap Tasmaner
I think we are justifiably anthropocentric, because the problems we have to deal with are human problems -- not that we should not value other species. It is just that we can never know what it is like to be a bat.
Thank you for taking so much time reflecting on my post.