Summarizing that story, out of our fear of the other, — Antony Nickles
philosophy created an intellectual problem of doubt about them — Antony Nickles
when the skeptic is right that there is no fact of the other (or ourselves) to know that will resolve our worries. — Antony Nickles
But Wittgenstein sees that this truth is only because our relation to others (the mechanics of it, the grammar) is not through knowledge resolving our doubts about them, but that it is part of our situation as humans that we are separate, that our knowledge of the other is finite. But the implications of that are simply that the ordinary mechanics of our relation to others is not one of, here, knowing “their understanding”, but of accepting or rejecting them; that their otherness is at times a moral claim on us, to respond to them (or ignore them), to be someone for them. Thus “the urge to transcend the human”, in our ordinary lives, is to avoid exposing ourselves to the judgment of who we are in how we relate to others. In the case of understanding, by only wanting to treat what others say as information we simply need to get correct, rather than acknowledge their concerns and interests, and have ours be questioned. To put it that this is the “result of having language” is the picture of something like that what we say has a “meaning” that stands alone from who we will be judged to be in having said it, rather than it expressing us, allowing who we are to be read through it. — Antony Nickles
I think how I put this to Bano here might be a good start. — Antony Nickles
We actually are scared of the ever-present truth of our human condition: that we are separate, that there is no guarantee that we will work out our differences, or that our criteria will always be sufficient, or that we won’t be wrong even after working to (pre)determine what is right, that we might still be guilty (or lost) after following all the rules, etc. — Antony Nickles
109. [...] All explanation must disappear, and description alone must take its place. And this description gets its light — that is to say, its purpose — from the philosophical problems. These are, of course, not empirical problems; but they are solved through an insight into the workings of our language, and that in such a way that these workings are recognized — despite an urge to misunderstand them. The problems are solved, not by coming up with new discoveries, but by assembling what we have long been familiar with. Philosophy is a struggle against the bewitchment of our understanding by the resources of our language.
123. A philosophical problem has the form: “I don’t know my way about.”
133. We don’t want to refine or complete the system of rules for the use of our words in unheard-of ways. For the clarity that we are aiming at is indeed complete clarity. But this simply means that the philosophical problems should completely disappear.The real discovery is the one that enables me to break off philosophizing when I want to. — The one that gives philosophy peace, so that it is no longer tormented by questions which bring itself in question. — Instead, a method is now demonstrated by examples, and the series of examples can be broken off. —– Problems are solved (difficulties eliminated), not a single problem. — Wittgenstein, PI
Cavell cannot see that “Wittgenstein’s certainty logically dismisses scepticism.”(Ibid.) Now, nostalgia for metaphysics is supposed to be the desire to transcend the human. Cavell is trying to place that yearning in the weave of our lives, not indulging it. Disappointment with criteria is a function of how criteria do work, their dependence, in particular, on our attunement in judgments and agreement in form of life. It does not, then, feed an “ineluctable skepticism”, as though Cavell agrees with some skeptical conclusion about the failures of certainty. That is, 1) Cavell explicitly does not accept the thesis of skepticism, that we do not know the world or other minds with certainty. Our relation to the world is not one of knowing. The truth of skepticism is not the expression of “dissatisfaction with knowledge” from some metaphysical height; rather, it points to a feature of our condition of which, presumably, the urge to transcend the human is an expression. To go further, 2) “if the fact that we share, or have established, criteria is the condition under which we can think and communicate in language, then skepticism is a natural possibility of that condition; it reveals most perfectly the standing threat to thought and communication, that they are only human, nothing more than natural to us.”(CR, 47) — Minar's paper
Criteria bring out that the thesis of skepticism – which starts life as a claim about our intellectual or epistemological limitations – transmutes into the truth, which is (again) that “our relation to the world is not one of knowing, where knowing construes itself as being certain. So it is also true that we do not fail to know such things.” (CR, 45) — Minar's paper
4.2 Disappointment with criteria
The connection with Wittgenstein here is all but explicit:
If I am to have a native tongue, I have to accept what "my elders" say and do as consequential; and they have to accept, even have to applaud, what I say and do as what they say and do. We do not know in advance what the content of our mutual acceptance is, how far we may be in agreement. I do not know in advance how deep my agreement with myself is, how far responsibility for the language may run. — Minar's paper
Here Rhees underscores the importance of the kind of openness – openness that in some sense “threatens the possibility of understanding altogether”(Rhees, 13) – that I have suggested he associates with skepticism: “If language really were a technique, then…. there would be no connexion between philosophy and scepticism. You should not understand what was meant by the notion of the distrust of understanding.” — Minar's paper
Not propositional, but still conceptual.
— Luke
Does Hacker discuss Wittgenstein on what might be called conceptual seeing - seeing as, seeing aspects, seeing connections? — Fooloso4
There are other aspects of Wittgenstein's philosophy, such as seeing aspects, that are not propositional. — Fooloso4
The question in hand here is, what happens with the picture theory as Wittgenstein moves on to the Investigations?
Who can give a simple, direct answer to that? — Banno
This might be a good place to start. What quickly becomes evident is that his interpretation of Wittgenstein is grounded on the problems and analysis of propositions, as can be seen in such claims as:
It [philosophy] is concerned with plotting the bounds of sense.
(43)
What philosophy describes are the logical relations of implication, exclusion, compatibility, presupposition, point and purpose, role and function among propositions in which a
given problematic expression occurs. Philosophy describes the uses of expressions in our language for the purpose of resolving or dissolving conceptual entanglements.
(45) — Fooloso4
Philosophy is a struggle against the bewitchment of our understanding by the resources of our language. (PI 109)
What *we* do is to bring words back from their metaphysical to their everyday use. (PI 116)
119. The results of philosophy are the discovery of some piece of plain nonsense and the bumps that the understanding has got by running up against the limits of language.
The civic status of a contradiction, or its status in civic life — that is the philosophical problem. (PI 125) — Wittgenstein PI
There are other aspects of Wittgenstein's philosophy, such as seeing aspects, that are not propositional. — Fooloso4
It is here that we can see continuity between the Tractatus and his later work. It is also here that the limits of Hacker's interpretation of Wittgenstein can be seen. — Fooloso4
Is there an inexpensive way to see the writing upon a larger scale? — Paine
1. W. concludes this part of the discussion by pin‐pointing one deep aspect of the illusions that beset us here. We think of our mental images as pictures which only we can see, in fact as ‘super‐pictures’ which cannot be misinterpreted. For an ordinary picture, though it is a picture of X, may look like (and be wrongly taken to be) a picture of Y. But it is essential to a mental image of X that it is of X and nothing else. So it comes to seem like a super‐likness. Yet this is confused, for that the mental image of X is an image of X is not determined by its likeness to X. We are prone to think that it is a picture which needs no interpretation, so closely does it resemble what it is a picture of. It is true that it needs no interpretation and also that it makes no sense to suppose that I might be mistaken in my characterization of my mental image. But that is not because it looks more like its object than any picture. It is rather that it neither looks like nor fails to look like its object. It is not a picture at all. How does one know that one’s image is of X and not Y (which looks like X)? One does not know, nor can one be mistaken. One says so, without grounds, as one says what one means or what one thinks.
2. The relation between an image and what it is an image of is comparable not to the relation between a portrait and its subject (where the portrait may resemble someone or something else), but to the relation between an expectation and what fulfils it (BB 36), a thought (or proposition) and what makes it true (PG 161), or a possibility and what it is a possibility of (PI §194). It is not an image of X in virtue of a method of projection or in virtue of a similarity, let alone a ‘super‐likeness’. (Cf. LA 67.) — PMS Hacker, Wittgenstein: Meaning and Mind (Volume 3 of an Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations), Part 2: Exegesis, Section 243-427
My mental image of the Eiffel Tower need not be an image of the Eiffel Tower. — Fooloso4
Moreover, why suppose that a mental image is required in order to use the name "Eiffel Tower" correctly
— Luke
You seem to have lost track of the argument. It is not required. The question is whether the mental image must of the Eiffel Tower and nothing else. — Fooloso4
Why would you think I am suggesting that when I said the opposite? — Fooloso4
What object is being referred to at PI 389?
— Luke
According to the interlocutor (and you(?)), whatever object the mental image is of is what the object is. — Fooloso4
If M is the mental image then M is not the image of M. — Fooloso4
How is the correction between the mental image and the object to be made? In the example of the Eiffel Tower I need to become aware that the mental image I have is the image of something else. Pointing to the object my mental image is an image of I might say: "See, this is the Eiffel Tower and my mental image looks just like it". — Fooloso4
Comparing my mental image to what I mistakenly think is the Eiffel Tower does not correct the problem. — Fooloso4
The point of the example of the Eiffel Tower is not that the names are mixed up... — Fooloso4
In the example of the Eiffel Tower there is, but at PI 389 there is no confusion as to what object is being referred to, and so, no need to name it. — Fooloso4
Therefore, the Eiffel Tower example does not show that sentence 3 is false, because sentence 3 does not name the object.
— Luke
It is not an intrinsic feature of my mental image of the Eiffel Tower that it is the image of "this" (the Eiffel Tower) and of nothing else. — Fooloso4
The point of the example of the Eiffel Tower is not that the names are mixed up, but that the mental image I have is actually an image of something else, the Arc de Triomphe. — Fooloso4
"This" refers to some object. At PI 389 there is only one object. There is no need to name it. — Fooloso4
Therefore, the objects are not correctly identified by comparing one's mental image to the object.
— Luke
A misnomer can be corrected by linking the correct name to the object. If I am told that this object I am standing in front of is the Eiffel Tower then I can see that my mental image was not what I thought it was. What I was picturing was not the Eiffel Tower. — Fooloso4
But it is an intrinsic feature of a mental image that it is the image of this and of nothing else.
Your example shows why this is not true. — Fooloso4
When they stand before the Eiffel Tower their mental image is of the Eiffel Tower,
— Luke
Do you mean that when they see the Eiffel Tower they are actually seeing a mental image of the Eiffel Tower? — Fooloso4
And they would be mistaken. It is not the Eiffel Tower. The mistake can be corrected when the two objects are correctly identified. — Fooloso4
The point of the example is that the mistake is corrected when the objects are in front of them. Before seeing them the mental image of the Eiffel Tower is a stone arch. — Fooloso4
The mental object and mental image are the same thing.
But you said that the mental image is not of the object?
— Luke
It is not of the object if:
If I mistakenly think that my mental image is of the Eiffel Tower
— Luke — Fooloso4
The mental image is not of the object.... — Fooloso4
They can make the comparison. We can't. If they have this mental image of what they think is an image of the Eiffel Tower and then visit the Eiffel Tower and Arc de Triomphe they might realize their mistake. — Fooloso4
If I mistakenly think that my mental image is of the Eiffel Tower, what does that have to do with a superlikeness?
— Luke
It shows that the mental image need not be more like the object than a physical picture. — Fooloso4
The mental image is not of the object before your mind. The mental object is the object before your mind. The mental object is an image of the same object that the picture is. The claim is that the mental image is more like this object than the physical picture is. — Fooloso4
My (or the interlocutor's) inference is erroneous because the mental image is not a representation of the object.
— Luke
Of course it is! Both the mental image and the physical image are images of the same object. — Fooloso4
The interlocutor is claiming that the mental image is more like that object than the physical image is. — Fooloso4
The same can be said of a mental picture. I might think my mental image is of the Eiffel Tower when it id actually a mental image of the Arc de Triomphe. — Fooloso4
This is why the comparison between a mental image and a physical image is misguided. — Fooloso4
In the case of 2 the image "I make" may be seen by others as a picture of something else. In the case of 3 no such ambiguity arises because no one else can see the image. If they could, the same ambiguity might arise. The mental image is not a superlikeness. — Fooloso4
If I draw a picture or take a photograph of X, it is not a picture of anything else. Whether someone thinks it is a picture of something else makes no difference. It is a picture of X. — Fooloso4
a) The picture I draw of X it is an image of X. I know because I drew it. — Fooloso4
A second person in involved in 2 but no one else can be involved in my mental image. If 2 and 3 are to be compared on an equal bases then a second person should not enter into the comparison. — Fooloso4
For however similar I make the picture to what it is supposed to represent, it may still be the picture of something else. — PI 389, sentence 2
But it is an intrinsic feature of a mental image that it is the image of this and of nothing else. — PI 389, sentence 3
Why do you say W rejects it?
— Luke
a) The picture I draw of X it is an image of X. I know because I drew it.
b) My mental image of X is an image of X.
What is the difference between a and b with regard to being an image of X? — Fooloso4
In the first case, the picture I draw of X may look to you like something else — Fooloso4
in the second, it cannot look to you like something else because you cannot see it. — Fooloso4
You stated earlier:
The point of PI 389 is to reject claims 1 -3
— Fooloso4 — Luke
As I have said, the three claims are part of the same argument. You can separate them as part of an analysis but you need to put them back together.
The claim at three is that it is an image of this. "This" is the object it is an image of. We cannot ignore the question of resemblance. — Fooloso4
If I remember correctly, this discussion began with PI 389 and you have returned to it more than once. PI 389 is about the likeness of mental image vs a picture to an object. — Fooloso4
When you say a mental image of X, X is the object that a mental image is an image of. When you say a mental image of ... there is something that it is an image of. — Fooloso4
The point of PI 389 is to reject claims 1 -3 — Fooloso4
But it is an intrinsic feature of a mental image that it is the image of this and of nothing else. — PI 389, sentence 3
When you gave the example of mistaking a hat for a sandwich both a hat and a sandwich are objects. — Fooloso4
Your argument was that the meaning of "picture" is different between a mental picture and a physical picture
— Luke
Have I made that argument? — Fooloso4
Could you please explain the two different uses of the term 'picture'?
— Luke
One is physical and can be made public, the other cannot. — Fooloso4
My point was that the "picture" aspect of a mental picture is no different to the "picture" aspect of a physical picture, because whatever is the content of the mental image is equivalent to the content of the "picture before the mind".
— Luke
I can't follow this argument. — Fooloso4
One remains relatively stable and unchanging the other may not. — Fooloso4
I don't see what this has to do with his mental image. How do we verify that? — Luke
You draw or describe your mental image and what you draw or describe looks like or sounds like a sandwich. Based on this representation of your mental image they will tell you that you are mistaken, it is not a hat its a sandwich. You might protest and say "I know it's a hat because its my mental image of a hat". If you are then asked to get a hat and put it on will you put a sandwich on your head? — Fooloso4
I don’t believe he uses the word “picture” (unqualified) to refer to a mental image.
— Luke
Do you mean he qualifies the mental picture by saying it is a mental picture?
— Fooloso4
Yes.
— Luke
Isn't that because a mental picture is not a physical picture? — Fooloso4
I don’t understand what it means for someone to mistake their mental image of a hat for a sandwich
— Luke
Oliver Sacks' The Man Who Mistook His Wife for a Hat might be of interest. — Fooloso4
I don’t see how we could verify whether a mistake had been made.
— Luke
If this person tried to eat a hat and we asked him why, we would know a mistake had been made. — Fooloso4
I don’t believe he uses the word “picture” (unqualified) to refer to a mental image.
— Luke
Do you mean he qualifies the mental picture by saying it is a mental picture? — Fooloso4
If you mistake your hat for a sandwich, then your mental image of a hat is a picture of a sandwich?
— Luke
I don't know. I would say that that this raises a problem. Wouldn't we say that if someone's mental image of a hat was a sandwich she would be mistaken? — Fooloso4
It might change in various ways. Some features may become more prominent. Something left out or added. I think it might help to think of this in terms of memory. Our memory of things change. — Fooloso4
If I say: "I was this picture" you might think I mean movie or photo or painting but would it cross your mind that I meant a mental image? — Fooloso4
If the mental image is of Y instead of X, then the picture before one's mind must be of Y.
— Luke
If I mistake X for Y my mental image of X is a picture of Y. — Fooloso4
Yes, but even though it changes, my mental picture of Zeus is still my mental picture of Zeus. — Fooloso4
No. The word is used in various ways. If you ask me to show you the picture in one case I can but in other I can't. If I remember correctly this was why you were reluctant to call the mental picture a picture. — Fooloso4
The sketch or description is not the mental picture. It is a representation of it.
— Fooloso4
It is neither a picture of a mental picture nor a description of a mental description.
— Luke
Have you changed your mind? In the prior post you asked:
Can these mental pictures not be made public (e.g. via a sketch or description)?
— Luke
Was your answer no they cannot be made public? — Fooloso4
They are the same only is so far as they are pictures of the same thing. My mental picture of you may be very different than a photo or portrait of you. If I see that picture I might say: "You are much more handsome than I pictured". — Fooloso4
The mental picture may or may not stay relatively stable, but there is nothing to compare it to in order to determine that. One's memory of it may be more or less reliable. — Fooloso4
The sketch or description is not the mental picture. It is a representation of it. — Fooloso4
The distinction made is between an image in the mind and a physical image. But a mental image and a physical image are are both pictures. — Fooloso4
I note that Wittgenstein is using these examples to undermine the (then) common view that such mental images are necessary to the meaning of a word.
— Luke
Was that in dispute in our discussion? — Fooloso4
PI 6. a picture of the object comes before the child’s mind when it hears the word.
PI 37. hearing a name calls before our mind the picture of what is named
PI 73. I get an idea of the shape of a leaf, a picture of it in my mind — Fooloso4
Could you please explain the two different uses of the term 'picture'?
— Luke
One is physical and can be made public, the other cannot. One remains relatively stable and unchanging the other may not. We can use one an item of comparison, the other only by the one whose mental image it is. — Fooloso4
A final analogy to illuminate the misguided supposition of predicates of perceptual qualities (e.g. ‘red’) having a double meaning (cf. §273). A theatrical or cinema director may sketch on paper roughly (etwa) how he imagines a scene. On the model of §273 it might seem that such a picture has two distinct representative functions. For others it represents the scene they are to create as the person envisages it. It tells them how he imagines the scene. But for him it represents his mental image of the scene which only he knows (since only he has it). Indeed, his visual impression of the picture he has painted tells him what he has imagined in a way in which, for others, it cannot. For in his case, his visual impression of what he has painted must surely coincide with the mental image he had when he imagined the scene.
This is a muddle. To paint what I imagine is not to copy a picture that is already ‘painted’ in my imagination (although I can, of course, imagine painting something, and then go on to paint what I imagined painting). The director’s sketch does indeed represent how he imagines the scene; i.e. to the question ‘How do you think it should look?’ he might produce the sketch and say ‘Like that’. This is what is called ‘representing what I imagined it should look like’. But it is erroneous to think that the picture represents to him what he imagined in any different sense, for it does not represent it in virtue of resembling his mental image, any more than the verbal expression of what he thought resembles his thought. It informs others how he imagined things should look, but it does not inform him! What makes the picture a good representation of what he imagined? Not its likeness to his mental image, but rather his avowed acknowledgement that that was what he had in mind. But that acknowledgement does not rest on an ‘inner glance’ at his mental image. ‘The image is not a picture, nor is the visual impression one. Neither “image” nor “impression” is the concept of a picture, although in both cases there is a tie‐up with a picture, and a different one in either case’ (Z §638). Hence it is a mistake to think that when I paint a picture to show you how I imagine a scene, the picture is a piece of information or a representation for me. It is an articulation or expression of how I imagine the scene, not an ‘outer’ picture of an ‘inner’ picture. Moreover, an impression of a picture is not a representation of a picture (cf. PI §366).
Similarly, although hearing the word ‘red’ may call forth a mental image of red (or of a field of poppies or a sunset), the answer to the question ‘What do you mean by “red”?’ is given by pointing to a sample. And if I ask myself ‘What do I mean by “red”?’, the answer is no different. — PMS Hacker, Wittgenstein: Meaning and Mind (Volume 3 of an Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations), Part 2: Exegesis, Section 243-427
The don't access my mental image. Their brain creates their own mental image in response to perceiving my picture. — wonderer1
How does your mental image inform others of anything?
— Luke
By stimulating the other to develop their own mental image which is approximate to mine. — wonderer1
Because he contrasts the mental picture to the picture. — Fooloso4
Wittgenstein poses the question: What is the content of the experience of imagining? And answer it:
The answer is a picture, or a description.
He is not asking about how that picture can be represented or communicated. — Fooloso4
How can I tell? I can't compare them unless two conditions are met: 1) I could call up the mental picture and 2) that it will remain unchanged each time I call it to mind. I do not think those conditions can be met. — Fooloso4
This:
it informs others, as pictures or words do
— Luke
and this:
has a double function: it informs others, as pictures or words do
— PI 280
are not the same. He does not reject the former but does reject the latter. It informs those who build the set. — Fooloso4
Why not approximately inform others? — wonderer1
I guess I wouldn't expect a painting to be anything other than an approximation of the painter's mental image. — wonderer1
I would expect that in painting the picture he'd likely recognize inaccuracies to the way the painting represents the mental image and recognize that the painting is not the mental image. — wonderer1
The picture or description is what is imagined. — Fooloso4
The former, but to answer the question I could draw a picture or describe that content. — Fooloso4
Suppose I draw a picture of or describe a picture I saw at an art show. Is that picture or description of what I saw the same as what I saw, that is, the picture? My picture might embellish or omit certain things. It is still a picture of this, that is, the picture I saw at an art show, but the pictures will not be the same. — Fooloso4
What PI 280 rejects is that:
His private impression of the picture tells him what he imagined ... — Fooloso4
This picture [that he painted in order to show how he imagined the stage set] has a double function: it informs others, as pictures or words do —– but for the informant it is in addition a representation (or piece of information?) of another kind: for him it is the picture of his image, as it can’t be for anyone else. His private impression of the picture tells him what he imagined, in a sense in which the picture can’t do this for others. — PI 280
I don't see any inconsistency. — Fooloso4
The content of the experience of imagining is what is imagined. The experience itself is a picture or description that occurs in the mind. In order to answer the question of what that is I can draw a picture or describe the content. — Fooloso4
PPF 10. What is the content of the experience of imagining? The answer is a picture, or a description.
If you are saying that the mental image or imagined picture might change, then in what sense is it a "picture"?
— Luke
This shows how a picture hanging on the wall differs from a mental picture. — Fooloso4
We could think of it instead as a series of different (inner) pictures.
— Luke
How do you reconcile this with PI 389? — Fooloso4
They are at t1 and t2 my inner picture of X. My inner picture of X has changed. It should be noted that I may not even be aware that it has changed. — Fooloso4
No. Why would I need a private impression of the picture I imagined to tell me what I imagined? — Fooloso4
W's rejection here is consistent with the assertion that the content of a public picture and the content of a private picture are, or can be, the same.
— Luke
They might be but they need not be the same. — Fooloso4
No. I reject it because things are not always as we imagine them to be. — Fooloso4
Do you agree that the content of the picture/description is the same regardless of whether it is a public object or whether it is privately imagined?
— Luke
Not necessarily. As I imagine something can change. — Fooloso4
PPF 10. What is the content of the experience of imagining? The answer is a picture, or a description.
The content of the experience of imagining is what is imagined. The experience itself is a picture or description that occurs in the mind. In order to answer the question of what that is I can draw a picture or describe the content. — Fooloso4
Could you please explain the two different uses of the term 'picture'?
— Luke
One is physical and can be made public, the other cannot. One remains relatively stable and unchanging the other may not. We can use one an item of comparison, the other only by the one whose mental image it is. — Fooloso4
And I don't see Wittgenstein using the word as a verb here, either, such as "picture this...".
— Luke
The first few examples of many:
2. Let us imagine a language
4. Imagine a script in which letters were used for sounds,
6. We could imagine that the language of §2 was the whole language of A and B — Fooloso4
As I noted earlier, this begets a picture of a picture or a description of a description. This is the view that W appears to reject at PI 280.
— Luke
What he rejects is that:
His private impression of the picture tells him what he imagined — Fooloso4
On my view, as stated in my previous post, what Wittgenstein means by this "content" is a public picture or public description of what is privately imagined.
— Luke
PPF 10. What is the content of the experience of imagining? The answer is a picture, or a description.
The content of the experience of imagining is what is imagined. The experience itself is a picture or description that occurs in the mind. In order to answer the question of what that is I can draw a picture or describe the content. — Fooloso4
The mental image is not a picture hanging on the wall of my mind. — Fooloso4
The experience itself is a picture or description that occurs in the mind. — Fooloso4
The two uses of the term 'picture' belong to different categories. — Fooloso4
I take PI 280 to be denying that the picture has a double function. The picture he paints to show how he imagines the stage set does not also inform him. It does not tell him what he imagined. — Fooloso4
The experience itself is a picture or description that occurs in the mind. In order to answer the question of what that is I can draw a picture or describe the content. — Fooloso4
I believe that Wittgenstein makes a case for sentence 2 of PI 389 - "For however similar I make the picture to what it is supposed to represent, it may still be the picture of something else" - in sections PI 139-141. — Luke
The question is whether a description can be the content of the experience of imagining. Imagining how someone might come to regard a mental image as a superlikeness is to give a description of the steps taken. Isn't that what we are doing when we are figuring out how to respond to each other, imagining how this or that description might be persuasive? Imagining how this or that description might get the other person to see it differently? — Fooloso4
133. The concept of an ‘inner picture’ is misleading, since the model for this concept is the ‘outer picture’; and yet the uses of these concept-words are no more like one another than the uses of “numeral” and “number”. (Indeed, someone who was inclined to call numbers ‘ideal numerals’ could generate a similar confusion by doing so.) — PI 133
The core idea of Wittgenstein’s formalism from 1929 (if not 1918) through 1944 is that mathematics is essentially syntactical, devoid of reference and semantics. The most obvious aspect of this view, which has been noted by numerous commentators who do not refer to Wittgenstein as a ‘formalist’ (Kielkopf 1970: 360–38; Klenk 1976: 5, 8, 9; Fogelin 1968: 267; Frascolla 1994: 40; Marion 1998: 13–14), is that, contra Platonism, the signs and propositions of a mathematical calculus do not refer to anything. As Wittgenstein says at (WVC 34, note 1), “[n]umbers are not represented by proxies; numbers are there”. This means not only that numbers are there in the use, it means that the numerals are the numbers, for “[a]rithmetic doesn’t talk about numbers, it works with numbers” (PR §109). — SEP article on Wittgenstein’s Philosophy of Mathematics
280. Someone paints a picture in order to show, for example, how he imagines a stage set. And now I say: “This picture has a double function: it informs others, as pictures or words do —– but for the informant it is in addition a representation (or piece of information?) of another kind: for him it is the picture of his image, as it can’t be for anyone else. His private impression of the picture tells him what he imagined, in a sense in which the picture can’t do this for others.” — And what right have I to speak in this second case of a representation or piece of information — if these words were correctly used in the first case? — PI 280
In response to the question of the mental content I might say: "I had a picture in my mind of a man on a horse". This description can be put in the form of a public or physical picture, but a mental picture and a physical picture of that mental picture are two different things. — Fooloso4
perhaps another way of saying this could be that it is an image of this.
— Luke
The same question: an image of what? What is "this"? — Fooloso4
At PI 10 he says:
What is the content of the experience of imagining? The answer is a picture, or a description. — Fooloso4
367. A mental image is the image which is described when someone describes what he imagines. — PI 367
If we cannot appeal to a mental image of a color then, with regard to color, we cannot determine that the mental image of a red object is more like the object than a physical picture of the red object. — Fooloso4
The term picture is used in different ways. At PI 389 he is referring to a physical picture, something that others can see. But we can also picture things to ourselves as in PI 10. These pictures are mental images. — Fooloso4
He says that 1) a mental image must be more like its object than any picture. This is because 2) a picture may be of something other than what it is supposed to represent. But 3) a mental image can only be an image of this. "This" does not mean an image of itself, an image of an image. It is an image of the object that he claims a picture may fail to represent. — Fooloso4
You can say that the mental image of a horse is of a horse
— Luke
The mental image of a horse is not a horse, it is an image of a horse. — Fooloso4
A mental image need not represent anything or be of anything, but this does not mean it represents itself or is of itself. It presents itself, it does not re-present itself. — Fooloso4
When the interlocutor says at the start of 2: "For ..." the claim is that because a picture may be a picture of something else, the mental image is more like its object than any picture. This is not the same as simply saying a picture may be a picture of something else. Something specific is supposed to follow from the interlocutors claim that need not follow from the observation that a picture may be a picture of something other than what it is supposed to represent. — Fooloso4
The point is that one's mental image is not part of the language game; only a description of one's mental image is.
— Luke
And what follows from this? — Fooloso4
I assume you mean mental image
— Luke
No, I mean a picture, a painting or photograph. — Fooloso4
3. A mental image cannot be of anything else (but itself).
— Luke
The interlocutor's claim is not a mental image is a mental image of a mental image. It is an image of the object it is an image of. — Fooloso4